Characterizing property of mathematical constructions
The typical diagram of the definition of a universal morphism.
Inmathematics, more specifically incategory theory, auniversal property is a property that characterizesup to anisomorphism the result of some constructions. Thus, universal properties can be used for defining some objects independently from the method chosen for constructing them. For example, the definitions of theintegers from thenatural numbers, of therational numbers from the integers, of thereal numbers from the rational numbers, and ofpolynomial rings from thefield of their coefficients can all be done in terms of universal properties. In particular, the concept of universal property allows a simple proof that allconstructions of real numbers are equivalent: it suffices to prove that they satisfy the same universal property.
Universal properties occur almost everywhere in mathematics, and the use of the concept allows the use of general properties of universal properties for easily proving some properties that would need boring verifications otherwise. For example, given acommutative ringR, thefield of fractions of thequotient ring ofR by aprime idealp can be identified with theresidue field of thelocalization ofR atp; that is (all these constructions can be defined by universal properties).
Before giving a formal definition of universal properties, we offer some motivation for studying such constructions.
The concrete details of a given construction may be messy, but if the construction satisfies a universal property, one can forget all those details: all there is to know about the construction is already contained in the universal property. Proofs often become short and elegant if the universal property is used rather than the concrete details. For example, thetensor algebra of avector space is slightly complicated to construct, but much easier to deal with by its universal property.
Universal properties define objects uniquely up to a uniqueisomorphism.[1] Therefore, one strategy to prove that two objects are isomorphic is to show that they satisfy the same universal property.
Universal constructions are functorial in nature: if one can carry out the construction for every object in a categoryC then one obtains afunctor onC. Furthermore, this functor is aright or left adjoint to the functorU used in the definition of the universal property.[2]
Universal properties occur everywhere in mathematics. By understanding their abstract properties, one obtains information about all these constructions and can avoid repeating the same analysis for each individual instance.
To understand the definition of a universal construction, it is important to look at examples. Universal constructions were not defined out of thin air, but were rather defined after mathematicians began noticing a pattern in many mathematical constructions (see Examples below). Hence, the definition may not make sense to one at first, but will become clear when one reconciles it with concrete examples.
Let be a functor between categories and. In what follows, let be an object of, and be objects of, and be a morphism in.
Then, the functor maps, and in to, and in.
Auniversal morphism from to is a unique pair in which has the following property, commonly referred to as auniversal property:
For any morphism of the form in, there exists aunique morphism in such that the following diagramcommutes:
The typical diagram of the definition of a universal morphism.
We candualize this categorical concept. Auniversal morphism from to is a unique pair that satisfies the following universal property:
For any morphism of the form in, there exists aunique morphism in such that the following diagram commutes:
The most important arrow here is which establishes the universal property.
Note that in each definition, the arrows are reversed. Both definitions are necessary to describe universal constructions which appear in mathematics; but they also arise due to the inherent duality present in category theory.In either case, we say that the pair which behaves as above satisfies a universal property.
Universal morphisms can be described more concisely as initial and terminal objects in acomma category (i.e. one where morphisms are seen as objects in their own right).
Let be a functor and an object of. Then recall that the comma category is the category where
Objects are pairs of the form, where is an object in
A morphism from to is given by a morphism in such that the diagram commutes:
A morphism in the comma category is given by the morphism which also makes the diagram commute.
Now suppose that the object in is initial. Thenfor every object, there exists a unique morphism such that the following diagram commutes.
This demonstrates the connection between a universal diagram being an initial object in a comma category.
Note that the equality here simply means the diagrams are the same. Also note that the diagram on the right side of the equality is the exact same as the one offered in defining auniversal morphism from to. Therefore, we see that a universal morphism from to is equivalent to an initial object in the comma category.
Conversely, recall that the comma category is the category where
Objects are pairs of the form where is an object in
A morphism from to is given by a morphism in such that the diagram commutes:
This simply demonstrates the definition of a morphism in a comma category.
Suppose is a terminal object in. Then for every object, there exists a unique morphism such that the following diagrams commute.
This shows that a terminal object in a specific comma category corresponds to a universal morphism.
The diagram on the right side of the equality is the same diagram pictured when defining auniversal morphism from to. Hence, a universal morphism from to corresponds with a terminal object in the comma category.
Below are a few examples, to highlight the general idea. The reader can construct numerous other examples by consulting the articles mentioned in the introduction.
be theforgetful functor which assigns to each algebra its underlying vector space.
Given anyvector space over we can construct thetensor algebra. The tensor algebra is characterized by the fact:
“Any linear map from to an algebra can be uniquely extended to analgebra homomorphism from to.”
This statement is an initial property of the tensor algebra since it expresses the fact that the pair, where is the inclusion map, is a universal morphism from the vector space to the functor.
Since this construction works for any vector space, we conclude that is a functor from-Vect to-Alg. This means that isleft adjoint to the forgetful functor (see the section below onrelation to adjoint functors).
Let and be objects of a category with finite products. The product of and is an object × together with two morphisms
:
:
such that for any other object of and morphisms and there exists a unique morphism such that and.
To understand this characterization as a universal property, take the category to be theproduct category and define thediagonal functor
by and. Then is a universal morphism from to the object of: if is any morphism from to, then it must equala morphism fromto followed by. As a commutative diagram:
Commutative diagram showing how products have a universal property.
For the example of the Cartesian product inSet, the morphism comprises the two projections and. Given any set and functions the unique map such that the required diagram commutes is given by.[3]
is the functor that maps each object in to the constant functor (i.e. for each in and for each in) and each morphism in to the natural transformation in defined as, for every object of, the componentat. In other words, the natural transformation is the one defined by having constant component for every object of.
Given a functor (thought of as an object in), thelimit of, if it exists, is nothing but a universal morphism from to. Dually, thecolimit of is a universal morphism from to.
Defining a quantity does not guarantee its existence. Given a functor and an object of, there may or may not exist a universal morphism from to. If, however, a universal morphism does exist, then it is essentially unique. Specifically, it is uniqueup to auniqueisomorphism: if is another pair, then there exists a unique isomorphism such that.This is easily seen by substituting in the definition of a universal morphism.
It is the pair which is essentially unique in this fashion. The object itself is only unique up to isomorphism. Indeed, if is a universal morphism and is any isomorphism then the pair, where is also a universal morphism.
The definition of a universal morphism can be rephrased in a variety of ways. Let be a functor and let be an object of. Then the following statements are equivalent:
Suppose is a universal morphism from to and is a universal morphism from to. By the universal property of universal morphisms, given any morphism there exists a unique morphism such that the following diagram commutes:
Universal morphisms can behave like a natural transformation between functors under suitable conditions.
Ifevery object of admits a universal morphism to, then the assignment and defines a functor. The maps then define anatural transformation from (the identity functor on) to. The functors are then a pair ofadjoint functors, with left-adjoint to and right-adjoint to.
Similar statements apply to the dual situation of terminal morphisms from. If such morphisms exist for every in one obtains a functor which is right-adjoint to (so is left-adjoint to).
Indeed, all pairs of adjoint functors arise from universal constructions in this manner. Let and be a pair of adjoint functors with unit and co-unit (see the article onadjoint functors for the definitions). Then we have a universal morphism for each object in and:
For each object in, is a universal morphism from to. That is, for all there exists a unique for which the following diagrams commute.
For each object in, is a universal morphism from to. That is, for all there exists a unique for which the following diagrams commute.
The unit and counit of an adjunction, which are natural transformations between functors, are an important example of universal morphisms.
Universal constructions are more general than adjoint functor pairs: a universal construction is like an optimization problem; it gives rise to an adjoint pair if and only if this problem has a solution for every object of (equivalently, every object of).
Universal properties of various topological constructions were presented byPierre Samuel in 1948. They were later used extensively byBourbaki. The closely related concept of adjoint functors was introduced independently byDaniel Kan in 1958.
^See for example, Polcino & Sehgal (2002), p. 133. exercise 1, about the universal property ofgroup rings.
^Fong, Brendan; Spivak, David I. (2018-10-12). "Seven Sketches in Compositionality: An Invitation to Applied Category Theory".arXiv:1803.05316 [math.CT].
Borceux, F.Handbook of Categorical Algebra: vol 1 Basic category theory (1994) Cambridge University Press, (Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications)ISBN0-521-44178-1