Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Jump to content
WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
Search

Theory (mathematical logic)

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected fromTheory (logic))
Set of sentences in a formal language
"Logical theory" redirects here. For John Dewey's "Studies in Logical Theory", seeJohn Dewey.

Inmathematical logic, atheory (also called aformal theory) is a set ofsentences in aformal language. In most scenarios adeductive system is first understood from context, giving rise to aformal system that combines the language with deduction rules. An elementϕT{\displaystyle \phi \in T} of adeductively closed theoryT{\displaystyle T} is then called atheorem of the theory. In many deductive systems there is usually a subsetΣT{\displaystyle \Sigma \subseteq T} that is called "the set ofaxioms" of the theoryT{\displaystyle T}, in which case the deductive system is also called an "axiomatic system". By definition, every axiom is automatically a theorem. Afirst-order theory is a set offirst-order sentences (theorems)recursively obtained by theinference rules of the system applied to the set of axioms.

General theories (as expressed in formal language)

[edit]

When defining theories for foundational purposes, additional care must be taken, as normal set-theoretic language may not be appropriate.

The construction of a theory begins by specifying a definite non-emptyconceptual classE{\displaystyle {\mathcal {E}}}, the elements of which are calledstatements. These initial statements are often called theprimitive elements orelementary statements of the theory—to distinguish them from other statements that may be derived from them.

A theoryT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} is a conceptual class consisting of certain of these elementary statements. The elementary statements that belong toT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} are called theelementary theorems ofT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} and are said to betrue. In this way, a theory can be seen as a way of designating a subset ofE{\displaystyle {\mathcal {E}}} that only contain statements that are true.

This general way of designating a theory stipulates that the truth of any of its elementary statements is not known without reference toT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}}. Thus the same elementary statement may be true with respect to one theory but false with respect to another. This is reminiscent of the case in ordinary language where statements such as "He is an honest person" cannot be judged true or false without interpreting who "he" is, and, for that matter, what an "honest person" is under this theory.[1]

Subtheories and extensions

[edit]
See also:Conservative extension

A theoryS{\displaystyle {\mathcal {S}}} is asubtheory of a theoryT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} ifS{\displaystyle {\mathcal {S}}} is a subset ofT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}}. IfT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} is a subset ofS{\displaystyle {\mathcal {S}}} thenS{\displaystyle {\mathcal {S}}} is called anextension or asupertheory ofT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}}

Deductive theories

[edit]

A theory is said to be adeductive theory ifT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} is aninductive class, which is to say that its content is based on someformal deductive system and that some of its elementary statements are taken asaxioms. In a deductive theory, any sentence that is alogical consequence of one or more of the axioms is also a sentence of that theory.[1] More formally, if{\displaystyle \vdash } is a Tarski-styleconsequence relation, thenT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} is closed under{\displaystyle \vdash } (and so each of its theorems is a logical consequence of its axioms) if and only if, for all sentencesϕ{\displaystyle \phi } in the language of the theoryT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}}, ifTϕ{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}\vdash \phi }, thenϕT{\displaystyle \phi \in {\mathcal {T}}}; or, equivalently, ifT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}'} is a finite subset ofT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} (possibly the set of axioms ofT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} in the case of finitely axiomatizable theories) andTϕ{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}'\vdash \phi }, thenϕT{\displaystyle \phi \in {\mathcal {T}}'}, and thereforeϕT{\displaystyle \phi \in {\mathcal {T}}}.

Consistency and completeness

[edit]
Main articles:Consistency andCompleteness (logic)

Asyntactically consistent theory is a theory from which not every sentence in the underlying language can be proven (with respect to somedeductive system, which is usually clear from context). In a deductive system (such as first-order logic) that satisfies theprinciple of explosion, this is equivalent to requiring that there is no sentence φ such that both φ and its negation can be proven from the theory.

Asatisfiable theory is a theory that has amodel. This means there is a structureM thatsatisfies every sentence in the theory. Any satisfiable theory is syntactically consistent, because the structure satisfying the theory will satisfy exactly one of φ and the negation of φ, for each sentence φ.

Aconsistent theory is sometimes defined to be a syntactically consistent theory, and sometimes defined to be a satisfiable theory. Forfirst-order logic, the most important case, it follows from thecompleteness theorem that the two meanings coincide.[2] In other logics, such assecond-order logic, there are syntactically consistent theories that are not satisfiable, such asω-inconsistent theories.

Acomplete consistent theory (or just acomplete theory) is aconsistent theoryT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} such that for every sentence φ in its language, either φ is provable fromT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} orT{\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}}{\displaystyle \cup } {φ} is inconsistent. For theories closed under logical consequence, this means that for every sentence φ, either φ or its negation is contained in the theory.[3] Anincomplete theory is a consistent theory that is not complete.

(see alsoω-consistent theory for a stronger notion of consistency.)

Interpretation of a theory

[edit]
Main article:Interpretation (logic)

Aninterpretation of a theory is the relationship between a theory and some subject matter when there is amany-to-one correspondence between certain elementary statements of the theory, and certain statements related to the subject matter. If every elementary statement in the theory has a correspondent it is called afull interpretation, otherwise it is called apartial interpretation.[4]

Theories associated with a structure

[edit]

Eachstructure has several associated theories. Thecomplete theory of a structureA is the set of allfirst-ordersentences over thesignature ofA that are satisfied byA. It is denoted by Th(A). More generally, thetheory ofK, a class of σ-structures, is the set of all first-orderσ-sentences that are satisfied by all structures inK, and is denoted by Th(K). Clearly Th(A) = Th({A}). These notions can also be defined with respect to other logics.

For each σ-structureA, there are several associated theories in a larger signature σ' that extends σ by adding one new constant symbol for each element of the domain ofA. (If the new constant symbols are identified with the elements ofA that they represent, σ' can be taken to be σ{\displaystyle \cup } A.) The cardinality of σ' is thus the larger of the cardinality of σ and the cardinality ofA.[further explanation needed]

Thediagram ofA consists of all atomic or negated atomic σ'-sentences that are satisfied byA and is denoted by diagA. Thepositive diagram ofA is the set of all atomic σ'-sentences thatA satisfies. It is denoted by diag+A. Theelementary diagram ofA is the set eldiagA ofall first-order σ'-sentences that are satisfied byA or, equivalently, the complete (first-order) theory of the naturalexpansion ofA to the signature σ'.

First-order theories

[edit]
Further information:List of first-order theories

A first-order theoryQS{\displaystyle {\mathcal {QS}}} is a set of sentences in a first-orderformal languageQ{\displaystyle {\mathcal {Q}}}.

Derivation in a first-order theory

[edit]
Main article:First-order logic § Deductive systems

There are many formal derivation ("proof") systems for first-order logic. These includeHilbert-style deductive systems,natural deduction, thesequent calculus, thetableaux method andresolution.

Syntactic consequence in a first-order theory

[edit]
Main article:First-order logic § Validity, satisfiability, and logical consequence

AformulaA is asyntactic consequence of a first-order theoryQS{\displaystyle {\mathcal {QS}}} if there is aderivation ofA using only formulas inQS{\displaystyle {\mathcal {QS}}} as non-logical axioms. Such a formulaA is also called a theorem ofQS{\displaystyle {\mathcal {QS}}}. The notation "QSA{\displaystyle {\mathcal {QS}}\vdash A}" indicatesA is a theorem ofQS{\displaystyle {\mathcal {QS}}}.

Interpretation of a first-order theory

[edit]
Main article:Structure (mathematical logic)

Aninterpretation of a first-order theory provides a semantics for the formulas of the theory. An interpretation is said to satisfy a formula if the formula is true according to the interpretation. Amodel of a first-order theoryQS{\displaystyle {\mathcal {QS}}} is an interpretation in which every formula ofQS{\displaystyle {\mathcal {QS}}} is satisfied.

First-order theories with identity

[edit]
Main article:First-order logic § Equality and its axioms

A first-order theoryQS{\displaystyle {\mathcal {QS}}} is a first-order theory with identity ifQS{\displaystyle {\mathcal {QS}}} includes the identity relation symbol "=" and the reflexivity and substitution axiom schemes for this symbol.

Topics related to first-order theories

[edit]

Examples

[edit]

One way to specify a theory is to define a set ofaxioms in a particular language. The theory can be taken to include just those axioms, or their logical or provable consequences, as desired. Theories obtained this way includeZFC andPeano arithmetic.

A second way to specify a theory is to begin with astructure, and let the theory be the set of sentences that are satisfied by the structure. This is a method for producing complete theories through the semantic route, with examples including the set of true sentences under the structure (N, +, ×, 0, 1, =), whereN is the set of natural numbers, and the set of true sentences under the structure (R, +, ×, 0, 1, =), whereR is the set of real numbers. The first of these, called the theory oftrue arithmetic, cannot be written as the set of logical consequences of anyenumerable set of axioms.The theory of (R, +, ×, 0, 1, =) was shown by Tarski to bedecidable; it is the theory ofreal closed fields (seeDecidability of first-order theories of the real numbers for more).

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^abHaskell Curry,Foundations of Mathematical Logic, 2010.
  2. ^Weiss, William; D'Mello, Cherie (2015)."Fundamentals of Model Theory"(PDF).University of Toronto — Department of Mathematics.
  3. ^"Completeness (in logic) - Encyclopedia of Mathematics".www.encyclopediaofmath.org. Retrieved2019-11-01.
  4. ^Haskell Curry (1963).Foundations of Mathematical Logic. Mcgraw Hill. Here: p.48

Further reading

[edit]
General
Theorems (list)
 and paradoxes
Logics
Traditional
Propositional
Predicate
Set theory
Types ofsets
Maps and cardinality
Set theories
Formal systems (list),
language and syntax
Example axiomatic
systems
 (list)
Proof theory
Model theory
Computability theory
Related
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Theory_(mathematical_logic)&oldid=1288929407"
Categories:
Hidden categories:

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp