![]() | This article has multiple issues. Please helpimprove it or discuss these issues on thetalk page.(Learn how and when to remove these messages) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
|
Ingame theory, thestag hunt, sometimes referred to as theassurance game,trust dilemma orcommon interest game, describes a conflict between safety and social cooperation. The stag hunt problem originated with philosopherJean-Jacques Rousseau in hisDiscourse on Inequality.
In the most common account of this dilemma, which is quite different from Rousseau's, twohunters must decide separately, and without the other knowing, whether to hunt astag or ahare. However, both hunters know the only way to successfully hunt a stag is with the other's help. One hunter can catch a hare alone with less effort and less time, but it is worth far less than a stag and has much less meat. But both hunters would be better off if both choose the more ambitious and more rewarding goal of getting the stag, giving up some autonomy in exchange for the other hunter's cooperation and added might. This situation is often seen as a useful analogy for many kinds of social cooperation, such as international agreements on climate change.[1]
The stag hunt differs from theprisoner's dilemma in that there are two pure-strategyNash equilibria:[2] one where both players cooperate, and one where both players defect.[a] In the prisoner's dilemma, despite the fact that both players cooperating isPareto efficient, the only pure Nash equilibrium is when both players choose to defect.
An example of thepayoff matrix for the stag hunt is pictured in Figure 2.
|
|
Formally, a stag hunt is a game with twopure strategy Nash equilibria—one that isrisk dominant and another that ispayoff dominant. Thepayoff matrix in Figure 1 illustrates a generic stag hunt, where.
In addition to the pure strategy Nash equilibria there is onemixed strategy Nash equilibrium. This equilibrium depends on the payoffs, but the risk dominance condition places a bound on the mixed strategy Nash equilibrium. No payoffs (that satisfy the above conditions including risk dominance) can generate a mixed strategy equilibrium where Stag is played with a probability higher than one half. Thebest response correspondences are pictured here.
Although most authors focus on the prisoner's dilemma as the game that best represents the problem of socialcooperation, some authors believe that the stag hunt represents an equally (or more) interesting context in which to study cooperation and its problems (for an overview seeSkyrms 2004).
There is a substantial relationship between the stag hunt and the prisoner's dilemma. Inbiology many circumstances that have been described as prisoner's dilemma might also be interpreted as a stag hunt, depending on how fitness is calculated.
Cooperate | Defect | |
Cooperate | 2, 2 | 0, 3 |
Defect | 3, 0 | 1, 1 |
Fig. 3: Prisoner's dilemma example |
It is also the case that some human interactions that seem like prisoner's dilemmas may in fact be stag hunts. For example, suppose we have a prisoner's dilemma as pictured in Figure 3. The payoff matrix would need adjusting if players who defect against cooperators might be punished for their defection. For instance, if theexpected punishment is −2, then the imposition of this punishment turns the above prisoner's dilemma into the stag hunt given at the introduction.
The original stag hunt dilemma is as follows: a group of hunters have tracked a large stag, and found it to follow a certain path. If all the hunters work together, they can kill the stag and all eat. If they are discovered, or do not cooperate, the stag will flee, and all will go hungry.
The hunters hide and wait along a path. An hour goes by, with no sign of the stag. Two, three, four hours pass, with no trace. A day passes. The stag may not pass every day, but the hunters are reasonably certain that it will come. However, a hare is seen by all hunters moving along the path.
If a hunter leaps out and kills the hare, he will eat, but the trap laid for the stag will be wasted and the other hunters will starve. There is no certainty that the stag will arrive; the hare is present. The dilemma is that if one hunter waits, he risks one of his fellows killing the hare for himself, sacrificing everyone else. This makes the risk twofold; the risk that the stag does not appear, and the risk that another hunter takes the kill.
In addition to the example suggested by Rousseau,David Hume provides a series of examples that are stag hunts. One example addresses two individuals who must row a boat. If both choose to row they can successfully move the boat. However, if one doesn't, the other wastes his effort. Hume's second example involves two neighbors wishing to drain a meadow. If they both work to drain it they will be successful, but if either fails to do his part the meadow will not be drained.
Several animal behaviors have been described as stag hunts. One is the coordination ofslime molds. In times of stress, individual unicellular protists will aggregate to form one large body. Here if they all act together they can successfully reproduce, but success depends on the cooperation of many individual protozoa. Another example is the hunting practices oforcas (known ascarousel feeding). Orcas cooperatively corral large schools of fish to the surface and stun them by hitting them with their tails. Since this requires that the fish have no way to escape, it requires the cooperation of many orcas.
AuthorJames Cambias describes a solution to the game as the basis for an extraterrestrial civilization in his 2014 science fiction bookA Darkling Sea.Carol M. Rose argues that the stag hunt theory is useful in 'law and humanities' theory.[3] In international law, countries are the participants in a stag hunt. They can, for example, work together to improve good corporate governance.[4]
{{cite web}}
: CS1 maint: numeric names: authors list (link)