Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Jump to content
WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
Search

Meno

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Dialogue by Plato
This article is about Plato's dialogue. For the Thessalian general and character from Plato's dialogue, seeMeno (general). For other uses, seeMeno (disambiguation).

This articlerelies excessively onreferences toprimary sources. Please improve this article by addingsecondary or tertiary sources.
Find sources: "Meno" – news ·newspapers ·books ·scholar ·JSTOR
(November 2022) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
You can helpexpand this article with text translated fromthe corresponding article in German. (October 2023)Click [show] for important translation instructions.
  • View a machine-translated version of the German article.
  • Machine translation, likeDeepL orGoogle Translate, is a useful starting point for translations, but translators must revise errors as necessary and confirm that the translation is accurate, rather than simply copy-pasting machine-translated text into the English Wikipedia.
  • Consideradding a topic to this template: there are already 2,409 articles in themain category, and specifying|topic= will aid in categorization.
  • Do not translate text that appears unreliable or low-quality. If possible, verify the text with references provided in the foreign-language article.
  • Youmust providecopyright attribution in theedit summary accompanying your translation by providing aninterlanguage link to the source of your translation. A model attribution edit summary isContent in this edit is translated from the existing German Wikipedia article at [[:de:Menon]]; see its history for attribution.
  • You may also add the template{{Translated|de|Menon}} to thetalk page.
  • For more guidance, seeWikipedia:Translation.
Part ofa series on
Platonism
The Republic
The works of Plato
Related articles
Related categories

Meno (/ˈmn/;Ancient Greek:Μένων,Ménōn) is aSocratic dialogue written byPlato around 385 BC., but set at an earlier date around 402 BC.[1]Meno begins the dialogue by asking Socrates whethervirtue (inAncient Greek:ἀρετή,aretē) can be taught, acquired by practice, or comes bynature.[2] In order to determine whether virtue is teachable or not,Socrates tells Meno that they first need to determine what virtue is.[3] When the characters speak of virtue, oraretē, they refer to virtue in general, rather than particular virtues, such as justice or temperance. The first part of the work showcasesSocratic dialectical style; Meno, unable to adequately define virtue, is reduced to confusion oraporia.[4] Socrates suggests that they seek an adequate definition for virtue together. In response, Meno suggests that it is impossible to seek what one does not know, because one will be unable to determine whether one has found it.[5]

Socrates challenges Meno's argument, often called "Meno's Paradox", "Learner's Paradox", or the "Arabic Paradox",[citation needed] by introducing the theory of knowledge as recollection (anamnesis). As presented in the dialogue, the theory proposes that souls are immortal and know all things in a disembodied state; learning in the embodied is actually a process of recollecting that which the soul knew before it came into a body.[6] Socrates demonstrates recollection in action by posing a mathematical puzzle to one of Meno's slaves.[7] Subsequently, Socrates and Meno return to the question of whether virtue is teachable, employing the method of hypothesis. Near the end of the dialogue, Meno poses another famous puzzle, called "the Meno problem" or "the Value Problem for Knowledge", which questions why knowledge is valued more highly than true belief.[8] In response, Socrates provides a famous and somewhat enigmatic distinction between knowledge and true belief.[9]

Characters

[edit]

Plato'sMeno is a Socratic dialogue in which the two main speakers,Socrates andMeno (alsotransliterated as "Menon"), discuss human virtue: what it is, and whether or not it can be taught. Meno is visiting Athens fromThessaly with a large entourage of slaves attending him. Young, good-looking and well-born, he is a student ofGorgias, a prominentsophist whose views on virtue clearly influence that of Meno's. Early in the dialogue, Meno claims that he has held forth many times on the subject of virtue, and in front of large audiences.[10]

One of Meno'sslaves also has a speaking role, as one of the features of the dialogue is Socrates' engagement with the slave to demonstrate his idea ofanamnesis: certain knowledge is innate and "recollected" by the soul through proper inquiry.

Another participant later in the dialogue is Athenian politicianAnytus,[11] later one of theprosecutors of Socrates,[12] with whom Meno is friendly.

Dialogue

[edit]

Introduction of virtue

[edit]

The dialogue begins with Meno asking Socrates to tell him whether virtue can be taught. Socrates says that he does not know what virtue is, and neither does anyone else he knows.[3] Meno responds that, according to Gorgias, his Sophist mentor, virtue means different for different people, that what is virtuous for a man is to conduct himself in the city so that he helps his friends, injures his enemies, and takes care all the while that he personally comes to no harm. Virtue is different for a woman, he says. Her domain is the management of the household, and she is supposed to obey her husband. He says that children (male and female) have their own proper virtue, and so do old men—free orslaves.[13] Socrates objects: there must be some virtue common to all human beings.

Socrates rejects the idea that human virtue depends on a person's sex or age. He leads Meno towards the idea that virtues are common to all people, thatsophrosunê ('temperance', i.e. exercise ofself-control) anddikê (akadikaiosunê; 'justice', i.e. refrain from harming others) are virtues even in children and old men.[14] Meno proposes to Socrates that the "capacity to govern men" may be a virtue common to all people. Socrates points out to the slaveholder that "governing well" cannot be a virtue of a slave, because then he would not be a slave.[15]

One of the errors that Socrates points out is that Meno lists many particular virtues without defining a common feature inherent to virtues which makes them thus. Socrates remarks that Meno makes many out of one, like somebody who breaks a plate.[16]

Meno proposes that virtue is the desire for good things and the power to get them. Socrates points out that this raises a second problem—many people do not recognize evil.[17] The discussion then turns to the question of accounting for the fact that so many people are mistaken about good and evil and take one for the other. Socrates asks Meno to consider whether good things must be acquired virtuously in order to be really good.[18] Socrates leads onto the question of whether virtue is one thing or many.

No satisfactory definition of virtue emerges in theMeno. Socrates' comments, however, show that he considers a successful definition to be unitary, rather than a list of varieties of virtue, that it must contain all and only those terms which are genuine instances of virtue, and must not becircular.[19]

Meno's paradox

[edit]

Meno asks Socrates:[20][21]

And how will you enquire, Socrates, into that which you do not know? What will you put forth as the subject of enquiry? And if you find what you want, how will you ever know that this is the thing which you did not know?

Socrates rephrases the question, which has come to be the canonical statement of Meno's paradox or the paradox of inquiry:[20][22]

[A] man cannot enquire either about that which he knows, or about that which he does not know; for if he knows, he has no need to enquire; and if not, he cannot; for he does not know the very subject about which he is to enquire.

— translated byBenjamin Jowett, 1871

Dialogue with Meno's slave

[edit]
Depiction of an Athenian slave from 380-370 BC,National Archaeological Museum of Athens

Socrates responds to thissophistical paradox with amythos ('narrative' or 'fiction') according to which souls are immortal and have learned everything prior totransmigrating into the human body. Since the soul has had contact with real things prior to birth, we have only to 'recollect' them when alive. Such recollection requiresSocratic questioning, which according to Socrates is not teaching. Socrates demonstrates his method of questioning and recollection by interrogating a slave who is ignorant of geometry.

Socrates begins one of the most influential dialogues of Western philosophy regarding the argument forinborn knowledge. By drawing geometric figures in the ground Socrates demonstrates that the slave is initially unaware of the length that a side must be in order to double the area of a square with 2-foot sides. The slave guesses first that the original side must be doubled in length (4 feet), and when this proves too much, that it must be 3 feet. This is still too much, and the slave is at a loss.

Socrates claims that before he got hold of him the slave (who has been picked at random from Meno's entourage) might have thought he could speak "well and fluently" on the subject of a square double the size of a given square.[23] Socrates comments that this "numbing" he caused in the slave has done him no harm and has even benefited him.[24]

The blue square is twice the area of the yellow square

Socrates then adds three more squares to the original square, to form a larger square four times the size. He draws four diagonal lines which bisect each of the smaller squares. Through questioning, Socrates leads the slave to the discovery that the square formed by these diagonals has an area of eight square feet, double that of the original. He says that the slave has "spontaneously recovered" knowledge which he knew from a past life,[25] without having been taught. Socrates is satisfied that new beliefs were "newly aroused" in the slave.

After witnessing the example with the slave boy, Meno tells Socrates that he thinks that Socrates is correct in his theory of recollection, to which Socrates agrees:[20][26]

Some things I have said of which I am not altogether confident. But that we shall be better and braver and less helpless if we think that we ought to enquire, than we should have been if we indulged in the idle fancy that there was no knowing and no use in seeking to know what we do not know; that is a theme upon which I am ready to fight, in word and deed, to the utmost of my power.

— translated byBenjamin Jowett, 1871, Meno.[27]

Anytus

[edit]

Meno now beseeches Socrates to return to the original question, how virtue is acquired, and in particular, whether or not it is acquired by teaching or through life experience. Socrates proceeds on the hypothesis that virtue is knowledge, and it is quickly agreed that, if this is true, virtue is teachable. They turn to the question of whether virtue is indeed knowledge. Socrates is hesitant, because, if virtue were knowledge, there should be teachers and learners of it, but there are none.

CoincidentallyAnytus appears, whom Socrates praises as the son ofAnthemion, who earned his fortune with intelligence and hard work. He says that Anthemion had his son well-educated and so Anytus is well-suited to join the investigation. Socrates suggests that the sophists are teachers of virtue. Anytus is horrified, saying that he neither knows any, nor cares to know any. Socrates then questions why it is that men do not always produce sons of the same virtue as themselves. He alludes to other notable male figures, such asThemistocles,Aristides,Pericles andThucydides, and casts doubt on whether these men produced sons as capable of virtue as themselves. Anytus becomes offended and accuses Socrates ofslander, warning him to be careful expressing such opinions. (The historical Anytus was one of Socrates' accusers in histrial.) Socrates suggests that Anytus does not realize what slander is, and continues his dialogue with Meno as to the definition of virtue.

True belief and knowledge

[edit]

After the discussion with Anytus, Socrates returns to quizzing Meno for his own thoughts on whether the sophists are teachers of virtue and whether virtue can be taught. Meno is again at a loss, and Socrates suggests that they have made a mistake in agreeing that knowledge is required for virtue. He points out the similarities and differences between "true belief" and "knowledge". True beliefs are as useful to us as knowledge, but they often fail to "stay in their place" and must be "tethered" by what he callsaitiaslogismos ('calculation of reason' or 'reasoned explanation'), immediately adding that this isanamnesis, or recollection.[28]

Whether Plato intends that the tethering of true beliefs with reasoned explanations must always involveanamnesis is explored in later interpretations of the text.[29][30] Socrates' distinction between "true belief" and "knowledge" forms the basis of the philosophicaldefinition of knowledge as "justified true belief".Myles Burnyeat and others, however, have argued that the phraseaitias logismos refers to a practical working out of a solution, rather than a justification.[31]

Socrates concludes that, in the virtuous people of the present and the past, at least, virtue has been the result of divine inspiration, akin to the inspiration of the poets, whereas a knowledge of it will require answering the basic question,what is virtue?. In most modern readings these closing remarks are "evidently ironic",[32] but Socrates' invocation of the gods may be sincere, albeit "highly tentative".[33]

This passage in the Meno is often seen as the first statement of the problem of the value of knowledge or "the Meno problem":how is knowledge more valuable than mere true belief?[34] The nature of knowledge and belief is also discussed in theThaetetus.

Meno and Protagoras

[edit]

Meno's theme is also dealt with in the dialogueProtagoras, where Plato ultimately has Socrates arrive at the opposite conclusion: virtuecan be taught. Likewise, while inProtagoras knowledge is uncompromisingly this-worldly, inMeno the theory of recollection points to a link between knowledge and eternal truths.[19]

Texts and translations

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^Rawson, G.,Plato: Meno in theInternet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, accessed on 16 December 2024
  2. ^Plato,Meno, 70a
  3. ^abPlato,Meno, 71b
  4. ^Plato,Meno, 80a-b
  5. ^Plato,Meno, 80d
  6. ^Plato,Meno, 81a-e
  7. ^Plato,Meno, 82a-86c
  8. ^Plato,Meno, 97b-d
  9. ^Plato,Meno, 98a
  10. ^Plato,Meno, 80b
  11. ^Plato,Meno, 89e onwards
  12. ^Plato,Apology, footnote 3, accessed on 28 December 2024
  13. ^Plato,Meno, 71e
  14. ^Plato,Meno, 73b
  15. ^Plato,Meno, 73c–d
  16. ^Plato,Meno, 77a
  17. ^Plato,Meno, 77d–e
  18. ^Plato,Meno, 78b
  19. ^abDay, Jane Mary. 1994.Plato's Meno in Focus.Routledge. p. 19.ISBN 0-415-00297-4.
  20. ^abcPlato,Meno (translated byB. Jowett 1871).
  21. ^Plato. [380 BC] 1976.Meno, translated byG. M. A. Grube. Indianapolis:Hackett. line 80d, p. 9.
  22. ^Plato. [380 BC] 1976.Meno, translated byG. M. A. Grube. Indianapolis:Hackett. line 80e:

    "[A] man cannot search either for what he knows or for what he does not know; He cannot search for what he knows--since he knows it, there is no need to search--nor for what he does not know, for he does not know what to look for."

  23. ^Plato,Meno, 84c
  24. ^Plato,Meno, 84b
  25. ^Plato,Meno, 85d
  26. ^Plato,Meno, 86b
  27. ^Plato (1871).Meno. Translated by Benjamin Jowett. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons. p. 37.
  28. ^Vlastos, Gregory. 1996.Studies in Greek Philosophy: Socrates, Plato, and Their Tradition 2.Princeton University Press.ISBN 0-691-01938-X. p. 155.
  29. ^Fine, Gail. 1992. "Inquiry in the 'Meno'." InThe Cambridge Companion to Plato, edited by R. Kraut. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.ISBN 0-521-43610-9. p. 221.
  30. ^Kahn, Charles. 2006. "Plato on Recollection" inA Companion to Plato 37, edited by H. H. Benson.Wiley-Blackwell.ISBN 1-4051-1521-1. p. 122.
  31. ^Fine, Gail. 2004. "Knowledge and True Belief in theMeno",Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 27(winter): 61–62, edited byD. Sedley.ISBN 0-19-927712-5.
  32. ^Waterfield, Robin. 2005.Meno and Other Dialogues, (Oxford World Classics). Oxford University Press.ISBN 0-19-280425-1. pxliv.
  33. ^Scott, Dominic. 2006.Plato's 'Meno'. Cambridge University Press. p 193.ISBN 0-521-64033-4.
  34. ^Pritchard, Duncan, John Turri, and J. Adam Carter. [2007] 2018. "The Value of Knowledge" (revised).The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Sources

[edit]

External links

[edit]
Wikisource has original text related to this article:
Notableparadoxes
Philosophical
Logical
Economic
Decision theory
Life
Concepts
Phrases
Family
Works
that
include
Socrates
Art
Stage
Literature
Other
Dialogues
Plato
Xenophon
Other
Related
Works
Of doubtful
authenticity
Philosophy
Allegories
and metaphors
Life
Legacy
International
National
Other
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Meno&oldid=1269748968"
Categories:
Hidden categories:

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp