A mosaic representing both the judicial and legislative aspects of law. The woman on the throne holds a sword to chastise the guilty and apalm branch to reward the meritorious.Glory surrounds her head and theaegis ofMinerva signifies the armor of righteousness and wisdom.[1]
Therule of law is a political and legalideal that all people and institutions within apolitical body are accountable to the same laws, including lawmakers, government officials, and judges.[2][3][4] It is sometimes stated simply as "no one is above the law" or "all are equal before the law". According toEncyclopædia Britannica, it is defined as "the mechanism, process, institution, practice, or norm that supports the equality of all citizens before the law, secures a nonarbitrary form of government, and more generally prevents the arbitrary use of power."[5]
Use of the phrase can be traced to16th-century Britain. In the following century, Scottish theologianSamuel Rutherford employed it in arguing against thedivine right of kings.[6]John Locke wrote that freedom in society means being subject only to laws written by a legislature that apply to everyone, with a person being otherwise free from both governmental and private restrictions of liberty. The phrase "rule of law" was further popularized in the 19th century by British juristA. V. Dicey. However, the principle, if not the phrase itself, was recognized by ancient thinkers.Aristotle wrote: "It is more proper that law should govern than any one of the citizens."[citation needed]
The termrule of law is closely related toconstitutionalism as well asRechtsstaat. It refers to a political situation, not to any specific legal rule.[7][8][9] Distinct is therule of man, where one person or group of persons rule arbitrarily.[10]
Although credit for popularizing the expression "the rule of law" in modern times is usually given toA. V. Dicey,[11][12] development of the legal concept can be traced through history to many ancient civilizations, includingancient Greece,Mesopotamia,India, andRome.[13][14]
The earliest conception of rule of law can be traced back to the Indian epicsRamayana andMahabharata - the earliest versions of which date around to 8th or 9th centuries BC.[15][16][17] TheMahabharata deals with the concepts ofDharma (used to mean law and duty interchangeably),Rajdharma (duty of the king) andDharmaraja. It states in one of its slokas that,"The people should execute a king who does not protect them, but deprives them of their property and assets and who takes no advice or guidance from any one. Such a king is not a king but misfortune."[18][19]
Other sources for the philosophy of rule of law can be traced to theUpanishads which state that, "The law is the king of the kings. No one is higher than the law. Not even the king." Other commentaries includeKautilya'sArthashastra (4th-century BC),Manusmriti (dated to the 1st to 3rd century CE),Yajnavalkya-Smriti (dated between the 3rd and 5th century CE),Brihaspati Smriti (dated between 15 CE and 16 CE).[20][21]
Several scholars have also traced the concept of the rule of law back to 4th-century BCAthens, seeing it either as the dominant value of theAthenian democracy,[22] or as one held in conjunction with the concept ofpopular sovereignty.[23] However, these arguments have been challenged and the present consensus is that upholding an abstract concept of the rule of law was not "the predominant consideration" of the Athenian legal system.[24]Aristotle, in hisPolitics, wrote: "It is more proper that law should govern than any one of the citizens: upon the same principle, if it is advantageous to place the supreme power in some particular persons, they should be appointed to be only guardians, and the servants of the laws."[25]
The idea of the rule of law can be regarded as a modern iteration of the ideas of ancient Greek philosophers, who argued that the best form of government was rule by the best men.[26]Plato advocated abenevolent monarchy ruled by an idealizedphilosopher king, who was above the law.[26] Plato nevertheless hoped that the best men would be good at respecting established laws, explaining that "Where the law is subject to some other authority and has none of its own, the collapse of the state, in my view, is not far off; but if law is the master of the government and the government is its slave, then the situation is full of promise and men enjoy all the blessings that the gods shower on a state."[27] Similarly,Aristotle flatly opposed letting the highest officials wield power beyond guarding and serving the laws.[26] In other words, Aristotle advocated the rule of law:
It is more proper that law should govern than any one of the citizens: upon the same principle, if it is advantageous to place the supreme power in some particular persons, they should be appointed to be only guardians, and the servants of the laws.[25]
The Roman statesmanCicero is often cited as saying, roughly: "We are all servants of the laws in order to be free."[28] During the Roman Republic, controversial magistrates might be put on trial when their terms of office expired. Under the Roman Empire, the sovereign was personally immune (legibus solutus), but those with grievances could sue the treasury.[11]
In China, members of the school oflegalism during the 3rd century BC argued for using law as a tool of governance, but they promoted "ruleby law" as opposed to "ruleof law," meaning that they placed the aristocrats and emperor above the law.[29] In contrast, theHuang–Lao school ofDaoism rejectedlegal positivism in favor of anatural law that even the ruler would be subject to.[30]
The ancient concept of ruleof law can be distinguished from ruleby law, according to political science professor Li Shuguang: "The difference ... is that, under the rule of law, the law is preeminent and can serve as a check against the abuse of power. Under rule by law, the law is a mere tool for a government, that suppresses in a legalistic fashion."[31]
Alfred the Great, Anglo-Saxon king in the 9th century, reformed the law of his kingdom and assembled a law code (theDoom Book) which he grounded on biblical commandments. He held that the same law had to be applied to all persons, whether rich or poor, friends or enemies. This was likely inspired byLeviticus 19:15: "You shall do no iniquity in judgment. You shall not favor the wretched and you shall not defer to the rich. In righteousness you are to judge your fellow."[32][better source needed]
In 1215, ArchbishopStephen Langton gathered the Barons in England and restricted the powers ofKing John and future sovereigns and magistrates under the rule of law, preserving ancient liberties byMagna Carta in return for exacting taxes.[33][34] The influence of Magna Carta ebbed and waned across centuries. The weakening of royal power it demonstrated was based more upon the instability presented by contested claims than thoughtful adherence to constitutional principles. Until 1534, the Church excommunicated people for violations, but after a time Magna Carta was simply replaced by other statutes considered binding upon the king to act according to "process of the law". Magna Carta's influence is considered greatly diminished by the reign ofHenry VI, after theWars of the Roses.[35] The ideas contained in Magna Carta are widely considered to have influenced theUnited States Constitution.[36]
The first known use of this English phrase occurred around 1500.[37] Another early example of the phrase "rule of law" is found in a petition toJames I of England in 1610, from theHouse of Commons:
Amongst many other points of happiness and freedom which your majesty's subjects of this kingdom have enjoyed under your royal progenitors, kings and queens of this realm, there is none which they have accounted more dear and precious than this, to be guided and governed by the certainrule of the law which giveth both to the head and members that which of right belongeth to them, and not by any uncertain or arbitrary form of government ...[38]
In 1607, English Chief JusticeSir Edward Coke said in theCase of Prohibitions "that the law was the golden met-wand and measure to try the causes of the subjects; and which protected His Majesty in safety and peace: with which the King (James I) was greatly offended, and said, that then he should be under the law, which was treason to affirm, as he said; to which I said, thatBracton saith,quod Rex non debet esse sub homine, sed sub Deo et lege (that the King ought not to be under any man but under God and the law.)."
Among the first modern authors to use the term and give the principle theoretical foundations wasSamuel Rutherford inLex, Rex (1644).[6] The title, Latin for "the law is king", subverts the traditional formulationrex lex ("the king is law").[40]James Harrington wrote inOceana (1656), drawing principally on Aristotle'sPolitics, that among forms of government an "Empire of Laws, and not of Men" was preferable to an "Empire of Men, and not of Laws".[41]
The natural liberty of man is to be free from any superior power on earth, and not to be under the will or legislative authority of man, but to have only the law of nature for his rule. The liberty of man, in society, is to be under no other legislative power, but that established, by consent, in the commonwealth; nor under the dominion of any will, or restraint of any law, but what that legislative shall enact, according to the trust put in it. Freedom then is not what Sir Robert Filmer tells us, Observations, A. 55. a liberty for every one to do what he lists, to live as he pleases, and not to be tied by any laws: but freedom of men under government is, to have a standing rule to live by, common to every one of that society, and made by the legislative power erected in it; a liberty to follow my own will in all things, where the rule prescribes not; and not to be subject to the inconstant, uncertain, unknown, arbitrary will of another man: as freedom of nature is, to be under no other restraint but the law of nature.[42]
In 1776, the notion that no one is above the law was popular during the founding of the United States. For example,Thomas Paine wrote in his pamphletCommon Sense that "in America,the law is king. For as in absolute governments the King is law, so in free countries the lawought to be king; and there ought to be no other."[45] In 1780,John Adams enshrined this principle in Article VI of the Declaration of Rights in theConstitution of the Commonwealth of Massachusetts:
No man, nor corporation, or association of men, have any other title to obtain advantages, or particular and exclusive privileges, distinct from those of the community, than what arises from the consideration of services rendered to the public; and this title being in nature neither hereditary, nor transmissible to children, or descendants, or relations by blood, the idea of a man born a magistrate, lawgiver, or judge, is absurd and unnatural.[46]
The term "rule of law" was popularised by British juristA. V. Dicey,[11] who viewed the rule of law incommon law systems as comprising three principles. First, that government must follow the law that it makes; second, that no one is exempt from the operation of the law and that it applies equally to all; and third, that general rights emerge from particular cases decided by the courts.[47]
The influence of Britain, France and the United States contributed to spreading the principle of the rule of law to other countries around the world.[48][49]
TheOxford English Dictionary has definedrule of law as:[50]
The authority and influence of law in society, esp. when viewed as a constraint on individual and institutional behaviour; (hence) the principle whereby all members of a society (including those in government) are considered equally subject to publicly disclosed legal codes and processes.
Despite wide use by politicians, judges and academics, the rule of law has been described as "an exceedingly elusive notion".[51] In modernlegal theory, there are at least two principal conceptions of the rule of law: aformalist or "thin" definition, and a substantive or "thick" definition. Formalist definitions of the rule of law do not make a judgment about the justness of law itself, but define specific procedural attributes that a legal framework must have in order to be in compliance with the rule of law. Substantive conceptions of the rule of law, generally from more recent authors, go beyond this and include certain substantive rights that are said to be based on, or derived from, the rule of law.[52] One occasionally encounters a third "functional" conception.[53]
The functional interpretation of the term rule of law contrasts the rule of law with therule of man.[54] According to the functional view, a society in which government officers have a great deal of discretion has a low degree of "rule of law", whereas a society in which government officers have little discretion has a high degree of "rule of law".[54] Upholding the rule of law can sometimes require the punishment of those who commit offenses that arejustifiable undernatural law but not statutory law.[55] The rule of law is thus somewhat at odds with flexibility, even when flexibility may be preferable.[54]
Formalist theorists claim that the rule of law requires procedural generality (general rules that apply to classes of persons and behaviors as opposed to individuals), publicity (no secret laws), prospective application (little or no retroactive laws), consistency (no contradictory laws),[56] equality (applied equally throughout all society), and certainty (certainty of application for a given situation), but that there are no requirements with regard to the substantive content of the law.[53][57] Formalists includeA. V. Dicey,F. A. Hayek,Joseph Raz, andJoseph Unger.
According to Dicey, the rule of law in the United Kingdom has three dominant characteristics:[58] First, the absolute supremacy of regular law – a person is to be judged by a fixed set of rules and punished for breaching only the law, and is not to be subject to "the exercise by persons in authority of wide, arbitrary, or discretionary powers of constraint".[59] Second, the equality of law — "the universal subjection of all classes to one law administered by the ordinary Courts".[60] Third, the fact that, in the United Kingdom, theconstitution is the result of thecommon law, being not the source but the consequence of citizens' rights.[61]
A 1977 article byJoseph Raz argued that the rule of law means that people should obey the law and be ruled by it.[62] Construed more narrowly, the rule of law would also mean that the government should be ruled by and subjected to the law. Following from Raz's general conception of the rule of law, he argued for the existence of two groups of principles of the rule of law: First, that the law is capable of guiding the behaviour of its subjects; second, that there exists an effective legal machinery that secures actual compliance with the rule of law.[63] The first group comprises principles such as the accessibility, clarity, and prospective nature of the law;[64] the stability of the law;[65] and the compliance of lawmaking with "open, stable, clear and general rules" that create a stable framework,[66] with such rules empowering authorities to make orders and providing guidelines for the exercise of such powers.[66] The second group includes principles includingjudicial independence,[67]natural justice,[68]judicial review,[68] and limited administrative discretion.[69]
Joseph Raz in February 2009. He stated in a 1977 article that the rule of law requires that "the making of particular laws should be guided by open and relatively stable general rules"
In Raz's view, one of the virtues of the rule of law is the restraint it imposes on authorities. It aims to exclude arbitrary power, as most of the exercises of arbitrary power violate the rule of law. Arbitrary power is excluded when courts hold themselves accountable only to the law and observe "fairly strict procedures". Another virtue is the protection it accords to individual freedom, namely, "the sense of freedom in which it is identified with an effective ability to choose between as many options as possible". Most importantly, to adhere to the rule of law is to respect humandignity by "treating humans as persons capable of planning and plotting their future".[70]
Raz also identified some of the potential pitfalls of the rule of law. He opined that as the rule of law is designed "to minimise the harm to freedom and dignity which the law may cause in its pursuit of its goals however laudable these may be", the strict pursuit of the rule of law may prevent one from achieving certain social goals which may be preferable to the rule of law: "Sacrificing too many social goals on the altar of the rule of law may make the law barren and empty".[71]
Substantive theorists believe that the rule of law necessarily entails protection of individual rights. Some substantive theorists believe that democracy is part of the rule of law.[54] Substantivists includeRonald Dworkin,Sir John Laws,Lon Fuller,Trevor Allan, andTom Bingham holding that the rule of law intrinsically protects some or all individual rights.
Ronald Dworkin in September 2008. Dworkin's conception of the rule of law is "thick", as it encompasses a substantive theory of law andadjudication.
Ronald Dworkin defines what he terms the "rights conception" of the rule of law as follows:[72]
It assumes that citizens have moral rights and duties with respect to one another, and political rights against the state as a whole. It insists that these moral and political rights be recognized in positive law, so that they may be enforced upon the demand of individual citizens through courts or other judicial institutions of the familiar type, so far as this is practicable. The rule of law on this conception is the ideal of rule by an accurate public conception of individual rights. It does not distinguish, as the rule book conception does, between the rule of law and substantive justice; on the contrary it requires, as part of the ideal of law, that the rules in the book capture and enforce moral rights.
Paul Craig, in analysing Dworkin's view, drew three conclusions. First, Dworkin rejects the need to distinguish between "legal" rules and a more completepolitical philosophy, since the rule of law is basically the theory of law andadjudication that he believes is correct. Secondly, the rule of law is not simply the thin or formal rule of law; the latter forms part of Dworkin's theory of law and adjudication. Thirdly, since taking a substantive view of the rule of law requires choosing what the best theory ofjustice is, it is necessary to articulate particular conceptions of what liberty, equality and other freedoms require.[73]
In his book, "What Is the Rule of Law?"Lon Fuller rejects legal positivism, the idea that law is no higher than a particular authority, that the law is morally neutral, and he sets out a list of requirements to include in his definition of the rule of law.[74]
Laws must exist and those laws should be obeyed by all, including government officials.
Laws must be published.
Laws must be prospective in nature so that the effect of the law may only take place after the law has been passed. For example, the court cannot convict a person of a crime committed before a criminal statute prohibiting the conduct was passed.
Laws should be written with reasonable clarity to avoid unfair enforcement.
Law must avoid contradictions.
Law must not command the impossible.
Law must stay constant through time to allow the formalization of rules; however, law also must allow for timely revision when the underlying social and political circumstances have changed.
Official action should be consistent with the declared rule.
In his book, "The rule of law"Tom Bingham further has requirements not only on how the laws must be handled, but also requirements that the laws must follow to include in his definition of the rule of law[75].
The Law Must Be Accessible
As far as possible, use law, not discretion
Equality before the law
Exercise of power must be used for the purpose for which the power were conferred
Respect for Human Rights
Means must be for resolving disputes for which the parties themselves are not able to resolve
Everyone should have a right to legal redress and to fair trials
The laws must be in compliance with international law
Economists and lawyers have studied and analysed the rule of law's impact oneconomic development. In particular, a major question in the area oflaw and economics is whether the rule of law matters to economic development, particularly indeveloping nations.[76] The economistF. A. Hayek analyzed how the rule of law might be beneficial to the free market. Hayek proposed that under the rule of law, individuals would be able to make wise investments and future plans with some confidence in a successful return on investment when he stated: "under the Rule of Law the government is prevented from stultifying individual efforts byad hoc action. Within the known rules of the game the individual is free to pursue his personal ends and desires, certain that the powers of government will not be used deliberately to frustrate his efforts."[77]
Studies have shown that weak rule of law (for example, discretionary regulatory enforcement) discourages investment. Economists have found, for example, that a rise in discretionary regulatory enforcement caused US firms to abandon international investments.[78]
Constitutional economics is the study of the compatibility of economic and financial decisions within existing constitutional law frameworks. Aspects of constitutional frameworks relevant to both the rule of law andpublic economics include government spending on thejudiciary, which, in many transitional anddeveloping countries, is completely controlled by the executive. Additionally, judicial corruption may arise from both the executive branch and private actors. Standards ofconstitutional economics such as transparency can also be used during annualbudget processes for the benefit of the rule of law. Further, the availability of an effective court system in situations of unfair government spending and executive impoundment of previously authorized appropriations is a key element for the success of the rule of law.[79]
Nobel laureates (2024)Daron Acemoglu andJames A. Robinson emphasize the importance of the rule of law in their bookWhy Nations Fail. They argue that the rule of law ensures that laws apply equally to everyone, including elites and government officials. This principle is crucial for promoting inclusive institutions, which are key to sustained economic growth and prosperity.
The authors highlight historical examples, such as the French Revolution, where the rule of law helped dismantle absolutism and feudal privileges, paving the way for inclusive institutions. They also discuss how pluralistic political institutions are essential for the rule of law to thrive, as they create broad coalitions that support fairness and equality.
The term "rule of law" has been used primarily in the English-speaking countries, and it is not yet fully clarified with regard to such well-established democracies such as Sweden, Denmark, France, Germany, or Japan. A common language between lawyers of common law and civil law countries is critically important for research of links between the rule of law and real economy.[81]
The rule of law can be hampered when there is a disconnect between legal and popular consensus. For example, under the auspices of theWorld Intellectual Property Organization, nominally strong copyright laws have been implemented throughout most of the world; but because the attitude of much of the population does not conform to these laws, a rebellion against ownership rights has manifested in rampantpiracy, including an increase inpeer-to-peer file sharing.[82] Similarly, in Russia,tax evasion is common and a person who admits he does not pay taxes is not judged or criticized by his colleagues and friends, because the tax system is viewed as unreasonable.[83]Bribery likewise has different normative implications across cultures.[84]
UNESCO has argued thateducation has an important role in promoting the rule of law and aculture of lawfulness, providing an important protective function by strengthening learners' abilities to face and overcome difficult life situations. Young people can be important contributors to a culture of lawfulness, and governments can provide educational support that nurtures positive values and attitudes in future generations.[85] A movement towards education for justice seeks to promote the rule of law in schools.[85]
Countries by adherence to the Rule of Law according to the 2017–18World Justice Project report
The rule of law has been considered one of the key dimensions that determine the quality andgood governance of a country.[86] Research, like theWorldwide Governance Indicators, defines the rule of law as "the extent to which agents have confidence and abide by the rules of society, and in particular the quality of contract enforcement, the police and the courts, as well as the likelihood of crime or violence."[86] Based on this definition the Worldwide Governance Indicators project has developed aggregate measurements for the rule of law in more than 200 countries, as seen in the map at right.[87] Other evaluations such as theWorld Justice Project Rule of Law Index[88] show that adherence to rule of law fell in 61% of countries in 2022. Globally, this means that 4.4 billion people live in countries where rule of law declined in 2021.[89]
In France and Germany the concepts of rule of law (Etat de droit andRechtsstaat respectively) are analogous to the principles of constitutional supremacy and protection of fundamental rights from public authorities, particularly thelegislature.[90][91] France was one of the early pioneers of the ideas of the rule of law.[92] The German interpretation is more rigid but similar to that of France and the United Kingdom.[93][94]
In the United Kingdom the rule of law is a long-standing principle of the way the country is governed, dating from England'sMagna Carta in 1215 and theBill of Rights 1689.[40][95][96] In the 19th century classic workIntroduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (1885),A. V. Dicey, a constitutional scholar and lawyer, wrote of the twin pillars of theBritish constitution: the rule of law andparliamentary sovereignty.[97]
All government officers of the United States, including thePresident,Justices of the Supreme Court, state judges and legislators, and allmembers of Congress, pledge first and foremost to uphold theConstitution, affirming that the rule of law is superior to the rule of any human leader.[98] At the same time, thefederal government has considerable discretion: the legislative branch is free to decide what statutes it will write, as long as it stays within itsenumerated powers and respects the constitutionally protectedrights of individuals. Likewise, the judicial branch has a degree ofjudicial discretion,[99] and the executive branch also has various discretionary powers includingprosecutorial discretion.
James Wilson said during thePhiladelphia Convention in 1787 that, "Laws may be unjust, may be unwise, may be dangerous, may be destructive; and yet not be so unconstitutional as to justify the Judges in refusing to give them effect."George Mason agreed that judges "could declare an unconstitutional law void. But with regard to every law, however unjust, oppressive or pernicious, which did not come plainly under this description, they would be under the necessity as judges to give it a free course."[100] Chief JusticeJohn Marshall a similar position in 1827: "When its existence as law is denied, that existence cannot be proved by showing what are the qualities of a law."[101]
Scholars continue to debate whether the U.S. Constitution adopted a particular interpretation of the "rule of law", and if so, which one. For example, John Harrison asserts that the word "law" in the Constitution is simply defined as that which is legally binding, rather than being "defined by formal or substantive criteria", and therefore judges do not have discretion to decide that laws fail to satisfy such unwritten and vague criteria.[102] Law professorFrederick Mark Gedicks disagrees, writing thatCicero,Augustine,Thomas Aquinas, and the framers of the U.S. Constitution believed that "an unjust law was not really a law at all".[103]
Some modern scholars contend that the rule of law has been corroded during the past century by the instrumental view of law promoted bylegal realists such asOliver Wendell Holmes andRoscoe Pound. For example, Brian Tamanaha asserts: "The rule of law is a centuries-old ideal, but the notion that law is a means to an end became entrenched only in the course of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries."[104]
Others argue that the rule of law has survived but was transformed to allow for the exercise of discretion by administrators. For much of American history, the dominant notion of the rule of law inadministrative law has been some version of Dicey's, that is, individuals should be able to challenge an administrative order by bringing suit in a court of general jurisdiction. The increased number of administrative cases led to fears that excess judicial oversight over administrative decisions would overwhelm the courts and destroy the advantages of specialization that led to the creation of administrative agencies in the first place. By 1941, a compromise had emerged. If administrators adopted procedures that more or less tracked "the ordinary legal manner" of the courts, further review of the facts by "the ordinary Courts of the land" was unnecessary. Thus Dicey's rule of law was recast into a purely procedural form.[105]
Numerous definitions of "rule of law" are used in United States governmental bodies. An organization's definition might depend on that organization's goal. For instance,military occupation orcounterinsurgency campaigns may necessitate prioritising physical security over human rights.[114] U.S. Army doctrine and U.S. Government (USG) interagency agreements might see the rule of law as a principle of governance:[114] Outlines of different definitions are given in aJAG Corps handbook for judge advocates deployed with the US Army.[114]
In Canada, the rule of law is associated withA.V. Dicey's view. It is mentioned in the preamble to theConstitution Act, 1982.The Constitution of Canada is "similar in principle" to theBritish constitution, and includes unwritten constitutional principles of democracy, judicial independence, federalism, constitutionalism and the rule of law, and the protection of minorities.[115]
In 1959,Roncarelli v Duplessis, theSupreme Court of Canada called the Rule of Law a "fundamental postulate" of theCanadian Constitution. According toReference Re Secession of Quebec, it encompasses, "a sense of orderliness, of subjection to known legal rules and of executive accountability to legal authority." InCanadian law, it means that the relationship between the state and the individual must be regulated by law and that the Constitution binds all governments, bothfederal and provincial, including theexecutive. With the adoption of theCanadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, the Canadian system of government was transformed to a significant extent from a system of Parliamentary supremacy to one of constitutional supremacy. The principle of the rule of law andconstitutionalism is aided by acknowledging that the constitution isentrenched beyond simplemajority rule.[116] However,the notwithstanding clause operates to provide a limited "legislative override" of certain fundamental freedoms contained in the Charter, and has been invoked at different times by provincial legislatures.
InCanadian administrative law, "all exercises of public authority must find their source in law. All decision-making powers have legal limits, derived from the enabling statute itself, the common or civil law or the Constitution.Judicial review is the means by which the courts supervise those who exercise statutory powers, to ensure that they do not overstep their legal authority. The function of judicial review is therefore to ensure the legality, the reasonableness and the fairness of the administrative process and its outcomes."[117] Administrative decision makers must adopt a culture of justification and demonstrate that their exercise of delegated public power can be “justified to citizens in terms of rationality and fairness.”[118]
East Asian cultures are influenced by two schools of thought,Confucianism, which advocated good governance as rule by leaders who are benevolent and virtuous, andlegalism, which advocated strict adherence to law. The influence of one school of thought over the other has varied throughout the centuries. One study indicates that throughout East Asia, only South Korea, Singapore, Japan, Taiwan and Hong Kong have societies that are robustly committed to a law-bound state.[119] According to Awzar Thi, a member of theAsian Human Rights Commission, the rule of law in Cambodia and most of Asia is weak or nonexistent:
Apart from a number of states and territories, across the continent there is a huge gulf between the rule of law rhetoric and reality. In Thailand, the police force is favor over the rich and corrupted. In Cambodia, judges are proxies for the ruling political party ... That a judge may harbor political prejudice or apply the law unevenly are the smallest worries for an ordinary criminal defendant in Asia. More likely ones are: Will the police fabricate the evidence? Will the prosecutor bother to show up? Will the judge fall asleep? Will I be poisoned in prison? Will my case be completed within a decade?[120]
In countries such as China and Vietnam, the transition to a market economy has been a major factor in a move toward the rule of law, because the rule of law is important to foreign investors and to economic development. It remains unclear whether the rule of law in countries like China and Vietnam will be limited to commercial matters or will spill into other areas as well, and if so whether that spillover will enhance prospects for related values such as democracy and human rights.[121]
In China, the phrase fǎzhì (法治), which can be translated as "rule of law," means using the law as an instrument to facilitate social control.[122]
Late Qing dynasty legal reforms unsuccessfully sought to implement Western legal principles including the rule of law and judicial independence.[123]: 122–123 Judicial independence further decreased in theRepublic of China underChiang Kai-shek per theKuomintang's policy of particization (danghua), under which administrative judges were required to have "deep comprehension" of the KMT's principles.[123]: 123
After China'sreform and opening-up, the Communist Party emphasized the rule of law as a basic strategy and method for state management of society.[124]: 110 Jiang Zemin first called for establishing a socialist rule of law at theFifteenth Party Congress in 1997.[124]: 110 Despite the CCP'sDocument 9 arguing that Western values have corrupted many people's understanding of the rule of law, the CCP has simultaneously endorsed governing the country in accordance with the rule of law.[125] These factors likely suggest that the CCP is creating a rule of law with Chinese characteristics, which may simply entail modifying the Western notion of rule of law to best match China's unique political, social, and historical conditions. As Document 9 suggests, the CCP does not see judicial independence, separation of power, or constitutional forms of governance as defined by Western society, as suiting China's unique form of governance.[126][127] This unique version of the rule of law with Chinese characteristics has led to different attempts to define China's method of governing the country by rule of law domestically and internationally.[128][127]
In his writings on socialist rule of law in China,Xi Jinping has emphasized traditional Chinese concepts including people as the root of the state (mingben), "the ideal of no lawsuit" (tianxia wusong), "respecting rite and stressing law" (longli zhongfa), "virtue first, penalty second" (dezhu xingfu), and "promoting virtue and being prudent in punishment" (mingde shenfa).[124]: 110–111 Xi states that the two fundamental aspects of the socialist rule of law are: that the political and legal organs (including courts, the police, and the procuratorate) must believe in the law and uphold the law; and all political and legal officials must follow the Communist Party.[124]: 115
Japan had centuries of tradition prior toWorld War II, during which there were laws, but they did not provide a central organizing principle for society, and they did not constrain the powers of government.[132] As the 21st century began, the percentage of people who were lawyers and judges in Japan remained very low relative to western Europe and the United States, and legislation in Japan tended to be terse and general, leaving much discretion in the hands of bureaucrats.[133][134]
The rule of law is enshrined in Article 2 of the Treaty on European Union as one of the common values for all Member States. Under the rule of law, all public powers always act within the constraints set out by law, in accordance with the values of democracy and fundamental rights, and under the control of independent and impartial courts. The rule of law includes principles such as legality, implying a transparent, accountable, democratic and pluralistic process for enacting laws; legal certainty; prohibiting the arbitrary exercise of executive power; effective judicial protection by independent and impartial courts, effective judicial review including respect for fundamental rights; separation of powers; and equality before the law. These principles have been recognised by the European Court of Justice and the European Court of Human Rights. In addition, the Council of Europe has developed standards and issued opinions and recommendations which provide well-established guidance to promote and uphold the rule of law.[135]
The Statute ofthe Council of Europe characterizes the rule of law as one of the core principles which the establishment of the organization based on. The paragraph 3 of the preamble of the Statute of the Council of Europe states: "Reaffirming their devotion to the spiritual and moral values which are the common heritage of their peoples and the true source of individual freedom, political liberty and the rule of law, principles which form the basis of all genuine democracy." The Statute lays the compliance with the rule of law principles as a condition for the European states to be a full member of the organization.[136]
In 1959, an event took place inNew Delhi and speaking as theInternational Commission of Jurists, made a declaration as to the fundamental principle of the rule of law. The event consisted of over 185 judges, lawyers, and law professors from 53 countries. This later became known as theDeclaration of Delhi. During the declaration they declared that the rule of law implied certain rights and freedoms, an independent judiciary, and social, economic and cultural conditions conducive to human dignity. One aspect not included in The Declaration of Delhi was for rule of law requiring legislative power to be subject tojudicial review.[137]
a principle of governance in which all persons, institutions and entities, public and private, including the State itself, are accountable to laws that are publicly promulgated, equally enforced and independently adjudicated, and which are consistent with international human rights norms and standards. It requires, as well, measures to ensure adherence to the principles of supremacy of law, equality before the law, accountability to the law, fairness in the application of the law, separation of powers, participation in decision-making, legal certainty, avoidance of arbitrariness and procedural and legal transparency.
The General Assembly has considered rule of law an agenda item since 1992, with renewed interest since 2006 and has adopted resolutions at its last three sessions.[139] The Security Council has held a number of thematic debates on the rule of law,[140] and adopted resolutions emphasizing the importance of these issues in the context of women, peace and security,[141] children in armed conflict,[142] and the protection of civilians in armed conflict.[143] ThePeacebuilding Commission has also regularly addressed rule of law issues with respect to countries on its agenda.[144] TheVienna Declaration and Programme of Action also requires the rule of law be included inhuman rights education.[145] Additionally, theSustainable Development Goal 16, a component of the 2030 Agenda is aimed at promoting the rule of law at national and international levels.[146]
In Our Common Agenda, theUnited NationsSecretary General wrote in paragraph 23: "In support of efforts to put people at the center of justice systems, I will promote a new vision for the rule of law, building on Sustainable Development Goal 16 and the 2012 Declaration of the High-level Meeting of the General Assembly on the Rule of Law at the National and International Levels."[147]
The Council of theInternational Bar Association passed a resolution in 2009 endorsing a substantive or "thick" definition of the rule of law:[148]
An independent, impartial judiciary; the presumption of innocence; the right to a fair and public trial without undue delay; a rational and proportionate approach to punishment; a strong and independent legal profession; strict protection of confidential communications between lawyer and client; equality of all before the law; these are all fundamental principles of the Rule of Law. Accordingly, arbitrary arrests; secret trials; indefinite detention without trial; cruel or degrading treatment or punishment; intimidation or corruption in the electoral process, are all unacceptable. The Rule of Law is the foundation of a civilised society. It establishes a transparent process accessible and equal to all. It ensures adherence to principles that both liberate and protect. The IBA calls upon all countries to respect these fundamental principles. It also calls upon its members to speak out in support of the Rule of Law within their respective communities.
The World Justice Project (WJP)[150] is an international organization that produces independent research and data, in order to build awareness, and stimulate action to advance the rule of law.[151]
The World Justice Project defines the rule of law as a durable system of laws, institutions, norms, and country commitment that uphold four universal principles:[152]
Accountability: the government and its officials and agents are accountable under the law.
Just Law: the law is clear, publicized, and stable, and is applied evenly. It ensures human rights as well as properly, contract, and procedural rights.
Open Government: the processes enforced are accessible, fair, and efficient.
Accessible and Impartial Justice: justice is delivered timely by competent, ethical, and independent representatives and neutrals who are accessible, have adequate resources, and reflect the makeup of the communities they serve.
TheInternational Development Law Organization (IDLO) is an intergovernmental organization with a joint focus on the promotion of rule of law and development. It works to empower people and communities to claim their rights, and provides governments with the know-how to realize them.[156] It supports emerging economies and middle-income countries to strengthen their legal capacity and rule of law framework for sustainable development and economic opportunity.[157] It is the only intergovernmental organization with an exclusive mandate to promote the rule of law and has experience working in more than 90 countries around the world.[158]
The International Development Law Organization has a holistic definition of the rule of law:
More than a matter of due process, the rule of law is an enabler of justice and development. The three notions are interdependent; when realized, they are mutually reinforcing. For IDLO, as much as a question of laws and procedure, the rule of law is a culture and daily practice. It is inseparable from equality, from access to justice and education, from access to health and the protection of the most vulnerable. It is crucial for the viability of communities and nations, and for the environment that sustains them.[159]
^Sempill, Julian (2020). "The Rule of Law and the Rule of Men: History, Legacy, Obscurity".Hague Journal on the Rule of Law.12 (3):511–540.doi:10.1007/s40803-020-00149-9.S2CID256425870.
^"Rule of Law". National Geographic Society. 15 March 2019. Retrieved29 January 2022.
^Hobson, Charles.The Great Chief Justice: John Marshall and the Rule of Law, p. 57 (University Press of Kansas, 1996): according toJohn Marshall, "the framers of the Constitution contemplated that instrument as a rule for the government of courts, as well as of the legislature."
^abRutherford, Samuel.Lex, rex: the law and the prince, a dispute for the just prerogative of king and people, containing the reasons and causes of the defensive wars of the kingdom of Scotland, and of their expedition for the ayd and help of their brethren of England,p. 237 (1644): "The prince remaineth, even being a prince, a social creature, a man, as well as a king; one who must buy, sell, promise, contract, dispose: ergo, he is not regula regulans, but under rule of law ..."
^Ten, C. l (2017), "Constitutionalism and the Rule of Law",A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, John Wiley & Sons, Ltd, pp. 493–502,doi:10.1002/9781405177245.ch22,ISBN978-1405177245
^Paul. "Resisting the Rule of Men." . Louis ULJ 62 (2017): 333. "I will say that we have "the rule of men" or "personal rule" when those who wield the power of the state are not obliged to give reasons to those over whom that power is being wielded—from the standpoint of the ruled, the rulers may simply act on their brute desires."
^abcWormuth, Francis.The Origins of Modern Constitutionalism, p. 28 (1949).
^Cowell, Herbert (1872).History and Constitution of the Courts and Legislative Authorities in India. Michigan: University of Michigan Press. pp. 37–56.ISBN1278155406.
^Ostwald, Martin (1986).From popular sovereignty to the sovereignty of law : law, society, and politics in fifth-century Athens. Berkeley: University of California Press. pp. 412–496.ISBN9780520067981.
^Ober, Josiah (1989).Mass and elite in democratic Athens : rhetoric, ideology, and the power of the people. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. pp. 144–7,299–300.ISBN9780691028644.
^Liddel, Peter P. (2007).Civic obligation and individual liberty in ancient Athens. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 130–131.ISBN978-0-19-922658-0.
^In full: "The magistrates who administer the law, the judges who act as its spokesmen, all the rest of us who live as its servants, grant it our allegiance as a guarantee of our freedom."—Cicero (1975).Murder Trials. Penguin Classics. Translated by Michael Grant. Harmondsworth: Penguin. p. 217. Original Latin: "Legum ministri magistratus, legum interpretes iudices, legum denique idcirco omnes servi sumus ut liberi esse possimus."—"Pro Cluentio".The Latin Library. 53:146. Retrieved5 March 2018.
^Oxford English Dictionary (OED), "Rule of Law, n.", accessed 27 April 2013. According to the OED, this sentence from about 1500 was written byJohn Blount: "Lawes And constitutcions be ordeyned be cause the noysome Appetit of man maye be kepte vnder the Rewle of lawe by the wiche mankinde ys dewly enformed to lyue honestly." And this sentence from 1559 is attributed toWilliam Bavand: "A Magistrate should..kepe rekenyng of all mennes behauiours, and to be carefull, least thei despisyng the rule of lawe, growe to a wilfulnes."
^Hallam, Henry.The Constitutional History of England, vol. 1, p. 441 (1827).
^Ferro, Víctor: El Dret Públic Català.Les Institucions a Catalunya fins al Decret de Nova Planta; Eumo Editorial;ISBN84-7602-203-4[page needed]
^Harrington, James (1747). Toland, John (ed.).The Oceana and other works (3 ed.). London: Millar. p. 37 (Internet Archive: copy possessed byJohn Adams).
^Albert Venn Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution, 5th ed (London: Macmillan and Co, 1897) at 175-84, cited in"Rule of Law", Centre for Constitutional Studies, July 4, 2019
^Oxford English Dictionary online (accessed 13 September 2018; spelling Americanized). The phrase "the rule of law" is also sometimes used in other senses.See Garner, Bryan A. (Editor in Chief).Black's Law Dictionary, 9th Edition, p. 1448. (Thomson Reuters, 2009).ISBN978-0-314-26578-4. Black's provides five definitions of "rule of law": the lead definition is "A substantive legal principle"; the second is the "supremacy of regular as opposed to arbitrary power".
^Luis Flores Ballesteros. "Corruption and development. Does the 'rule of law' factor weigh more than we think?" 54 Pesos May. 2008:54 Pesos 15 November 2008.[1]
^Hayek, F.A. (1994).The Road to Serfdom. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. p. 81.ISBN978-0-226-32061-8.
^Pech, Laurent (10 September 2006). "Rule of Law in France".Middlesex University – School of Law.SSRN929099.
^Letourneur, M.; Drago, R. (1958). "The Rule of Law as Understood in France".The American Journal of Comparative Law.7 (2):147–177.doi:10.2307/837562.JSTOR837562.
^Peerenboom, Randall (2004)."Rule of Law in France".Asian discourses of rule of law : theories and implementation of rule of law in twelve Asian countries, France and the U.S. (Digital printing. ed.). RoutledgeCurzon. p. 81.ISBN978-0-415-32612-4.
^Osborn v. Bank of the United States, 22 U.S. 738 (1824): "When [courts] are said to exercise a discretion, it is a mere legal discretion, a discretion to be exercised in discerning the course prescribed by law; and, when that is discerned, it is the duty of the court to follow it."
^Ogden v. Saunders,25U.S.213, 347 (1827). This was Marshall's only dissent in a constitutional case. Theindividualist anarchistLysander Spooner later denounced Marshall for this part of hisOgden dissent. SeeSpooner, Lysander (2008).Let's Abolish Government. Ludwig Von Mises Institute. p. 87. These same issues were also discussed in an earlier U.S. Supreme Court case,Calder v. Bull,3U.S.386 (1798), with JusticesJames Iredell andSamuel Chase taking opposite positions. See Presser, Stephen. "Symposium: Samuel Chase: In Defense of the Rule of Law and Against the Jeffersonians",Vanderbilt Law Review, vol. 62, p. 349 (March 2009).
^Harrison, John. "Substantive Due Process and the Constitutional Text,"Virginia Law Review, vol. 83, p. 493 (1997).
^Tamanaha, Brian.How an Instrumental View of Law Corrodes the Rule of Law, twelfth annual Clifford Symposium on Tort Law and Social Policy.
^Ernst, Daniel R. (2014).Tocqueville's Nightmare: The Administrative State Emerges in America, 1900–1940. Oxford University Press.ISBN978-0-19-992086-0[page needed]
^Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration) v Vavilov, 2019 SCC 65, at para 14, citing the Rt. Hon. B. McLachlin, “The Roles of Administrative Tribunals and Courts in Maintaining the Rule of Law” (1998), 12 C.J.A.L.P. 171, at p. 174
^abcdFang, Qiang (2024). "Understanding the Rule of Law in Xi's China". In Fang, Qiang; Li, Xiaobing (eds.).China under Xi Jinping: A New Assessment.Leiden University Press.ISBN9789087284411.
^Goldsworthy, Jeffrey."Legislative Sovereignty and the Rule of Law" in Tom Campbell, Keith D. Ewing and Adam Tomkins (eds),Sceptical Essays on Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), p. 69.
^"About IDLO".IDLO – International Development Law Organization. 26 February 2014.Archived from the original on 2 October 2019. Retrieved30 March 2022.
^"Rule of Law".IDLO – International Development Law Organization. February 24, 2014.Archived from the original on October 2, 2019. RetrievedFebruary 15, 2022.
Oakeshott, Michael (2006). "Chapters 31 and 32". In Terry Nardin and Luke O'Sullivan (ed.).Lectures in the History of Political Thought. Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic. p. 515.ISBN978-1-84540-093-4.OCLC63185299.