Thehistory of scientific method considers changes in the methodology of scientific inquiry, as distinct from thehistory of science itself. The development of rules forscientific reasoning has not been straightforward;scientific method has been the subject of intense and recurring debate throughout the history of science, and eminent natural philosophers and scientists have argued for the primacy of one or another approach to establishing scientific knowledge.
Rationalist explanations of nature, includingatomism, appeared both in ancient Greece in the thought ofLeucippus andDemocritus, and in ancient India, in theNyaya,Vaisheshika and Buddhist schools, whileCharvaka materialism rejected inference as a source of knowledge in favour of an empiricism that was always subject to doubt.Aristotle pioneered scientific method in ancient Greece alongside his empirical biology and his work on logic, rejecting a purelydeductive framework in favour of generalisations made from observations of nature.
Some of the most important debates in the history of scientific method center on:rationalism, especially as advocated byRené Descartes;inductivism, which rose to particular prominence withIsaac Newton and his followers; andhypothetico-deductivism, which came to the fore in the early 19th century. In the late 19th and early 20th centuries, a debate overrealism vs.antirealism was central to discussions of scientific method as powerful scientific theories extended beyond the realm of the observable, while in the mid-20th century some prominent philosophers argued against any universal rules ofscience at all.[1]
There are few explicit discussions of scientific methodologies in surviving records from early cultures. The most that can be inferred about the approaches to undertaking science in this period stems from descriptions of early investigations into nature, in the surviving records. AnEgyptian medical textbook, theEdwin Smith papyrus, (c. 1600 BCE), applies the following components: examination, diagnosis, treatment and prognosis, to the treatment of disease,[2] which display strong parallels to the basicempirical method of science and according toG. E. R. Lloyd[3] played a significant role in the development of this methodology. TheEbers papyrus (c. 1550 BCE) also contains evidence of traditionalempiricism.
By the middle of the 1st millennium BCE inMesopotamia,Babylonian astronomy had evolved into the earliest example of a scientific astronomy, as it was "the first and highly successful attempt at giving a refined mathematical description of astronomical phenomena." According to the historianAsger Aaboe, "all subsequent varieties of scientific astronomy, in theHellenistic world,in India,in the Islamic world, and inthe West – if not indeed all subsequent endeavour in theexact sciences – depend upon Babylonian astronomy in decisive and fundamental ways."[4]
The earlyBabylonians andEgyptians developed much technical knowledge, crafts, and mathematics[5] used in practical tasks of divination, as well as a knowledge of medicine,[6] and made lists of various kinds. While the Babylonians in particular had engaged in the earliest forms of anempirical mathematical science, with their early attempts at mathematically describing natural phenomena, they generally lacked underlying rational theories of nature.[4][7][8]
Greek-speaking ancient philosophers engaged in the earliest known forms of what is today recognized as a rational theoretical science,[7][9] with the move towards a more rational understanding of nature which began at least since the Archaic Period (650 – 480 BCE) with the Presocratic school.Thales was the first known philosopher to use natural explanations, proclaiming that every event had a natural cause, even though he is known for saying "all things are full of gods" and sacrificed an ox when he discovered his theorem.[10]Leucippus, went on to develop the theory ofatomism – the idea that everything is composed entirely of various imperishable, indivisible elements calledatoms. This was elaborated in great detail byDemocritus.[a]
Similar atomist ideas emerged independently among ancientIndian philosophers of theNyaya,Vaisesika andBuddhist schools.[11] In particular, like the Nyaya, Vaisesika, and Buddhist schools, theCārvāka epistemology was materialist, and skeptical enough to admit perception as the basis for unconditionally true knowledge, while cautioning that if one could only infer a truth, then one must also harbor a doubt about that truth; an inferred truth could not be unconditional.[12]
Towards the middle of the 5th century BCE, some of the components of a scientific tradition were already heavily established, even before Plato, who was an important contributor to this emerging tradition, thanks to the development of deductive reasoning, as propounded by his student,Aristotle. InProtagoras (318d–f),Plato mentioned the teaching of arithmetic, astronomy and geometry in schools. The philosophical ideas of this time were mostly freed from the constraints of everyday phenomena andcommon sense. This denial of reality as we experience it reached an extreme inParmenides who argued that the world is one and that change and subdivision do not exist.[b]
As early as the 4th century BCE,armillary spheres had been invented in China,[c] and in the 3rd century BCE in Greece for use inastronomy; their use was promulgated thereafter, for example by§ Ibn al-Haytham, and by§ Tycho Brahe.
In the 3rd and 4th centuries BCE, theGreek physiciansHerophilos (335–280 BCE) andErasistratus of Chios employed experiments to further their medical research; Erasistratus at one time repeatedly weighed a caged bird, and noted its weight loss between feeding times.[15]
Aristotle's inductive-deductive method used inductions from observations to infer general principles, deductions from those principles to check against further observations, and more cycles of induction and deduction to continue the advance of knowledge.[16]
TheOrganon (Greek:Ὄργανον, meaning "instrument, tool, organ") is the standard collection ofAristotle's six works onlogic. The nameOrganon was given by Aristotle's followers, thePeripatetics.The order of the works is not chronological (the chronology is now difficult to determine) but was deliberately chosen byTheophrastus to constitute a well-structured system.[citation needed] Indeed, parts of them seem to be a scheme of a lecture on logic. The arrangement of the works was made byAndronicus of Rhodes around 40 BCE.[17]
TheOrganon comprises the following six works:
Aristotle'sMetaphysics has some points of overlap with the works making up theOrganon but is not traditionally considered part of it; additionally there are works on logic attributed, with varying degrees of plausibility, to Aristotle that were not known to the Peripatetics.
Aristotle has been called the founder of modern science byDe Lacy O'Leary.[18] His demonstration method is found inPosterior Analytics. He provided another of the ingredients of scientific tradition:empiricism. For Aristotle, universal truths can be known from particular things via induction. To some extent then, Aristotle reconciles abstract thought with observation, although it would be a mistake to imply that Aristotelian science is empirical in form. Indeed, Aristotle did not accept that knowledge acquired by induction could rightly be counted as scientific knowledge. Nevertheless, induction was for him a necessary preliminary to the main business of scientific enquiry, providing the primary premises required for scientific demonstrations.
Aristotle largely ignored inductive reasoning in his treatment of scientific enquiry. To make it clear why this is so, consider this statement in thePosterior Analytics:
We suppose ourselves to possess unqualified scientific knowledge of a thing, as opposed to knowing it in the accidental way in which the sophist knows, when we think that we know the cause on which the fact depends, as the cause of that fact and of no other, and, further, that the fact could not be other than it is.
It was therefore the work of the philosopher to demonstrate universal truths and to discover their causes.[19] While induction was sufficient for discovering universals by generalization, it did not succeed in identifying causes. For this task Aristotle used the tool ofdeductive reasoning in the form ofsyllogisms. Using the syllogism, scientists could infer new universal truths from those already established.
Aristotle developed a complete normative approach to scientific inquiry involving the syllogism, which he discusses at length in hisPosterior Analytics. A difficulty with this scheme lay in showing that derived truths have solid primary premises. Aristotle would not allow that demonstrations could be circular (supporting the conclusion by the premises, and the premises by the conclusion). Nor would he allow an infinite number of middle terms between the primary premises and the conclusion. This leads to the question of how the primary premises are found or developed, and as mentioned above, Aristotle allowed that induction would be required for this task.
Towards the end of thePosterior Analytics, Aristotle discusses knowledge imparted by induction.
Thus it is clear that we must get to know the primary premises by induction; for the method by which even sense-perception implants the universal is inductive. [...] it follows that there will be no scientific knowledge of the primary premises, and since except intuition nothing can be truer than scientific knowledge, it will be intuition that apprehends the primary premises. [...] If, therefore, it is the only other kind of true thinking except scientific knowing,intuition will be the originative source of scientific knowledge.
The account leaves room for doubt regarding the nature and extent of Aristotle's empiricism. In particular, it seems that Aristotle considers sense-perception only as a vehicle for knowledge through intuition. He restricted his investigations in natural history to their natural settings,[20] such as at the Pyrrha lagoon,[21] now calledKalloni, atLesbos. Aristotle and Theophrastus together formulated the new science of biology,[22] inductively, case by case, for two years before Aristotle was called to tutorAlexander. Aristotle performed no modern-style experiments in the form in which they appear in today's physics and chemistry laboratories.[23]Induction is not afforded the status of scientific reasoning, and so it is left to intuition to provide a solid foundation for Aristotle's science. With that said, Aristotle brings us somewhat closer an empirical science than his predecessors.
In his work Kαvώv ('canon', a straight edge or ruler, thus any type of measure or standard, referred to as 'canonic'),Epicurus laid out his first rule for inquiry in physics: 'that thefirst concepts be seen,[24]: p.20 and that theynot require demonstration '.[24]: pp.35–47
His second rule for inquiry was that prior to an investigation,we are to have self-evident concepts,[24]: pp.61–80 so that we might infer [ἔχωμεν οἷς σημειωσόμεθα] both what is expected [τò προσμένον], and also what is non-apparent [τò ἄδηλον].[24]: pp.83–103
Epicurus applies his method of inference (the use of observations as signs, Asmis' summary, p. 333:the method of using the phenomena as signs (σημεῖα) of what is unobserved)[24]: pp.175–196 immediately to theatomic theory ofDemocritus. In Aristotle'sPrior Analytics, Aristotle himself employs the use of signs.[24]: pp.212–224 [25] But Epicurus presented his 'canonic' as rival to Aristotle's logic.[24]: pp.19–34 See:Lucretius (c. 99 BCE – c. 55 BCE)De rerum natura (On the nature of things) a didactic poem explaining Epicurus' philosophy and physics.
During theMiddle Ages issues of what is now termed science began to be addressed. There was greater emphasis on combining theory with practice in theIslamic world than there had been in Classical times, and it was common for those studying the sciences to be artisans as well, something that had been "considered an aberration in the ancient world." Islamic experts in the sciences were often expert instrument makers who enhanced their powers of observation and calculation with them.[26] Starting in the early ninth century,early Muslim scientists such asal-Kindi (801–873) and the authors writing under the name ofJābir ibn Hayyān (writings dated to c. 850–950) began to put a greater emphasis on the use of experiment as a source of knowledge.[27][28] Several scientific methods thus emerged from the medievalMuslim world by the early 11th century, all of which emphasized experimentation as well as quantification to varying degrees.
TheArab physicistIbn al-Haytham (Alhazen) used experimentation to obtain the results in hisBook of Optics (1021). He combinedobservations,experiments andrational arguments to support his intromission theory ofvision, in whichrays oflight are emitted from objects rather than from the eyes. He used similar arguments to show that the ancientemission theory of vision supported byPtolemy andEuclid (in which the eyes emit the rays of light used for seeing), and the ancientintromission theory supported byAristotle (where objects emit physical particles to the eyes), were both wrong.[30]
Experimental evidence supported most of the propositions in hisBook of Optics and grounded his theories of vision, light and colour, as well as his research in catoptrics and dioptrics. His legacy was elaborated through the 'reforming' of hisOptics byKamal al-Din al-Farisi (d. c. 1320) in the latter'sKitab Tanqih al-Manazir (The Revision of [Ibn al-Haytham's]Optics).[31][32]
Alhazen viewed his scientific studies as a search fortruth: "Truth is sought for its own sake. And those who are engaged upon the quest for anything for its own sake are not interested in other things. Finding the truth is difficult, and the road to it is rough. ...[33]
Alhazen's work included the conjecture that "Light travels through transparent bodies in straight lines only", which he was able to corroborate only after years of effort. He stated, "[This] is clearly observed in the lights which enter into dark rooms through holes. ... the entering light will be clearly observable in the dust which fills the air."[29] He also demonstrated the conjecture by placing a straight stick or a taut thread next to the light beam.[34]
Ibn al-Haytham also employedscientific skepticism and emphasized the role ofempiricism. He also explained the role ofinduction insyllogism, and criticizedAristotle for his lack of contribution to the method of induction, which Ibn al-Haytham regarded as superior to syllogism, and he considered induction to be the basic requirement for true scientific research.[35]
Something likeOccam's razor is also present in theBook of Optics. For example, after demonstrating that light is generated by luminous objects and emitted or reflected into the eyes, he states that therefore "theextramission of [visual] rays is superfluous and useless."[36] He may also have been the first scientist to adopt a form ofpositivism in his approach. He wrote that "we do not go beyond experience, and we cannot be content to use pure concepts in investigating natural phenomena", and that the understanding of these cannot be acquired without mathematics. After assuming that light is a material substance, he does not further discuss its nature but confines his investigations to the diffusion and propagation of light. The only properties of light he takes into account are those treatable by geometry and verifiable by experiment.[37]
ThePersian scientistAbū Rayhān al-Bīrūnī introduced early scientific methods for several different fields ofinquiry during the 1020s and 1030s. For example, in his treatise onmineralogy,Kitab al-Jawahir (Book of Precious Stones), al-Biruni is "the mostexact ofexperimental scientists", while in the introduction to hisstudy of India, he declares that "to execute our project, it has not been possible to follow the geometric method" and thus became one of the pioneers ofcomparative sociology in insisting on field experience and information.[38] He also developed an early experimental method formechanics.[39]
Al-Biruni's methods resembled the modern scientific method, particularly in his emphasis on repeated experimentation. Biruni was concerned with how to conceptualize and prevent bothsystematic errors and observational biases, such as "errors caused by the use of small instruments and errors made by human observers." He argued that if instruments produce errors because of their imperfections or idiosyncratic qualities, then multiple observations must be taken,analyzed qualitatively, and on this basis, arrive at a "common-sense single value for the constant sought", whether anarithmetic mean or a "reliableestimate."[40] In his scientific method, "universals came out of practical,experimental work" and "theories are formulated after discoveries", as withinductivism.[38]
In theOn Demonstration section ofThe Book of Healing (1027), thePersian philosopher and scientistAvicenna (Ibn Sina) discussedphilosophy of science and described an early scientific method of inquiry. He discussedAristotle'sPosterior Analytics and significantly diverged from it on several points. Avicenna discussed the issue of a proper procedure for scientific inquiry and the question of "How does one acquire the first principles of a science?" He asked how a scientist might find "the initialaxioms orhypotheses of adeductive science without inferring them from some more basic premises?" He explained that the ideal situation is when one grasps that a "relation holds between the terms, which would allow for absolute, universal certainty." Avicenna added two further methods for finding afirst principle: the ancientAristotelian method of induction (istiqra), and the more recent method ofexamination andexperimentation (tajriba). Avicenna criticized Aristotelian induction, arguing that "it does not lead to the absolute, universal, and certain premises that it purports to provide." In its place, he advocated "a method of experimentation as a means for scientific inquiry."[41]
Earlier, inThe Canon of Medicine (1025), Avicenna was also the first to describe what is essentiallymethods of agreement, difference and concomitant variation which are critical toinductive logic and the scientific method.[42][43][44] However, unlike his contemporary al-Biruni's scientific method, in which "universals came out of practical, experimental work" and "theories are formulated after discoveries", Avicenna developed a scientific procedure in which "general and universal questions came first and led to experimental work."[38] Due to the differences between their methods, al-Biruni referred to himself as a mathematicalscientist and to Avicenna as aphilosopher, during a debate between the two scholars.[45]
During the EuropeanRenaissance of the 12th century, ideas on scientific methodology, including Aristotle'sempiricism and theexperimental approaches of Alhazen and Avicenna, were introduced to medieval Europe viaLatin translations ofArabic andGreek texts and commentaries.[46]Robert Grosseteste's commentary on thePosterior Analytics places Grosseteste among the firstscholastic thinkers in Europe to understandAristotle's vision of the dual nature of scientific reasoning. Concluding from particular observations into a universal law, and then back again, from universal laws to prediction of particulars. Grosseteste called this "resolution and composition". Further, Grosseteste said that both paths should be verified through experimentation to verify the principles.[47]
WhileRoger Bacon was not a scientific man and did not undertake experiments himself, he was an excellent writer whose works encouraged those concepts.[48]: 48–49 About 1256 he joined theFranciscan Order and became subject to the Franciscan statute forbiddingFriars from publishing books or pamphlets without specific approval. After the accession of PopeClement IV in 1265, the Pope granted Bacon a special commission to write to him on scientific matters. In eighteen months he completed three large treatises, theOpus Majus,Opus Minus, andOpus Tertium which he sent to the Pope.[49]William Whewell has calledOpus Majus at once the Encyclopaedia and Organon of the 13th century.[50]
Aristotle's ideas became a framework for critical debate beginning with absorption of the Aristotelian texts into the university curriculum in the first half of the 13th century.[52] Contributing to this was the success of medieval theologians in reconciling Aristotelian philosophy with Christian theology. Within the sciences, medieval philosophers were not afraid of disagreeing with Aristotle on many specific issues, although their disagreements were stated within the language of Aristotelian philosophy. All medieval natural philosophers were Aristotelians, but "Aristotelianism" had become a somewhat broad and flexible concept. With the end of Middle Ages, theRenaissance rejection of medieval traditions coupled with an extreme reverence for classical sources led to a recovery of other ancient philosophical traditions, especially the teachings of Plato.[53] By the 17th century, those who clung dogmatically to Aristotle's teachings were faced with several competing approaches to nature.[54]
The discovery of the Americas at the close of the 15th century showed the scholars of Europe that new discoveries could be found outside of the authoritative works of Aristotle, Pliny, Galen, and other ancient writers.
Galen of Pergamon (129 – c. 200 AD) had studied with four schools in antiquity —Platonists,Aristotelians,Stoics, andEpicureans, and at Alexandria, the center of medicine at the time. In hisMethodus Medendi, Galen had synthesized the empirical and dogmatic schools of medicine into his own method, which was preserved by Arab scholars. After the translations from Arabic were critically scrutinized, a backlash occurred and demand arose in Europe for translations of Galen's medical text from the original Greek. Galen's method became very popular in Europe.Thomas Linacre, the teacher of Erasmus, thereupon translatedMethodus Medendi from Greek into Latin for a larger audience in 1519.[55] Limbrick 1988 notes that 630 editions, translations, and commentaries on Galen were produced in Europe in the 16th century, eventually eclipsing Arabic medicine there, and peaking in 1560, at the time of theScientific Revolution.[56]
By the late 15th century, the physician-scholarNiccolò Leoniceno was finding errors inPliny'sNatural History. As a physician, Leoniceno was concerned about these botanical errors propagating to themateria medica on which medicines were based.[57] To counter this, a botanical garden was established atOrto botanico di Padova, University of Padua (in use for teaching by 1546), in order that medical students might have empirical access to the plants of a pharmacopia. Other Renaissance teaching gardens were established, notably by the physicianLeonhart Fuchs, one of the founders ofbotany.[58]
The first printed work devoted to the concept of method is Jodocus Willichius,De methodo omnium artium et disciplinarum informanda opusculum (1550).An Informative Essay on the Method of All Arts and Disciplines (1550)[59]
In 1562Outlines of Pyrrhonism by the ancientPyrrhonist philosopherSextus Empiricus (c. 160–210 AD) was published in a Latin translation (from Greek), quickly placing thearguments of classical skepticism in the European mainstream. These arguments establish seemingly insurmountable challenges for the possibility ofcertain knowledge.
The skeptic philosopher and physicianFrancisco Sanches, was led by his medical training at Rome, 1571–73, to search for a true method of knowing (modus sciendi), as nothing clear can be known by the methods of Aristotle and his followers[60] — for example, 1) syllogism fails uponcircular reasoning; 2) Aristotle'smodal logic was not stated clearly enough for use in medieval times, and remains a research problem to this day.[61] Following the physician Galen'smethod of medicine, Sanches lists the methods of judgement and experience, which are faulty in the wrong hands,[62] and we are left with the bleak statementThat Nothing is Known (1581, in LatinQuod Nihil Scitur). This challenge was taken up by René Descartes in the next generation (1637), but at the least, Sanches warns us that we ought to refrain from the methods, summaries, and commentaries on Aristotle, if we seek scientific knowledge. In this, he is echoed by Francis Bacon who was influenced by another prominent exponent of skepticism,Montaigne; Sanches cites the humanistJuan Luis Vives who sought a better educational system, as well as a statement of human rights as a pathway for improvement of the lot of the poor.
"Sanches develops his scepticism by means of an intellectual critique of Aristotelianism, rather than by an appeal to the history of human stupidity and the variety and contrariety of previous theories." —Popkin 1979, p. 37, as cited bySanches, Limbrick & Thomson 1988, pp. 24–25
"To work, then; and if you know something, then teach me; I shall be extremely grateful to you. In the meantime, as I prepare to examineThings, I shall raise the question anything isknown, and if so, how, in the introductory passages of another book,[63] a book in which I will expound, as far as human frailty allows,[64] themethod of knowing. Farewell.
WHAT IS TAUGHT HAS NO MORE STRENGTH THAN IT DERIVES FROM HIM WHO IS TAUGHT.
WHAT?" —Francisco Sanches (1581)Quod Nihil Scitur p. 100[65]
Descartes' famous "Cogito" argument is an attempt to overcome skepticism and reestablish a foundation for certainty but other thinkers responded by revising what the search for knowledge, particularly physical knowledge, might be.
The first modern science, in which practitioners were prepared to revise or reject long-held beliefs in the light of new evidence, was astronomy, andTycho Brahe was the first modern astronomer.SeeSextant, right. Note the explicit reduction of geometrical diagrams to practice (real objects with actual lengths and angles).
In 1572, Tycho noticed a completelynew star that was brighter than any star or planet. Astonished by the existence of a star thatought not to have been there and gaining the patronage ofKing Frederick II of Denmark, Tycho built theUraniborg observatory at enormous cost. Over a period of fifteen years (1576–1591), Tycho and upwards of thirty assistants charted the positions of stars, planets, and other celestial bodies at Uraniborg with unprecedented accuracy. In 1600, Tycho hiredJohannes Kepler to assist him in analyzing and publishing his observations. Kepler later used Tycho's observations of the motion of Mars to deduce thelaws of planetary motion, which were later explained in terms ofNewton's law of universal gravitation.[66][67]
Besides Tycho's specific role in advancing astronomical knowledge, Tycho's single-minded pursuit of ever-more-accurate measurement was enormously influential in creating a modern scientific culture in which theory and evidence were understood to be inseparably linked.SeeSextant, right.
By 1723, standardunits of measure had spread to§ terrestrial mass and length.[d]
"If a man will begin with certainties, he shall end in doubts; but if he will be content to begin with doubts, he shall end in certainties." —Francis Bacon (1605)The Advancement of Learning, Book 1, v, 8
Francis Bacon (1561–1626) enteredTrinity College, Cambridge in April 1573, where he applied himself diligently to the several sciences as then taught, and came to the conclusion that the methods employed and the results attained were alike erroneous; he learned to despise the current Aristotelian philosophy. He believed philosophy must be taught its true purpose, and for this purpose a new method must be devised. With this conception in his mind, Bacon left the university.[51]
Bacon attempted to describe a rational procedure for establishing causation between phenomena based on induction. Bacon's induction was, however, radically different than that employed by the Aristotelians. As Bacon put it,
[A]nother form of induction must be devised than has hitherto been employed, and it must be used for proving and discovering not first principles (as they are called) only, but also the lesser axioms, and the middle, and indeed all. For the induction which proceeds by simple enumeration is childish. —Novum Organum section CV
Bacon's method relied on experimentalhistories to eliminate alternative theories.[69] Bacon explains how his method is applied in hisNovum Organum (published 1620). In an example he gives on the examination of the nature of heat, Bacon creates two tables, the first of which he names "Table of Essence and Presence", enumerating the many various circumstances under which we find heat. In the other table, labelled "Table of Deviation, or of Absence in Proximity", he lists circumstances which bear resemblance to those of the first table except for the absence of heat. From an analysis of what he calls thenatures (light emitting, heavy, colored, etc.) of the items in these lists we are brought to conclusions about theform nature, or cause, of heat. Those natures which are always present in the first table, but never in the second are deemed to be the cause of heat.
The role experimentation played in this process was twofold. The most laborious job of the scientist would be to gather the facts, or 'histories', required to create the tables of presence and absence. Such histories would document a mixture of common knowledge and experimental results. Secondly,experiments of light, or, as we might say,crucial experiments would be needed to resolve any remaining ambiguities over causes.
Bacon showed an uncompromising commitment toexperimentation. Despite this, he did not make any great scientific discoveries during his lifetime. This may be because he was not the most able experimenter.[70] It may also be becausehypothesising plays only a small role in Bacon's method compared to modern science.[71] Hypotheses, in Bacon's method, are supposed to emerge during the process of investigation, with the help of mathematics and logic. Bacon gave a substantial but secondary role to mathematics"which ought only to give definiteness to natural philosophy, not to generate or give it birth" (Novum Organum XCVI). An over-emphasis on axiomatic reasoning had rendered previous non-empirical philosophy impotent, in Bacon's view, which was expressed in hisNovum Organum:
XIX. There are and can be only two ways of searching into and discovering truth. The one flies from the senses and particulars to the most general axioms, and from these principles, the truth of which it takes for settled and immoveable, proceeds to judgment and to the discovery of middle axioms. And this way is now in fashion. The other derives axioms from the senses and particulars, rising by a gradual and unbroken ascent, so that it arrives at the most general axioms last of all. This is the true way, but as yet untried.
In Bacon'sutopian novel,TheNew Atlantis, the ultimate role is given for inductive reasoning:
Lastly, we have three that raise the former discoveries by experiments into greater observations, axioms, and aphorisms. These we call interpreters of nature.
In 1619,René Descartes began writing his first major treatise on proper scientific and philosophical thinking, the unfinishedRules for the Direction of the Mind. His aim was to create a complete science that he hoped would overthrow the Aristotelian system and establish himself as the sole architect[72] of a new system of guiding principles for scientific research.
This work was continued and clarified in his 1637 treatise,Discourse on Method, and in his 1641Meditations. Descartes describes the intriguing and disciplined thought experiments he used to arrive at the idea we instantly associate with him:I think therefore I am.
From this foundational thought, Descartes finds proof of the existence of a God who, possessing all possible perfections, will not deceive him provided he resolves "[...] never to accept anything for true which I did not clearly know to be such; that is to say, carefully to avoid precipitancy and prejudice, and to comprise nothing more in my judgment than what was presented to my mind so clearly and distinctly as to exclude all ground of methodic doubt."[73]
This rule allowed Descartes to progress beyond his own thoughts and judge that there exist extended bodies outside of his own thoughts. Descartes published seven sets of objections to theMeditations from various sources[74] along with his replies to them. Despite his apparent departure from the Aristotelian system, a number of his critics felt that Descartes had done little more than replace the primary premises of Aristotle with those of his own. Descartes says as much himself in a letter written in 1647 to the translator ofPrinciples of Philosophy,
a perfect knowledge [...] must necessarily be deduced from first causes [...] we must try to deduce from these principles knowledge of the things which depend on them, that there be nothing in the whole chain of deductions deriving from them that is not perfectly manifest.[75]
And again, some years earlier, speaking of Galileo's physics in a letter to his friend and criticMersenne from 1638,
without having considered the first causes of nature, [Galileo] has merely looked for the explanations of a few particular effects, and he has thereby built without foundations.[76]
Whereas Aristotle purported to arrive at his first principles by induction, Descartes believed he could obtain them using reason only. In this sense, he was a Platonist, as he believed in the innate ideas, as opposed to Aristotle'sblank slate (tabula rasa), and stated that the seeds of science are inside us.[77]
Unlike Bacon, Descartes successfully applied his own ideas in practice. He made significant contributions to science, in particular in aberration-corrected optics. His work inanalytic geometry was a necessary precedent todifferential calculus and instrumental in bringing mathematical analysis to bear on scientific matters.
During the period of religious conservatism brought about by theReformation andCounter-Reformation,Galileo Galilei unveiled his new science of motion. Neither the contents of Galileo's science, nor the methods of study he selected were in keeping with Aristotelian teachings. Whereas Aristotle thought that a science should be demonstrated from first principles, Galileo had used experiments as a research tool. Galileo nevertheless presented his treatise in the form of mathematical demonstrations without reference to experimental results. It is important to understand that this in itself was a bold and innovative step in terms of scientific method. The usefulness of mathematics in obtaining scientific results was far from obvious.[78] This is because mathematics did not lend itself to the primary pursuit of Aristotelian science: the discovery of causes.
Whether it is because Galileo was realistic about the acceptability of presenting experimental results as evidence or because he himself had doubts about theepistemological status of experimental findings is not known. Nevertheless, it is not in hisLatin treatise on motion that we find reference to experiments, but in his supplementary dialogues written in the Italian vernacular. In these dialogues experimental results are given, although Galileo may have found them inadequate for persuading his audience.Thought experiments showing logical contradictions in Aristotelian thinking, presented in the skilled rhetoric of Galileo's dialogue were further enticements for the reader.
As an example, in the dramatic dialogue titledThird Day from hisTwo New Sciences, Galileo has the characters of the dialogue discuss an experiment involving two free falling objects of differing weight. An outline of the Aristotelian view is offered by the character Simplicio. For this experiment he expects that "a body which is ten times as heavy as another will move ten times as rapidly as the other". The character Salviati, representing Galileo's persona in the dialogue, replies by voicing his doubt that Aristotle ever attempted the experiment. Salviati then asks the two other characters of the dialogue to consider a thought experiment whereby two stones of differing weights are tied together before being released. Following Aristotle, Salviati reasons that "the more rapid one will be partly retarded by the slower, and the slower will be somewhat hastened by the swifter". But this leads to a contradiction, since the two stones together make a heavier object than either stone apart, the heavier object should in fact fall with a speed greater than that of either stone. From this contradiction, Salviati concludes that Aristotle must, in fact, be wrong and the objects will fall at the same speed regardless of their weight, a conclusion that is borne out by experiment.
In his 1991 survey of developments in the modern accumulation of knowledge such as this, Charles Van Doren[79] considers that the Copernican Revolution really is the Galilean Cartesian (René Descartes) or simply the Galilean revolution on account of the courage and depth of change brought about by the work of Galileo.
Both Bacon and Descartes wanted to provide a firm foundation for scientific thought that avoided the deceptions of the mind and senses. Bacon envisaged that foundation as essentially empirical, whereas Descartes provides a metaphysical foundation for knowledge. If there were any doubts about the direction in which scientific method would develop, they were set to rest by the success ofIsaac Newton. Implicitly rejecting Descartes' emphasis onrationalism in favor of Bacon's empirical approach, he outlines his four "rules of reasoning" in thePrincipia,
- We are to admit no more causes of natural things than such as are both true and sufficient to explain their appearances.
- Therefore to the same natural effects we must, as far as possible, assign the same causes.
- The qualities of bodies, which admit neither intension nor remission of degrees, and which are found to belong to all bodies within the reach of our experiments, are to be esteemed the universal qualities of all bodies whatsoever.
- In experimental philosophy we are to look upon propositions collected by general induction from phænomena as accurately or very nearly true, notwithstanding any contrary hypotheses that may be imagined, until such time as other phænomena occur, by which they may either be made more accurate, or liable to exceptions.[80]
But Newton also left an admonition about atheory of everything:
To explain all nature is too difficult a task for any one man or even for any one age. 'Tis much better to do a little with certainty, and leave the rest for others that come after you, than to explain all things.[81]
Newton's work became a model that other sciences sought to emulate, and his inductive approach formed the basis for much of natural philosophy through the 18th and early 19th centuries. Some methods of reasoning were later systematized byMill's Methods (or Mill's canon), which are five explicit statements of what can be discarded and what can be kept while building a hypothesis.George Boole andWilliam Stanley Jevons also wrote on the principles of reasoning.
Attempts to systematize a scientific method were confronted in the mid-18th century by theproblem of induction, apositivist logic formulation which, in short, asserts that nothing can be known with certainty except what is actually observed.David Hume took empiricism to the skeptical extreme; among his positions was that there is no logical necessity that the future should resemble the past, thus we are unable to justify inductive reasoning itself by appealing to its past success. Hume's arguments, of course, came on the heels of many, many centuries of excessive speculation upon excessive speculation not grounded in empirical observation and testing. Many of Hume's radically skeptical arguments were argued against, but not resolutely refuted, byImmanuel Kant'sCritique of Pure Reason in the late 18th century.[82] Hume's arguments continue to hold a strong lingering influence and certainly on the consciousness of the educated classes for the better part of the 19th century when the argument at the time became the focus on whether or not the inductive method was valid.
Hans Christian Ørsted, (Ørsted is theDanish spelling;Oersted in other languages) (1777–1851) was heavily influenced by Kant, in particular, Kant'sMetaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft (Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science).[83] The following sections on Ørsted encapsulate our current, common view ofscientific method. His work appeared in Danish, most accessibly in public lectures, which he translated into German, French, English, and occasionally Latin. But some of his views go beyond Kant:
Ørsted's "First Introduction to General Physics" (1811) exemplified the steps ofobservation,[85]hypothesis,[86]deduction[87] and experiment. In 1805, based on his researches onelectromagnetism Ørsted came to believe that electricity is propagated by undulatory action (i.e., fluctuation). By 1820, he felt confident enough in his beliefs that he resolved to demonstrate them in a public lecture, and in fact observed a small magnetic effect from a galvanic circuit (i.e., voltaic circuit),without rehearsal;[88][89]
In 1831John Herschel (1792–1871) publishedA Preliminary Discourse on the study of Natural Philosophy, setting out the principles of science. Measuring and comparing observations was to be used to find generalisations in "empirical laws", which described regularities in phenomena, then natural philosophers were to work towards the higher aim of finding a universal "law of nature" which explained the causes and effects producing such regularities. An explanatory hypothesis was to be found by evaluating true causes (Newton's "vera causae") derived from experience, for example evidence of past climate change could be due to changes in the shape of continents, or to changes in Earth's orbit. Possible causes could be inferred by analogy to known causes of similar phenomena.[90][91] It was essential to evaluate the importance of a hypothesis; "our next step in the verification of an induction must, therefore, consist in extending its application to cases not originally contemplated; in studiously varying the circumstances under which our causes act, with a view to ascertain whether their effect is general; and in pushing the application of our laws to extreme cases."[92]
William Whewell (1794–1866) regarded hisHistory of the Inductive Sciences, from the Earliest to the Present Time (1837) to be an introduction to thePhilosophy of the Inductive Sciences (1840) which analyzes the method exemplified in the formation of ideas. Whewell attempts to follow Bacon's plan for discovery of an effectual art of discovery. He named thehypothetico-deductive method (whichEncyclopædia Britannica credits to Newton[93]); Whewell also coined the termscientist. Whewell examines ideas and attempts to construct science by uniting ideas to facts. He analyses induction into three steps:
Upon these follow special techniques applicable for quantity, such as themethod of least squares,curves,means, and special methods depending on resemblance (such aspattern matching, the method of gradation, and the method of natural classification (such ascladistics).But no art of discovery, such as Bacon anticipated, follows, for "invention,sagacity,genius" are needed at every step.[94] Whewell's sophisticated concept of science had similarities to that shown by Herschel, and he considered that a good hypothesis should connect fields that had previously been thought unrelated, a process he calledconsilience. However, where Herschel held that theorigin of new biological species would be found in a natural rather than a miraculous process, Whewell opposed this and considered that no natural cause had been shown foradaptation so an unknowndivine cause was appropriate.[90]
John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) was stimulated to publishA System of Logic (1843) upon reading Whewell'sHistory of the Inductive Sciences. Mill may be regarded as the final exponent of the empirical school of philosophy begun byJohn Locke, whose fundamental characteristic is the duty incumbent upon all thinkers to investigate for themselves rather than to accept the authority of others. Knowledge must be based on experience.[95]
In the mid-19th centuryClaude Bernard was also influential, especially in bringing the scientific method to medicine. In his discourse on scientific method,An Introduction to the Study of Experimental Medicine (1865), he described what makes a scientific theory good and what makes a scientist a true discoverer. Unlike many scientific writers of his time, Bernard wrote about his own experiments and thoughts, and used the first person.[96]
William Stanley Jevons'The Principles of Science: a treatise on logic and scientific method (1873, 1877) Chapter XII "The Inductive or Inverse Method", Summary of the Theory of Inductive Inference, states "Thus there are but three steps in the process of induction :-
Jevons then frames those steps in terms of probability, which he then applied to economic laws.Ernest Nagel notes that Jevons and Whewell were not the first writers to argue for the centrality of thehypothetico-deductive method in the logic of science.[97]
In the late 19th century,Charles Sanders Peirce proposed a schema that would turn out to have considerable influence in the further development of scientific method generally. Peirce's work quickly accelerated the progress on several fronts. Firstly, speaking in broader context in "How to Make Our Ideas Clear" (1878),[98] Peirce outlined an objectively verifiable method to test the truth of putative knowledge on a way that goes beyond mere foundational alternatives, focusing upon bothDeduction andInduction. He thus placed induction and deduction in a complementary rather than competitive context (the latter of which had been the primary trend at least sinceDavid Hume a century before). Secondly, and of more direct importance to scientific method, Peirce put forth the basic schema for hypothesis-testing that continues to prevail today. Extracting the theory of inquiry from its raw materials in classical logic, he refined it in parallel with the early development of symbolic logic to address the then-current problems in scientific reasoning. Peirce examined and articulated the three fundamental modes of reasoning that play a role in scientific inquiry today, the processes that are currently known asabductive,deductive, andinductive inference. Thirdly, he played a major role in the progress of symbolic logic itself – indeed this was his primary specialty.
Charles S. Peirce was also a pioneer instatistics. Peirce held that science achieves statistical probabilities, not certainties, and that chance, a veering from law, is very real. He assigned probability to an argument's conclusion rather than to a proposition, event, etc., as such. Most of his statistical writings promote thefrequency interpretation of probability (objective ratios of cases), and many of his writings express skepticism about (and criticize the use of)probability when such models are not based on objectiverandomization.[99] Though Peirce was largely a frequentist, hispossible world semantics introduced the "propensity" theory of probability. Peirce (sometimes withJastrow) investigated theprobability judgments of experimental subjects, pioneeringdecision analysis.
Peirce was one of thefounders of statistics. He formulated modern statistics in "Illustrations of the Logic of Science" (1877–1878) and "A Theory of Probable Inference" (1883). With arepeated measures design, he introducedblinded,controlled randomized experiments (beforeFisher). He invented anoptimal design for experiments on gravity, in which he "corrected the means". He usedlogistic regression,correlation, andsmoothing, and improved the treatment ofoutliers. He introduced terms "confidence" and "likelihood" (beforeNeyman andFisher). (See the historical books ofStephen Stigler.) Many of Peirce's ideas were later popularized and developed byRonald A. Fisher,Jerzy Neyman,Frank P. Ramsey,Bruno de Finetti, andKarl Popper.
Karl Popper (1902–1994) is generally credited with providing major improvements in the understanding of the scientific method in the mid-to-late 20th century. In 1934 Popper publishedThe Logic of Scientific Discovery, which repudiated the by then traditional observationalist-inductivist account of the scientific method. He advocated empiricalfalsifiability as the criterion for distinguishing scientific work fromnon-science. According to Popper, scientific theory should make predictions (preferably predictions not made by a competing theory) which can be tested and the theory rejected if these predictions are shown not to be correct. Following Peirce and others, he argued that science would best progress using deductive reasoning as its primary emphasis, known ascritical rationalism. His astute formulations of logical procedure helped to rein in the excessive use of inductive speculation upon inductive speculation, and also helped to strengthen the conceptual foundations for today'speer review procedures.[citation needed]
Ludwik Fleck, a Polish epidemiologist who was contemporary with Karl Popper but who influenced Kuhn and others with hisGenesis and Development of a Scientific Fact (in German 1935, English 1979). Before Fleck, scientific fact was thought to spring fully formed (in the view ofMax Jammer, for example), when a gestation period is now recognized to be essential before acceptance of a phenomenon as fact.[100]
Critics of Popper, chieflyThomas Kuhn,Paul Feyerabend andImre Lakatos, rejected the idea that there exists asingle method that applies to all science and could account for its progress. In 1962 Kuhn published the influential bookThe Structure of Scientific Revolutions which suggested that scientists worked within a series of paradigms, and argued there was little evidence of scientists actually following a falsificationist methodology. Kuhn quotedMax Planck who had said in his autobiography, "a new scientific truth does not triumph by convincing its opponents and making them see the light, but rather because its opponents eventually die, and a new generation grows up that is familiar with it."[101]
A well quoted source on the subject of the scientific method and statistical models,George E. P. Box (1919–2013) wrote "Since all models are wrong the scientist cannot obtain a correct one by excessive elaboration. On the contrary following William of Occam he should seek an economical description of natural phenomena. Just as the ability to devise simple but evocative models is the signature of the great scientist, so over-elaboration and over-parameterization is often the mark of mediocrity" and "Since all models are wrong the scientist must be alert to what is importantly wrong. It is inappropriate to be concerned about mice when there are tigers abroad."[102]
These debates clearly show that there is no universal agreement as to what constitutesthe "scientific method".[103] There remain, nonetheless, certaincore principles that are the foundation of scientific inquiry today.[104]
InQuod Nihil Scitur (1581),Francisco Sanches refers to another book title,De modo sciendi (on the method of knowing). This work appeared in Spanish asMétodo universal de las ciencias.[64]
In 1833Robert andWilliam Chambers published their 'Chambers's information for the people'. Under the rubric 'Logic' we find a description of investigation that is familiar as scientific method,
Investigation, or the art of inquiring into the nature of causes and their operation, is a leading characteristic of reason [...] Investigation implies three things – Observation, Hypothesis, and Experiment [...] The first step in the process, it will be perceived, is to observe...[105]
In 1885, the words "Scientific method" appear together with a description of the method inFrancis Ellingwood Abbot's 'Scientific Theism',
Now all the established truths which are formulated in the multifarious propositions of science have been won by the use of Scientific Method. This method consists in essentially three distinct steps (1) observation and experiment, (2) hypothesis, (3) verification by fresh observation and experiment.[106]
The Eleventh Edition ofEncyclopædia Britannica did not include an article on scientific method; the Thirteenth Edition listed scientific management, but not method. By the Fifteenth Edition, a 1-inch article in theMicropædia of Britannica was part of the 1975 printing, while a fuller treatment (extending across multiple articles, and accessible mostly via the index volumes of Britannica) was available in later printings.[107]
In the past few centuries,some statistical methods have been developed, for reasoning in the face of uncertainty, as an outgrowth of methods for eliminating error. This was an echo of the program of Francis Bacon'sNovum Organum of 1620.Bayesian inference acknowledges one's ability to alter one's beliefs in the face of evidence. This has been calledbelief revision, ordefeasible reasoning: the models in play during the phases of scientific method can be reviewed, revisited and revised, in the light of further evidence. This arose from the work ofFrank P. Ramsey[108](1903–1930), ofJohn Maynard Keynes[109](1883–1946), and earlier, ofWilliam Stanley Jevons[110][111] (1835–1882) in economics.
The question of howscience operates and therefore how todistinguish genuine science frompseudoscience has importance well beyond scientific circles or the academic community. In thejudicial system and inpublic policy controversies, for example, a study's deviation fromaccepted scientific practice is grounds for rejecting it asjunk science or pseudoscience. However, the high public perception of science means that pseudoscience is widespread. An advertisement in which an actor wears a white coat and product ingredients are given Greek or Latin sounding names is intended to give the impression of scientific endorsement.Richard Feynman has likened pseudoscience tocargo cults in which many of the external forms are followed, but the underlying basis is missing: that is, fringe or alternative theories often present themselves with a pseudoscientific appearance to gain acceptance.[112]
"In reforming optics he, as it were, adoptedpositivism (before the term was invented): we do not go beyond experience, and we cannot be content to use pure concepts in investigating natural phenomena. Understanding of these cannot be acquired without mathematics. Thus, once he has assumed light is a material substance, Ibn al-Haytham does not discuss its nature further, but confines himself to considering its propagation and diffusion. In his opticsthe smallest parts of light, as he calls them, retain only properties that can be treated by geometry and verified by experiment; they lack all sensible qualities except energy."
"Using a whole body of mathematical methods (not only those inherited from the antique theory of ratios and infinitesimal techniques, but also the methods of the contemporary algebra and fine calculation techniques), Arabic scientists raised statics to a new, higher level. The classical results of Archimedes in the theory of the centre of gravity were generalized and applied to three-dimensional bodies, the theory of ponderable lever was founded and the 'science of gravity' was created and later further developed in medieval Europe. The phenomena of statics were studied by using the dynamic approach so that two trends – statics and dynamics – turned out to be inter-related within a single science, mechanics. The combination of the dynamic approach with Archimedean hydrostatics gave birth to a direction in science which may be called medieval hydrodynamics. [...] Numerous fine experimental methods were developed for determining the specific weight, which were based, in particular, on the theory of balances and weighing. The classical works of al-Biruni and al-Khazini can by right be considered as the beginning of the application of experimental methods inmedieval science."
The scientific method 'is often misrepresented as a fixed sequence of steps,' rather than being seen for what it truly is, 'a highly variable and creative process' (AAAS 2000:18). The claim here is that science has general principles that must be mastered to increase productivity and enhance perspective, not that these principles provide a simple and automated sequence of steps to follow.
{{citation}}
: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link) Critical edition of Sanches'Quod Nihil Scitur Latin: (1581, 1618, 1649, 1665), Portuguese: (1948, 1955, 1957), Spanish: (1944, 1972), French: (1976, 1984), German: (2007)