Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Jump to content
WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
Search

Exhaustivity

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Semantic interpretations of language

Inlinguistics,exhaustivity is the phenomenon where aproposition can be strengthened with thenegation of certain alternatives. For example, in response to the question "Which students got an A?", the utterance "Ava got an A" has anexhaustive interpretation when it conveys that no other students got an A. It has anon-exhaustive interpretation when it merely conveys that Ava was among the students who got an A.

Exhaustivity is a major topic in the linguistic subfields ofsemantics andpragmatics. Research on the topic aims to explain when and why expressions receive exhaustive interpretations. Particular factors includefocus,[1]disjunction,[2]questions,[3] andpolarity items.[4] A major theoretical issue is whether exhaustivity is a semanticentailment encoded in thegrammar, a pragmaticimplicature arising fromGriceansocial cognition, or some combination of the two.[5][6][7][8]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^Rooth 1992;Rooth 2016.
  2. ^Chierchia, Fox & Spector 2012;Chierchia 2004;Fox 2007.
  3. ^Karttunen & Peters 1979.
  4. ^Krifka 1995;Chierchia 2013.
  5. ^Grice 1975.
  6. ^Chierchia, Fox & Spector 2012;Chierchia 2013, pp. 100–33.
  7. ^Karttunen & Peters 1979;Krifka 1993.
  8. ^Krifka 1993;Chierchia, Fox & Spector 2012;Rooth 2016;Spector 2016.

Bibliography

[edit]
  • Chierchia, Gennaro (2004). "Scalar implicature, polarity phenomena, and the syntax/pragmatics interface". In Belleti, Adriana (ed.).Structures and Beyond. Oxford University Press. pp. 39–103.
  • Chierchia, Gennaro (2013).Logic in grammar: Polarity, Free choice, and Intervention. Oxford University Press.
  • Chierchia, Gennaro; Fox, Danny; Spector, Benjamin (2012). "Scalar implicature as a grammatical phenomenon". In von Heusinger, Klaus; Maienborn, Claudia; Portner, Paul (eds.).Handbook of semantics. Vol. 3. Mouten de Gruyter. pp. 2297–2331. Archived fromthe original on April 5, 2022.
  • Fox, Danny (2007). "Free choice and the theory of scalar implicatures". In Sauerland, Uli; Stateva, Penka (eds.).Presupposition and implicature in compositional semantics. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 537–586.doi:10.1093/jos/10.4.269.
  • Grice, H.P. (1975). "Logic and Conversation". In Cole, P.; Morgan, J. (eds.).Syntax and Semantics. Vol. 3.
  • Karttunen, L.; Peters, S. (1979). "Conventional implicature". In Oh, C.-K.; Dinneen, D. A. (eds.).Presupposition. New York: Academic Press.
  • Krifka, Manfred (1993). "Focus and presupposition in dynamic interpretation".Journal of Semantics.10 (4):269–300.doi:10.1093/jos/10.4.269.
  • Krifka, Manfred (1995). "The semantics and pragmatics of polarity items".Linguistic Analysis.24: 209=257.
  • Rooth, Mats (1992). "A theory of focus interpretation".Natural Language Semantics.1 (1):75–116.doi:10.1007/BF02342617.S2CID 14108349.
  • Rooth, Mats (2016). "Alternative semantics". In Féry, Caroline; Ishihara, Shinichiro (eds.).The Oxford Handbook of Information Structure. Oxford University Press.doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199642670.013.19.
  • Spector, Benjamin (2016)."Comparing exhaustivity operators".Semantics and Pragmatics.9 (11):1–13.doi:10.3765/sp.9.11.
Stub icon

Thisgrammar-related article is astub. You can help Wikipedia byexpanding it.

Central concepts
Topics
Areas
Phenomena
Formalism
Formal systems
Concepts
See also
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Exhaustivity&oldid=1280399748"
Categories:
Hidden categories:

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp