Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Jump to content
WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
Search

Diodorus Cronus

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
For other people named Diodorus, seeDiodorus (disambiguation).
This articlerelies excessively onreferences toprimary sources. Please improve this article by addingsecondary or tertiary sources.
Find sources: "Diodorus Cronus" – news ·newspapers ·books ·scholar ·JSTOR
(January 2023) (Learn how and when to remove this message)

Diodorus Cronus (Greek:Διόδωρος Κρόνος; died c. 284 BC)[1] was aGreekphilosopher anddialectician connected to theMegarian school. He was most notable for logic innovations, including his master argument formulated in response toAristotle's discussion offuture contingents.

Life

[edit]

Diodorus was the son of Ameinias ofIasus inCaria. He lived in the court ofAlexandria in the reign ofPtolemy I Soter, who is said to have given him the surname of Cronus ("old fogey"[2]) on account of his inability to solve at once somedialectic problem proposed byStilpo, when the two philosophers were dining with the king. Diodorus is said to have taken that disgrace so much to heart that after his return from the meal, and writing a treatise on the problem, he died in despair.[3] However, according toStrabo,[4] Diodorus himself adopted the surname of Cronus from his teacher,Apollonius Cronus. Diodorus is thought to have died around 284 BC; his date of birth is unknown.[2] It was once thought that he was old enough to have influencedAristotle (384–322 BC), but there is no strong evidence for this.[2]

Diodorus was particularly celebrated for his great dialectic skill, for which he was calledThe Dialectician.[5] This effectively became his surname, and descended even to his five daughters, Menexene, Argia, Theognis, Artemesia, and Pantaclea, who were likewise distinguished as dialecticians.[6] His pupils includedPhilo the Dialectician, andZeno of Citium—the founder of theStoic school. Although influenced by theMegarian school it is not clear how closely Diodorus and his fellow dialecticians were connected to that particular philosophical school.[2][7]

Philosophy

[edit]

He was most notable for logic innovations, including his master argument formulated in response toAristotle's discussion offuture contingents.Diogenes Laërtius says that Diodorus also made use of theSorites paradox, and is said to have invented two others of the same kind, viz.The Masked Man andThe Horns, which are, however, also ascribed toEubulides.[3] Aulus Gellius claims that he also rejected the view that words are ambiguous, any uncertainty in understanding was always due to speakers expressing themselves obscurely.[8] According to Sextus Empiricus,[9] he also maintained that space was indivisible, and consequently that motion was impossible. He further denied the coming into existence and all multiplicity both in time and in space; but he considered the things that fill up space as one whole composed of an infinite number of indivisible particles.[better source needed]

Master argument

[edit]
See also:Problem of future contingents

Aristotle, in his workOn Interpretation, had wrestled with theproblem of future contingents.[10] In particular, whether one can meaningfully regard futurecontingents as true or false now, if the future is open; and, if so: how?[10]

In response, Diodorus maintained that possible was identical with necessary (i.e., not contingent); so that the future is as certain and defined as the past.[11]Alexander of Aphrodisias[12] tells us that Diodorus believed that that alone is possible which either is happening now, or will happen at some future time. When speaking about facts of an unrecorded past, we know that a given fact either occurred, or did not occur—without knowing which of the two is true; therefore, we affirm only that the factmay have occurred. So too about the future: either the assertion that a given fact will—at some time—occur, or else the assertion that it willnever occur, is positively true; the assertion that itmay or may not occur, at some time or another, represents only our ignorance as to which of the two is true.[11] That which willnever at any time occur is, in a word, impossible.[11]

Diodorus went on to formulate an argument that became known as themaster argument[13] orruling argument (Greek:ὁ κυριεύων λόγος /ho kurieuôn logos). The most succinct description of it is provided byEpictetus:

The argument called the master argument appears to have been proposed from such principles as these: there is in fact a common contradiction between one another in these three propositions, each two being in contradiction to the third. The propositions are: (1) every past truth must be necessary; (2) that an impossibility does not follow a possibility; (3) something is possible which neither is nor will be true. Diodorus observing this contradiction employed the probative force of the first two for the demonstration of this proposition: That nothing is possible which is not true and never will be.[14]

Epictetus' description of the master argument is not in the form as it would have been presented by Diodorus, which makes it difficult to know the precise nature of his argument. To modern logicians, it is not obvious why these three premises are inconsistent, or why the first two should lead to the rejection of the third.[15] Modern interpretations therefore assume that there must have been extra premises in the argument tacitly assumed by Diodorus and his contemporaries.[16]

One possible reconstruction is as follows:[17] For Diodorus, if a future event is not going to happen, then it was true in the past that it would not happen. Since every past truth is necessary (proposition 1), it was necessary that in the past it would not happen. Since the impossible cannot follow from the possible (proposition 2), it must have always been impossible for the event to occur. Therefore if something will not be true, it will never be possible for it to be true, and thus proposition 3 is shown to be false.

Epictetus goes on to point out thatPanthoides,Cleanthes, andAntipater of Tarsus made use of the second and third proposition to demonstrate that the first proposition was false.Chrysippus, on the other hand, agreed with Diodorus that everything true as an event in the past is necessary, but attacked Diodorus' view that the possible must be either what is true or what will be true.[18][19] He thus made use of the first and third proposition to demonstrate that the second proposition was false.[20]

Nom de plume

[edit]

During the 1960s and 1970s the philosopherRichard Clyde Taylor also coauthored several articles under the nom de plume ofDiodorus Cronus which included:"Time, Truth and Ability" (Analysis, 1965) and"The Necessity of Everything That One Does" (The Southern Journal of Philosophy,1971).[21][22]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^Dorandi 1999, p. 52.
  2. ^abcdSedley, David."Diodorus Cronus". InZalta, Edward N. (ed.).Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  3. ^abLaërtius 1925, § 111.
  4. ^Strabo, xiv., xvii.
  5. ^Strabo, xiv., xvii.; Sextus Empiricus,adv. Gram. i.; Pliny,Hist. Nat. vii. 54.
  6. ^Clement of Alexandria,Stromata, iv. 19
  7. ^Bobzien, Susanne."Dialectical School". InZalta, Edward N. (ed.).Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  8. ^Aulus Gellius, xi. 12
  9. ^Sextus Empiricus,Adv. Math., x. 85–118
  10. ^abØhrstrøm, Peter; Hasle, Per."Future Contingents". InZalta, Edward N. (ed.).Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  11. ^abcGeorge Grote, (1888),Plato, and the other companions of Sokrates, Volume 3, page 501
  12. ^Alexander of Aphrodisias,In An. Pr. 183-4
  13. ^Not to be confused withGeorge Berkeley'smaster argument.
  14. ^Epictetus,Discourses, ii.19.1-4
  15. ^William Kneale, Martha Kneale, (1962),The Development of Logic, page 119, Clarendon Press
  16. ^Richard Gaskin, (1995),The sea battle and the master argument: Aristotle and Diodorus on the metaphysics of the future, page 219. Walter de Gruyter
  17. ^Robert Dobbin, (2008),Discourses and Selected Writings, page 263. Penguin Classics
  18. ^Cicero,de Fato, 6, 7, 9,ad Fam. ix. 4; Epictetus,Discourses, ii. 19.2-5
  19. ^Josiah B. Gould,The Philosophy of Chrysippus, pages 77-8. SUNY Press.
  20. ^Epictetus,Discourses, ii.19.2-5
  21. ^Correcting the Scholarly Record for Research Integrity Dougherty, M.V. Springer International Publishing 2018 p. 32-33 ISBN 9783319994352 Richard Taylor and Diodous Cronus on Google Books
  22. ^Cronus, Diodorus (1965). "Time, Truth and Ability".Analysis.25 (4):137–141.JSTOR 3326340.

References

[edit]

Further reading

[edit]
  • Gaskin, Richard,The Sea-Battle and the Master Argument. Aristotle and Diodorus Cronus on the Metaphysics of the Future. Berlin, Walter de Gruyter, 1995.
  • Sedley, David.Diodorus Cronus and Hellenistic Philosophy. Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society 203, N.S. 23 (1977), P. 74-120.
  • Vuillemin, Jules.Nécessité ou contingence. L'aporie de Diodore et les systèmes philosophiques. Paris 1984. (English translation:Necessity or Contingency. The Master Argument, Stanford: CSLI Publications, 1996.ISBN 1-881526-86-0, paperbackISBN 1-881526-85-2).

External links

[edit]
Megarian school
Dialectical school
International
National
People
Other
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Diodorus_Cronus&oldid=1273105088"
Categories:
Hidden categories:

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp