Generalization of games used in game theory
Acontinuous game is a mathematical concept, used ingame theory, that generalizes the idea of an ordinary game like tic-tac-toe (noughts and crosses) or checkers (draughts). In other words, it extends the notion of a discrete game, where the players choose from a finite set of pure strategies. The continuous game concepts allows games to include more general sets of pure strategies, which may beuncountably infinite.
In general, a game with uncountably infinite strategy sets will not necessarily have aNash equilibrium solution. If, however, the strategy sets are required to becompact and the utility functionscontinuous, then a Nash equilibrium will be guaranteed; this is by Glicksberg's generalization of theKakutani fixed point theorem. The class of continuous games is for this reason usually defined and studied as a subset of the larger class of infinite games (i.e. games with infinite strategy sets) in which the strategy sets are compact and the utility functions continuous.
Define then-player continuous game
where
is the set of
players,
where each
is acompact set, in ametric space, corresponding to the
th player's set of pure strategies,
where
is the utility function of player
- We define
to be the set of Borelprobability measures on
, giving us the mixed strategy space of playeri. - Define the strategy profile
where
Let
be a strategy profile of all players except for player
. As with discrete games, we can define abest responsecorrespondence for player
,
.
is a relation from the set of all probability distributions over opponent player profiles to a set of player
's strategies, such that each element of

is a best response to
. Define
.
A strategy profile
is aNash equilibrium if and only if
The existence of a Nash equilibrium for any continuous game with continuous utility functions can be proven usingIrving Glicksberg's generalization of theKakutani fixed point theorem.[1] In general, there may not be a solution if we allow strategy spaces,
's which are not compact, or if we allow non-continuous utility functions.
Aseparable game is a continuous game where, for any i, the utility function
can be expressed in the sum-of-products form:
, where
,
,
, and the functions
are continuous.
Apolynomial game is a separable game where each
is a compact interval on
and each utility function can be written as a multivariate polynomial.
In general, mixed Nash equilibria of separable games are easier to compute than non-separable games as implied by the following theorem:
- For any separable game there exists at least one Nash equilibrium where playeri mixes at most
pure strategies.[2]
Whereas an equilibrium strategy for a non-separable game may require anuncountably infinitesupport, a separable game is guaranteed to have at least one Nash equilibrium with finitely supported mixed strategies.
Consider a zero-sum 2-player game between playersX andY, with
. Denote elements of
and
as
and
respectively. Define the utility functions
where
.
The pure strategy best response relations are:
![{\displaystyle b_{X}(y)={\begin{cases}1,&{\mbox{if }}y\in \left[0,1/2\right)\\0{\text{ or }}1,&{\mbox{if }}y=1/2\\0,&{\mbox{if }}y\in \left(1/2,1\right]\end{cases}}}](/image.pl?url=https%3a%2f%2fwikimedia.org%2fapi%2frest_v1%2fmedia%2fmath%2frender%2fsvg%2fd2a9e41248021569d55075ae9ad5c94aac90a01d&f=jpg&w=240)

and
do not intersect, so there is no pure strategy Nash equilibrium.However, there should be a mixed strategy equilibrium. To find it, express the expected value,
as alinear combination of the first and secondmoments of the probability distributions ofX andY:

(where
and similarly forY).
The constraints on
and
(with similar constraints fory,) are given byHausdorff as:

Each pair of constraints defines a compact convex subset in the plane. Since
is linear, any extrema with respect to a player's first two moments will lie on the boundary of this subset. Player i's equilibrium strategy will lie on

Note that the first equation only permits mixtures of 0 and 1 whereas the second equation only permits pure strategies. Moreover, if the best response at a certain point to player i lies on
, it will lie on the whole line, so that both 0 and 1 are a best response.
simply gives the pure strategy
, so
will never give both 0 and 1.However
gives both 0 and 1 when y = 1/2.A Nash equilibrium exists when:

This determines one unique equilibrium where Player X plays a random mixture of 0 for 1/2 of the time and 1 the other 1/2 of the time. Player Y plays the pure strategy of 1/2. The value of the game is 1/4.
Non-Separable Games
[edit]A rational payoff function
[edit]Consider a zero-sum 2-player game between playersX andY, with
. Denote elements of
and
as
and
respectively. Define the utility functions
where

This game has no pure strategy Nash equilibrium. It can be shown[3] that a unique mixed strategy Nash equilibrium exists with the following pair ofcumulative distribution functions:

Or, equivalently, the following pair ofprobability density functions:

The value of the game is
.
Requiring a Cantor distribution
[edit]Consider a zero-sum 2-player game between playersX andY, with
. Denote elements of
and
as
and
respectively. Define the utility functions
where
.
This game has a unique mixed strategy equilibrium where each player plays a mixed strategy with theCantor singular function as thecumulative distribution function.[4]
- H. W. Kuhn and A. W. Tucker, eds. (1950).Contributions to the Theory of Games: Vol. II. Annals of Mathematics Studies28. Princeton University Press.ISBN 0-691-07935-8.
- ^I.L. Glicksberg. A further generalization of the Kakutani fixed point theorem, with application to Nash equilibrium points. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 3(1):170–174, February 1952.
- ^N. Stein, A. Ozdaglar and P.A. Parrilo. "Separable and Low-Rank Continuous Games".International Journal of Game Theory, 37(4):475–504, December 2008.https://arxiv.org/abs/0707.3462
- ^Irving Leonard Glicksberg & Oliver Alfred Gross (1950). "Notes on Games over the Square." Kuhn, H.W. & Tucker, A.W. eds.Contributions to the Theory of Games: Volume II. Annals of Mathematics Studies28, p.173–183. Princeton University Press.
- ^Gross, O. (1952). "A rational payoff characterization of the Cantor distribution." TechnicalReport D-1349, The RAND Corporation.