Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Jump to content
WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
Search

Property (philosophy)

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected fromAttribute (philosophy))
Differentiating and characterizing feature

Inlogic andphilosophy (especiallymetaphysics), aproperty is a characteristic of anobject; for example, a red object is said to have the property of redness. The property may be considered a form of object in its own right, able to possess other properties. A property, however, differs from individual objects in that it may beinstantiated, and often in more than one object. It differs from the logical and mathematical concept ofclass by not having any concept ofextensionality, and from the philosophical concept ofclass in that a property is considered to be distinct from the objects which possess it. Understanding how different individual entities (or particulars) can in some sense have some of the same properties is the basis of theproblem of universals.

Terms and usage

[edit]

A property is any member of a class of entities that are capable of being attributed to objects. Terms similar toproperty includepredicable,attribute,quality,feature,characteristic,type,exemplifiable,predicate, andintensional entity.[1]

Generally speaking, an object is said toexemplify,instantiate,bear,have orpossess a property if the property can be truly predicated of the object. The collection of objects that possess a property is called theextension of the property. Properties are said tocharacterize orinhere in objects that possess them.[1] Followers ofAlexius Meinong assert the existence of two kinds of predication: existent objectsexemplify properties, while nonexistent objects are said toexemplify,satisfy,immanently contain orbe consubstantiated by properties that areactually possessed and are said toencode,be determined by,be consociated with orbe constituted by properties that aremerely ascribed to objects. For example, sincePegasus is merely mythical, Pegasus encodes the property of being a horse, but Pegasus exemplifies the property of being a character ofGreek mythology as well.[2]Edward Jonathan Lowe even treatedinstantiation,characterization andexemplification as three separate kinds of predication.[1]

Broadly construed, examples of properties include redness, the property of being two,[3] the property of being nonexistent,[4] the property of being identical toSocrates,[1] the property of being a desk,[1] the property of being a property,[1] the property of being both round and square,[1] and the property of beingheterological. Some philosophers refuse to treatexistence as a property, andPeter van Inwagen suggested that one should deny the existence of certain "properties" so as to avoid paradoxes such asRussell's paradox andGrelling–Nelson paradox, though such moves remain controversial.[1]

Metaphysical debates

[edit]

In modernanalytic philosophy there are several debates about the fundamental nature of properties. These center around questions such as: Are properties universals or particulars? Are properties real? Are they categorical or dispositional? Are properties physical or mental?

Universals vs. particulars

[edit]

At least sincePlato, properties are viewed by numerous philosophers asuniversals, which are typically capable of being instantiated by different objects. Philosophers opposing this view regard properties asparticulars, namelytropes.[1]

Realism vs. anti-realism

[edit]

A realist about properties asserts that properties have genuine, mind-independent existence.[1] One way to spell this out is in terms of exact, repeatable, instantiations known asuniversals. The other realist position asserts that properties are particulars (tropes), which are unique instantiations in individual objects that merely resemble one another to various degrees. Transcendent realism, proposed byPlato and favored byBertrand Russell, asserts that properties exist even if uninstantiated.[1] Immanent realism, defended byAristotle andDavid Malet Armstrong, contends that properties exist only if instantiated.[1]

The anti-realist position, often referred to asnominalism claims that properties are names we attach to particulars. The properties themselves have no existence.

Categoricalism vs. dispositionalism

[edit]

Properties are often classified as eithercategorical anddispositional.[5][6] Categorical properties concern what something is like, e.g. what qualities it has. Dispositional properties, on the other hand, involve what powers something has, what it is able to do, even if it is not actually doing it.[5] For example, the shape of a sugar cube is a categorical property while its tendency to dissolve in water is a dispositional property. For many properties there is a lack of consensus as to how they should be classified, for example, whether colors are categorical or dispositional properties.[7][8]

According tocategoricalism, dispositions reduce to causal bases.[9] On this view, the fragility of a wine glass, a dispositional property, is not a fundamental feature of the glass since it can be explained in terms of the categorical property of the glass's micro-structural composition.Dispositionalism, on the other hand, asserts that a property is nothing more than a set of causal powers.[7] Fragility, according to this view, identifies a real property of the glass (e.g. to shatter when dropped on a sufficiently hard surface). Several intermediary positions exist.[7] The Identity view states that properties are both categorical (qualitative) and dispositional; these are just two ways of viewing the same property. One hybrid view claims that some properties are categorical and some are dispositional. A second hybrid view claims that properties have both a categorical (qualitative) and dispositional part, but that these are distinct ontological parts.

Physicalism, idealism, and property dualism

[edit]
Main articles:Physicalism,Idealism, andProperty dualism
Property dualism: the exemplification of two kinds of property by one kind of substance

Property dualism describes a category of positions in thephilosophy of mind which hold that, although the world is constituted of just one kind ofsubstance—the physical kind—there exist two distinct kinds of properties:physical properties andmental properties. In other words, it is the view that non-physical, mental properties (such as beliefs, desires and emotions) inhere in some physical substances (namely brains).

This stands in contrast to physicalism and idealism. Physicalism claims that all properties, include mental properties, ultimately reduce to, orsupervene on, physical properties.[10] Metaphysical idealism, by contrast, claims that "something mental (the mind, spirit, reason, will) is the ultimate foundation of all reality, or even exhaustive of reality."[11]

Types

[edit]

Intrinsic and extrinsic

[edit]
Main article:Intrinsic and extrinsic properties (philosophy)

Anintrinsic property is a property that an object or a thing has of itself, independently of other things, including its context. Anextrinsic (orrelational) property is a property that depends on a thing's relationship with other things. The latter is sometimes also called anattribute, since the value of that property isgiven to the object via its relation with another object. For example,mass is a physical intrinsic property of anyphysical object, whereasweight is an extrinsic property that varies depending on the strength of the gravitational field in which therespective object is placed. Another example of a relational property is thename of a person (an attribute given by the person's parents).

Essential and accidental

[edit]

In classicalAristotelian terminology, aproperty (Greek:idion, Latin:proprium) is one of thepredicables. It is a non-essential quality of a species (like anaccident), but a quality which is nevertheless characteristically present in members of that species. For example, "ability to laugh" may be considered a special characteristic of human beings. However, "laughter" is not anessential quality of the specieshuman, whose Aristotelian definition of "rational animal" does not require laughter. Therefore, in the classical framework,properties are characteristic qualities that are not truly required for the continued existence of an entity but are, nevertheless, possessed by the entity.

Determinate and determinable

[edit]

A property may be classified as eitherdeterminate ordeterminable. A determinable property is one that can get more specific. For example, color is a determinable property because it can be restricted to redness, blueness, etc.[12] A determinate property is one that cannot become more specific. This distinction may be useful in dealing with issues ofidentity.[13]

Pure and impure

[edit]

Impure properties are properties that, unlikepure properties, involve reference to a particular substance in their definition.[14] So, for example,being a wife is a pure property whilebeing the wife of Socrates is an impure property due to the reference to the particular "Socrates".[15] Sometimes, the termsqualitative andnon-qualitative are used instead ofpure andimpure.[16] Most but not allimpure properties are extrinsic properties. This distinction is relevant for the principle ofidentity of indiscernibles, which states that two things are identical if they areindiscernible, i.e. if they share all their properties.[14] This principle is usually defined in terms of pure properties only. The reason for this is that impure properties are not relevant for similarity or discernibility but taking them into consideration nonetheless would result in the principle being trivially true.[14] Another application of this distinction concerns the problem of duplication, for example, in theTwin Earth thought experiment. It is usually held that duplication only involves qualitative identity but perfect duplicates can still differ concerning theirnon-qualitative orimpure properties.[16]

Lovely and suspect

[edit]

Daniel Dennett distinguishes betweenlovely properties (such as loveliness itself), which, although theyrequire an observer to be recognised, exist latently in perceivable objects; andsuspect properties which have no existence at all until attributed by an observer (such as being suspected of a crime).[17]

Properties and predicates

[edit]

The ontological fact that something has a property is typically represented in language by applying apredicate to asubject. However, taking any grammatical predicate whatsoever to be a property, or to have a corresponding property, leads to certain difficulties, such asRussell's paradox and theGrelling–Nelson paradox. Moreover, a real property can imply a host of true predicates: for instance, if X has the property of weighing more than 2 kilos, then the predicates "..weighs more than 1.9 kilos", "..weighs more than 1.8 kilos", etc., are all true of it. Other predicates, such as "is an individual", or "has some properties" are uninformative or vacuous. There is some resistance to regarding such so-called "Cambridge properties" as legitimate.[18] These properties in the widest sense are sometimes referred to asabundant properties. They are contrasted withsparse properties, which include only properties "responsible for the objective resemblances and causal powers of things".[19]

Role in similarity

[edit]

The traditional conception ofsimilarity holds that properties are responsible for similarity: two objects are similar because they have a property in common. The more properties they share, the more similar they are. They resemble each other exactly if they share all their properties.[20][21] For this conception of similarity to work, it is important that only properties relevant to resemblance are taken into account, sometimes referred to assparse properties in contrast toabundant properties.[22][19]

Relations

[edit]
Main article:Relation (philosophy)

The distinction between properties andrelations can hardly be given in terms that do not ultimately presuppose it.[23]

Relations are true of several particulars, or shared amongst them. Thus the relation "... is taller than ..." holds "between" two individuals, who would occupy the two ellipses ('...'). Relations can be expressed by N-place predicates, where N is greater than 1.

Relations should be distinguished from relational properties. For example,marriage is a relation since it is between two people, butbeing married to X is a relational property had by a certain person since it concerns only one person.[23]

There are at least some apparent relational properties which are merely derived from non-relational (or 1-place) properties. For instance "A is heavier than B" is a relationalpredicate, but it is derived from the two non relational properties: the mass of A and the mass of B. Such relations are called external relations, as opposed to the more genuine internal relations.[24] Some philosophers believe that all relations are external, leading to a scepticism about relations in general, on the basis that external relations have no fundamental existence.[citation needed]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^abcdefghijkl"Properties".The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2017.
  2. ^Reicher, Maria."Nonexistent Objects".The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). Retrieved25 March 2021.
  3. ^Yi, Byeong-uk (April 1999)."Is Two a Property?"(PDF).Journal of Philosophy.96 (4):163–190.doi:10.2307/2564701.JSTOR 2564701. Retrieved25 March 2021.
  4. ^Berto, Francesco (2012).Existence as a Real Property: The Ontology of Meinongianism. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 130.ISBN 978-9400742062.
  5. ^abBorchert, Donald (2006). "Ontology".Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan.
  6. ^Kriegel, Uriah (2019)."Introverted Metaphysics: How We Get Our Grip on the Ultimate Nature of Objects, Properties, and Causation".Metaphilosophy.50 (5):688–707.doi:10.1111/meta.12391.S2CID 211938090.
  7. ^abcChoi, Sungho; Fara, Michael (2018)."Dispositions".The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  8. ^Rubenstein, Eric M."Color".Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved7 January 2021.
  9. ^"Properties".The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2017.
  10. ^"Physicalism".The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2017.
  11. ^"Idealism".The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2018.
  12. ^Stanford Encyclopaedia of PhilosophyDeterminate and Determinable Properties
  13. ^Georges Dicker (1998).Hume's Epistemology & Metaphysics. Routledge. p. 31.
  14. ^abcForrest, Peter (2020)."The Identity of Indiscernibles: 1. Formulating the Principle".The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved25 January 2021.
  15. ^Rosenkrantz, Gary S. (1979)."The Pure and the Impure".Logique et Analyse.22 (88):515–523.ISSN 0024-5836.JSTOR 44085165.
  16. ^abCowling, Sam (2015)."Non-Qualitative Properties".Erkenntnis.80 (2):275–301.doi:10.1007/s10670-014-9626-9.S2CID 254472503.
  17. ^"Lovely and Suspect Qualities". Retrieved3 August 2016.
  18. ^Nelson, Michael (1 January 2012). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.).The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved3 August 2016 – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  19. ^abOrilia, Francesco; Paolini Paoletti, Michele (2020)."Properties".The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  20. ^Allen, Sophie."Properties".Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved19 January 2021.
  21. ^Tversky, Amos (1977)."Features of Similarity".Psychological Review.84 (4):327–352.doi:10.1037/0033-295X.84.4.327.
  22. ^Blumson, Ben (2018)."Two Conceptions of Similarity".Philosophical Quarterly.68 (270):21–37.doi:10.1093/pq/pqx021.
  23. ^abMacBride, Fraser."Relations". InZalta, Edward N. (ed.).Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  24. ^G. E. Moore (December 15, 1919),"External and Internal Relations"

External links

[edit]
Theories
Concepts
Metaphysicians
Notable works
Related topics
Philosophers
Theories
Concepts
Works
Related articles
Authority control databases: NationalEdit this at Wikidata
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Property_(philosophy)&oldid=1289397207"
Categories:
Hidden categories:

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp