Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'normativism'

311 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  863
    ModalNormativism and De Re Modality.Tom Donaldson &Jennifer Wang -2022 -Argumenta 7 (2):293-307.
    In the middle of the last century, it was common to explain the notion of necessity in linguistic terms. A necessary truth, it was said, is a sentence whose truth is guaranteed by linguistic rules. Quine famously argued that, on this view, de re modal claims do not make sense. “Porcupettes are porcupines” is necessarily true, but it would be a mistake to say of a particular porcupette that it is necessarily a porcupine, or that it is possibly purple. Linguistic (...) theories of necessity fell out of favour with the publication of Kripke’s Naming and Necessity, and Quine’s arguments were put aside. In her recent book, Norms and Necessity, Amie Thomasson presents her modalnormativism, which is an updated version of the mid-century theories just described. Quine’s arguments are thus relevant once again. We recapitulate Quine’s central argument, in the context of modalnormativism. We then criticise Amie Thomasson’s discussion of de re modality. We finish by briefly presenting an alternative account of de re modal statements, which is compatible with modalnormativism. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  2. Anti-Normativism Evaluated.Ulf Hlobil -2015 -International Journal of Philosophical Studies 23 (3):376-395.
    I argue that recent attempts to show that meaning and content are not normative fail. The two most important arguments anti-normativists have presented are what I call the ‘argument from constitution’ and the ‘argument from guidance’. Both of these arguments suffer from the same basic problem: they overlook the possibility of focusing on assessability by norms, rather than compliance with norms or guidance by norms. Moreover, I argue that the anti-normativists arguments fail even if we ignore this basic problem. Thus, (...) we have not been given good reasons to think thatnormativism is false. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  3.  669
    Modalnormativism on semantic rules.Rohan Sud -2024 -Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 67 (8):2361-2380.
    According to Amie Thomasson’s modalnormativism, the function of modal discourse is to convey semantic rules. But what is a "semantic rule"? I raise three worries according to which there is no conception of a semantic rule that can serve the needs of a modal normativist. The first worry focuses on de re and a posteriori necessities. The second worry concerns Thomasson's inferential specification of the meaning of modal terms. The third worry asks about the normative status of semantic (...) rules. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4. Factualism,Normativism and the Bounds of Normativity.Thomas M. Besch -2011 -Dialogue 50 (2):347-365.
    The paper argues that applications of the principle that “ought” implies “can” (OIC) depend on normative considerations even if the link between “ought” and “can” is logical in nature. Thus, we should reject a common, “factualist” conception of OIC and endorse weak “normativism”. Even if we use OIC as the rule ““cannot” therefore “not ought””, applying OIC is not a mere matter of facts and logic, as factualists claim, but often draws on “proto-ideals” of moral agency.
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  5.  46
    Defendingnormativism.Steven Hrotic -2011 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (5):258-259.
    Elqayam & Evans (E&E) argue that evaluativenormativism leads to unacceptable research biases, and should be avoided. Though it is stipulated that the particular biases they discuss are cause for concern, this argument should not be generalized. The boundary between evaluative and goal-directed norms is difficult to define, and normative assumptions are an integral part of academic progress; moreover, the biases that result may have beneficial potential.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  74
    ContinentalNormativism and Its British Counterpart: How Different Are They?Stanley L. Paulson -1993 -Ratio Juris 6 (3):227-244.
    The separability thesis claims that the concept of law can be explicated independently of morality, the normativity thesis, that it can be explicated independently of fact. Continentalnormativism, prominent above all in the work of Hans Kelsen, may be characterized in terms of the coupling of these theses. Like Kelsen, H. L. A. Hart is a proponent of the separability thesis. And–a leitmotiv–both theorists reject reductive legal positivism. They do not, however, reject it for the same reasons. Kelsen's reason, (...) in a word, is the normativity thesis. Hart, however, grounds his theory in social fact. In place of the reductive thesis of the legal positivist tradition, and in sharp contrast to Kelsen's normativity thesis, Hart defends a non‐reductive version of what the author terms the facticity thesis. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  7
    LegalNormativism, Argumentation and Logic.Andrew Schumann &Elena Lisanyuk -2025 -Argumentation 39 (1).
    The paper substantiates the prospects ofnormativism in law, namely the possibility of using purely logical means to make a judgment as a logical conclusion. The main criticism ofnormativism is based on the possibility of conflicts of judicial decisions and especially on conflicts of the norms themselves, when a court under similar circumstances can make opposing decisions which are formally valid. Critics ofnormativism argue that logic is helpless in resolving the conflicts and that higher justice (...) must be guided by the discretion of judges who share common values or a common ideology, especially in the case of totalitarian societies. However, we show that there are two types of logical argumentation in the elimination of these conflicts: (a) Aristotelian, when a more general basis is sought, from which only one of the contradictions follows; (b) non-Aristotelian, when a compromise is reached between two contrary statements. In the second case, this technique is used mainly for civil cases. Moreover, this technique is quite formal and does not require an appeal to paraconsistent or other non-classical logics for eliminating the conflict. Using two recent court cases, we demonstrate how the proposed two types of logical argumentation work. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Resistingnormativism in psychology.Georges Rey -2007 - In Brian P. McLaughlin & Jonathan Cohen,Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind. Wiley-Blackwell.
    “Intentional content,” as I understand it, is whatever serves as the object of “propositional” attitude verbs, such as “think,” “judge,” “represent,” “prefer” (whether or not these objects are “propositions”). These verbs are standardly used to pick out the intentional states invoked to explain the states and behavior of people and many animals. I shall take the “normativity of the intentional,” or “Normativism,” to be the claim that any adequate theory of intentional states involves considerations of value not essentially involved (...) in the natural sciences. Thus, according toNormativism, whether or not someone thinks that fish sleep, or even can represent fish at all, depends upon making a judgment about the person’s goodness or rationality, of a sort that would not be involved in merely determining whether or not fish in fact sleep. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  9.  78
    Normativism and realism within contemporary democratic constitutionalism.Valerio Fabbrizi -2018 -Philosophy and Social Criticism 44 (6):1-21.
    The renewed interest on political realism can offer a new reading of the traditional dichotomy between normative and realist conception of constitutionalism. The purpose of this article is to analyse this renewed discussion, especially by focusing on the relationship between “political realism” and “political constitutionalism,” in the light of some theorists and authors—such as Richard Bellamy and Jeremy Waldron. After a brief introduction in which political realism will be discussed, especially through Bernard Williams’ reinterpretation, the article proposes a rereading of (...) democratic constitutionalism from the classical dichotomy betweennormativism and realism in political theory. The focus will be set on three key issues: 1. Richard Bellamy’s constitutional theory in a realist perspective; 2. An insight of legal constitutionalism under a normative banner; 3. A brief conclusion in which the risks of a majoritarian and populist constitutionalism will be discussed. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  149
    Beyond Naturalism andNormativism: Reconceiving the 'Disease' Debate.Jeremy Simon -2007 -Philosophical Papers 36 (3):343-370.
    In considering the debate about the meaning of ‘disease’, the positions are generally presented as falling into two categories: naturalist, e.g., Boorse, and normativist, e.g., Engelhardt and many others. This division is too coarse, and obscures much of what is going on in this debate. I therefore propose that accounts of the meaning of ‘disease’ be assessed according to Hare’s (1997) taxonomy of evaluative terms. Such an analysis will allow us to better understand both individual positions and their inter-relationships. Most (...) importantly, it will show that it is unlikely that there is a single unique disease-concept at issue. Rather, different authors are, for the most part, considering different concepts. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  11.  136
    Metaphysical Explanations for Modal Normativists.Theodore Locke -2020 -Metaphysics 3 (1):33-54.
    I expand modalnormativism, a theory of metaphysical modality, to give a normativist account of metaphysical explanation. According to modalnormativism, basic modal claims do not have a descriptive function, but instead have the normative function of enabling language users to express semantic rules that govern the use of ordinary non-modal vocabulary. However, a worry for modalnormativism is that it doesn’t keep up with all of the important and interesting metaphysics we can do by giving and (...) evaluating metaphysical explanations. So, I advance modalnormativism by arguing that metaphysical explanations also have a normative rather than descriptive function. In particular, non-causal explanatory claims have formal and semantic properties that make them expressively stricter than basic modal claims and so are better suited to express fine-grained aspects of semantic rules. A major payoff of my normativist account of metaphysical explanations is that it yields a plausible story about how we come to evaluate and know metaphysical explanations—we do this primarily by conceptual analysis. I also respond to a number of objections, including the objection that the epistemic payoffs of my view are not worth the metaphysical costs. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  12.  45
    ModalNormativism and Metasemantics.Theodore D. Locke -2023 - In Miguel Garcia-Godinez,Thomasson on Ontology. Springer Verlag. pp. 109-136.
    I argue that we can accept modalnormativism—a view that the function of modal claims is to express semantic rules—while also accepting possible worlds semantics. I argue that by keeping the metaphysical insights ofnormativism at the level of metasemantics—i.e., at the level of accounts of what metaphysically explains facts about the meaning of modal claims—it is open to the normativist to wholeheartedly accept possible worlds semantics.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  52
    Normativism versus mechanism.Valerie A. Thompson -2011 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (5):272-273.
    Using normative correctness as a diagnostic tool reduces the outcome of complex cognitive functions to a binary classification (normative or non-normative). It also focuses attention on outcomes, rather than processes, impeding the development of good cognitive theories. Given that both normative and non-normative responses may be produced by the same process, normativity is a poor indicator of underlying processes.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14.  118
    Rescuing DoxasticNormativism.Ragnar Francén Olinder -2012 -Theoria 78 (4):293-308.
    According to doxasticnormativism, part of what makes an attitude a belief rather than another type of attitude is that it is governed by a truth-norm. It has been objected that this view fails since there are true propositions such that if you believed them they would not be true, and thus the obligation to believe true propositions cannot hold for these. I argue that the solution for doxastic normativists is to find a norm that draws the right distinction (...) between those true propositions we are obliged to believe (“ordinary non-tricky propositions”) and those we are not (“tricky propositions”). I develop a norm which I argue does exactly this, and further argue that it can be used to salvage the idea that belief is constitutively normative. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  286
    (1 other version)Normativism defended.Ralph Wedgwood -2007 - In Brian P. McLaughlin & Jonathan Cohen,Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 85--102.
    My aim in this chapter is to defend the claim that “the intentional is normative” against a number of objections, including those that Georges Rey has presented in his contribution to this volume. In the first section of this chapter, I shall outline a specific version of this claim; and in the second section, I shall give a quick sketch of the principal argument that I have used to support this claim, and briefly comment on Rey’s criticisms of this argument.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  16. DismantlingNormativism.Joanna Klimczyk -2018 -Principia 64 (Tom 64):43-80.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Socialnormativism.Jaroslav Peregrin -unknown
    Normativity is one of the keywords of contemporary philosophical discussions (which partly reincarnate traditional debates about the differences between Geisteswissenschaften and Naturwissenschaften ). But are the philosophers who argue for the irreducible role of normativity within accounts for human societies obliged to assume, as Stephen Turner has recently put it, the existence of a "non‐natural, non‐empirical stuff that is claimed to be necessarily, intrinsically there and to in some sense account for the actual"?
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  257
    How to be a Normativist about the Nature of Belief.Kate Nolfi -2015 -Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 96 (2):181-204.
    According to the normativist, it is built into the nature of belief itself that beliefs are subject to a certain set of norms. I argue here that only a normativist account can explain certain non‐normative facts about what it takes to have the capacity for belief. But this way of defendingnormativism places an explanatory burden on any normativist account that an account on which a truth norm is explanatorily fundamental simply cannot discharge. I develop an alternative account that (...) can achieve explanatory adequacy where this sort of truth privileging account falls short. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  19.  78
    IntentionalNormativism Meets Normative Supervenience and the Because Constraint.Daniel Laurier -2011 -Dialogue 50 (2):315-331.
    ABSTRACT: I explain and rebut four objections to the claim that attributions of intentional attitudes are normative judgments, all stemming, directly or indirectly, from the widespread assumption that the normative supervenes on the non-normative.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20.  601
    De MinimisNormativism: a New Theory of Full Aptness.J. Adam Carter -2021 -Philosophical Quarterly 71 (1):16-36.
    Full aptness is the most important concept in performance-based virtue epistemology. The structure of full aptness, in epistemology and elsewhere, is bi-levelled. At the first level, we evaluate beliefs, like performances, on the basis of whether they are successful, competent, and apt – viz., successful because competent. But the fact that aptness itself can be fragile – as it is when an apt performance could easily have been inapt – points to a higher zone of quality beyond mere aptness. To (...) break in to this zone, one must not merely perform aptly but also in doing so safeguard in skilled ways against certain risks to inaptness. But how must this be done, exactly? This paper has two central aims. First, I challenge the credentials of mainstream thinking about full-aptness by raising some new and serious problems for the view. I then propose a novel account of full aptness – what I call de minimisnormativism – which keeps all the advantages of the canonical view, avoids its problems entirely, and offers some additional payoffs. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  21.  253
    Normativism and Doxastic Deliberation.Conor McHugh -2013 -Analytic Philosophy 54 (4):447-465.
  22.  23
    On Turner’s Anti-Normativism.Pietro Salis -2023 - In Raffaela Giovagnoli & Robert Lowe,The Logic of Social Practices II. Springer Nature Switzerland. pp. 159-176.
    Stephen Turner’s anti-normativism is based on the idea that the normative can be explained away by social science. Exploiting the idea fostered by the sociology of scientific knowledge that reasons can be understood naturalistically as the causes of the beliefs of scientists and endorsing a non-normative conception of rationality, Turner has argued that normative accounts are better understood as “Good Bad Theories” (GBT). GBT are understood as false accounts that play a role in social coordination like magical or religious (...) rituals in primitive societies (e.g. Tabu and the like). According to Turner, “norms,” “obligations,” “reasons,” and “commitments” are like Tabu and can be explained away as GBT. Hence, Turner expected normative accounts to disappear completely in a fully disenchanted world. Turner focuses on the idea, widespread among philosophers, that the normative does not reduce to the causal: his main claim is that social science succeeds in the reduction of the normative in causal terms, overcoming normative/causal dualism. Furthermore, this success is presented as creating a serious challenge fornormativism. By focusing on certain (supposedly normative) features of beliefs like those involved in belief change dynamics, I will point out some interesting implications and problems for Turner’s anti-normativism. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  82
    Davidson: Normativist or Anti-normativist?John Fennell -2015 -Acta Analytica 30 (1):67-86.
    This paper contests the standard reading, due to Bilgrami and Glüer, that Davidson is an anti-normativist about word-meaning. Their case for his anti-normativism rests on his avowed anti-conventionalism about word-meaning. While not denying Davidson’s anti-conventionalism, I argue in the central part of the paper devoted to Bilgrami that the constitutive role that charity must play in interpretation for Davidson puts pressure on his anti-conventionalism, ultimately forcing a more tempered anti-conventionalism than Bilgrami allows. Simply put, my argument is that two (...) central doctrines of Davidson’s—constitutive charity and anti-conventionalism—do not sit easily together in the project of interpreting speakers of our home language and that if they are to be made compatible, it is his anti-conventionalism that gets weakened. This ushers a certain meaningnormativism into Davidson’s view. To strengthen my case for reading Davidson as a normativist about word-meaning, I respond to two important arguments against his allegednormativism: first, that meaning normativity is incompatible with the truism that the relation between a word and its meaning is arbitrary and, second, that constitutive charity far from ushering in meaning normativity is incompatible with it. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  28
    Une critique normativiste du naturalisme.Charlotte Gauvry -2020 -Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 108 (4):531-546.
    L’enjeu du présent article est d’examiner la critique du naturalisme menée par Charles Taylor de 1970 à 1990 et d’en interroger la portée. L’article commence par définir les thèses ontologiques et épistémologiques constitutives de ce que Taylor appelle « le naturalisme » et qu’il considère, non sans le déplorer, comme le courant philosophique hégémonique de la deuxième moitié du xx e siècle. Il analyse ensuite les différents arguments mobilisés par Taylor pour en contester la légitimité et il en identifie un (...) comme central : la cécité du naturalisme au caractère déterminant de « l’arrière-plan ». Cet argument se décline en deux versions : la cécité au statut herméneutique de l’arrière-plan, la cécité à son statut normatif. Pour finir, l’article formule plusieurs objections à l’endroit de la proposition normativiste élaborée par Taylor en réponse au naturalisme. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  17
    Normativism.Walter Sinnott-Armstrong -2006 - InMoral skepticisms. New York: Oxford University Press.
    This chapter coversnormativism, which attempts to derive moral conclusions from normative but non-moral premises. One version refers to moral explanations, another version includes contractarianism and contractualism, which justifies moral beliefs by reference to contractors who are rational, impartial, and/or reasonable. Neither version can solve the skeptical regress problem.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  97
    Counterpossibles for modal normativists.Theodore D. Locke -2019 -Synthese 198 (2):1235-1257.
    Counterpossibles are counterfactuals that involve some metaphysical impossibility. Modalnormativism is a non-descriptivist account of metaphysical necessity and possibility according to which modal claims, e.g. ‘necessarily, all bachelors are unmarried’, do not function as descriptive claims about the modal nature of reality but function as normative illustrations of constitutive rules and permissions that govern the use of ordinary non-modal vocabulary, e.g. ‘bachelor’. In this paper, I assume modalnormativism and develop a novel account of counterpossibles and claims about (...) metaphysical similarity between possible and impossible worlds. I argue that considerations of metaphysical similarity between various impossible worlds and the actual world only require us to tacitly consider how the actual constitutive rules that govern the use of our terms change in order to accommodate the description of some hypothetical impossible scenario. I then argue for my account by raising worries for alternative epistemic and realist accounts of counterpossibles and showing how my account avoids those worries. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  27.  83
    Normativism, Anti-Normativism and Humanist Pragmatism: Stephen P. Turner: Explaining the Normative. Polity Press, Cambridge, 2010, pbk. $24.95, hbk. $69.95, 228 pp + index.Maksymilian Del Mar -2010 -Human Studies 33 (2-3):305-323.
    Review Essay of Stephen P. Turner, Explaining the Normative, 2010.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  416
    ModalNormativism and the Methods of Metaphysics.Amie L. Thomasson -2007 -Philosophical Topics 35 (1-2):135-160.
  29.  59
    A role fornormativism.Igor Douven -2011 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (5):252-253.
    Elqayam & Evans (E&E) argue against prescriptivenormativism and in favor of descriptivism. I challenge the assumption, implicit in their article, that there is a choice to be made between the two approaches. While descriptivism may be the right approach for some questions, others call for a normativist approach. To illustrate the point, I briefly discuss two questions of the latter sort.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  82
    Counterpart theory: metaphysical modalnormativism by another name.Kristie Miller -2023 -Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 1 (8):2339-2360.
    In this paper, I argue that not only is metaphysical modalnormativism an attractive view but that, as a matter of fact, many of us have, all along, been metaphysical modal normativists of a particular stripe. Namely, we have been the kinds of modal normativists, in the form of counterpart theorists, who are robust realists about possibility simpliciter. Having introduced modalnormativism as Thomasson does in Norms and Necessity, I go on to recast it in somewhat different terms. (...) With this re-casting in place we can see that while the view offers a pleasingly deflationary account of metaphysical necessity and possibility it does so only against the backdrop of robust realism about possibility simpliciter. If that is right, then Lewis’ counterpart theory turns out to be a potent version of metaphysical modalnormativism. So many of us have, all along, been metaphysical modal normativists, and so much the better for it. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  108
    Normativism and the mental: A problem of language individuation.Adèle Mercier -1993 -Philosophical Studies 72 (1):71-88.
    My aim in this paper is two?fold. I start by contrasting three versions of externalist arguments based on etiological considerations, whose differences are not often appreciated. My purpose in doing so is to isolate one of these versions of externalism as most supportive of current anti?individualist attitudes toward the mental. My second aim is to show that this version, which I call (for reasons soon to be clear) Dialectal Etiology , is marred to a greater extent than the other two (...) by an important problem of language individuation.ii.. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  62
    Betweennormativism and naturalism: Honneth on social pathology.Arvi Särkelä &Arto Laitinen -2019 -Constellations 26 (2):286-300.
  33.  302
    Subtracting “ought” from “is”: Descriptivism versusnormativism in the study of human thinking.Shira Elqayam &Jonathan St B. T. Evans -2011 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (5):233-248.
    We propose a critique ofnormativism, defined as the idea that human thinking reflects a normative system against which it should be measured and judged. We analyze the methodological problems associated withnormativism, proposing that it invites the controversial “is-ought” inference, much contested in the philosophical literature. This problem is triggered when there are competing normative accounts (the arbitration problem), as empirical evidence can help arbitrate between descriptive theories, but not between normative systems. Drawing on linguistics as a model, we (...) propose that a clear distinction between normative systems and competence theories is essential, arguing that equating them invites an “is-ought” inference: to wit, supporting normative “ought” theories with empirical “is” evidence. We analyze in detail two research programmes with normativist features – Oaksford and Chater's rational analysis and Stanovich and West's individual differences approach – demonstrating how, in each case, equating norm and competence leads to an is-ought inference.Normativism triggers a host of research biases in the psychology of reasoning and decision making: focusing on untrained participants and novel problems, analyzing psychological processes in terms of their normative correlates, and neglecting philosophically significant paradigms when they do not supply clear standards for normative judgement. For example, in a dual-process framework,normativism can lead to a fallacious “ought-is” inference, in which normative responses are taken as diagnostic of analytic reasoning. We propose that little can be gained fromnormativism that cannot be achieved by descriptivist computational-level analysis, illustrating our position with Hypothetical Thinking Theory and the theory of the suppositional conditional. We conclude that descriptivism is a viable option, and that theories of higher mental processing would be better off freed from normative considerations. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  34.  62
    A Sellarsian Approach to theNormativism-Antinormativism Controversy.Dionysis Christias -2015 -Philosophy of the Social Sciences 45 (2):143-175.
    In this article, it is argued that Sellars’ view of normativity is the key for a proper resolution of the debate betweennormativism and anti-normativism, as the latter is described in Turner’s recent book Explaining the Normative. Drawing on an early Sellarsian article , I suggest that bothnormativism and anti-normativism are ultimately unsatisfactory positions and for the same reason: due to their failure to draw a distinction between causal or explanatory reducibility and logical or conceptual (...) reducibility of the normative to the non-normative. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35.  99
    Againstnormativism about mental attitudes.Marianna Bergamaschi Ganapini -2021 -Analytic Philosophy 62 (3):295-311.
    Analytic Philosophy, Volume 62, Issue 3, Page 295-311, September 2021.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  199
    The concept of health: beyondnormativism and naturalism.Richard P. Hamilton -2010 -Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 16 (2):323-329.
    Philosophical discussions of health and disease have traditionally been dominated by a debate between normativists, who hold that health is an inescapably value-laded concept and naturalists, such as Christopher Boorse, who believe that it is possible to derive a purely descriptive or theoretical definition of health based upon biological function. In this paper I defend a distinctive view which traces its origins in Aristotle's naturalistic ethics. An Arisotelian would agree with Boorse that health and disease are ubiquitous features of the (...) natural world and thus not mere projections of human interests and values. She would differ from him in rejecting the idea that value is a non-natural quality. I conclude my discussion with some comments of the normative character of living systems. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  37. Normativism or the Normative Theory of Legal Science: Some Epistemological Problems.Riccardo Guastini -1998 - In Stanley L. Paulson,Normativity and Norms: Critical Perspectives on Kelsenian Themes. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 317--30.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  50
    A Critique of an Epistemic Intellectual Culture: Cartesianism,Normativism and Modern Crises.V. P. J. Arponen -2016 -Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 46 (1):84-103.
    The so-called epistemological turn of the Descartes-Locke-Kant tradition is a hallmark of modern philosophy. The broad family ofnormativism constitutes one major response to the Cartesian heritage building upon some version of the idea that human knowledge, action and sociality build fundamentally upon some form of social agreement and standards. Representationalism and the Cartesian picture more generally have been challenged by normativists but this paper argues that, even where these challenges bynormativism have been taken to heart, our (...) intellectual culture remains fundamentally epistemic in certain problematic senses. Two problems are highlighted: first,normativism remains functionally Cartesian, for human action and sociality appear as processes driven by the shared understandings by competent contributors, and second,normativism is unable to account for forms of human action and sociality other than those occurring in the relatively small worlds of normatively regulated conceptual spaces of mutual access and listening. These points are illustrated by an applied discussion of the blind spots of normativist accounts of the emerging environmental and the on-going economic crises. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. Why We Need a NewNormativism about Collective Action.Matthew Rachar &Javier Gomez Lavin -2022 -Philosophical Quarterly 72 (2):478-507.
    What do we owe each other when we act together? According to normativists about collective action, necessarily something and potentially quite a bit. They contend that collective action inherently involves a special normative status amongst participants, which may, for example, involve mutual obligations to receive the concurrence of the others before leaving. We build on recent empirical work whose results lend plausibility to a normativist account by further investigating the specific package of mutual obligations associated with collective action according to (...) our everyday understanding. However, our results cast doubt on a proposed obligation to seek the permission of co-actors before exiting a collective action, and suggest instead that this obligation is a function of explicit promising. We then discuss how our results pave the path for a newnormativism, a theory that neither under- nor overshoots the target given by our common conception of the interpersonal obligations present in collective action.*. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  40.  623
    Overselling the case againstnormativism.Tim Fuller &Richard Samuels -2011 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (5):255-255.
    Though we are in broad agreement with much of Elqayam & Evans' (E&E's) position, we criticize two aspects of their argument. First, rejectingnormativism is unlikely to yield the benefits that E&E seek. Second, their conception of rational norms is overly restrictive and, as a consequence, their arguments at most challenge a relatively restrictive version ofnormativism.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  74
    Pathologizing Ugliness: A Conceptual Analysis of the Naturalist and Normativist Claims in “Aesthetic Pathology”.Yves Saint James Aquino -2022 -Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 47 (6):735-748.
    Pathologizing ugliness refers to the use of disease language and medical processes to foster and support the claim that undesirable features are pathological conditions requiring medical or surgical intervention. Primarily situated in cosmetic surgery, the practice appeals to the concept of “aesthetic pathology”, which is a medical designation for features that deviate from some designated aesthetic norms. This article offers a two-pronged conceptual analysis of aesthetic pathology. First, I argue that three sets of claims, derived from normativist and naturalistic accounts (...) of disease, inform the framing of ugliness as a disease. These claims concern: (1) aesthetic harms, (2) aesthetic dysfunction, and (3) aesthetic deviation. Second, I introduce the notion of a hybridization loop in medicine, which merges the naturalist and normative understanding of the disease that potentially enables pathologizing practices. In the context of cosmetic surgery, the loop simultaneously promotes the framing of beauty ideals as normal biological attributes and the framing of normal appearance as an aesthetic ideal to legitimize the need for cosmetic interventions. The article thus offers an original discussion of the conceptual problems arising from a specific practice in cosmetic surgery that depicts ugliness as the disease. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  26
    The Naturalistic Moment inNormativism.Stephen Turner -2015 - In Johannes Bakker,Rural Sociologists at Work: Candid Accounts of Theory, Method, and Practice. Routledge.
    This chapter focuses on a question about one role: the explanatory role ofnormativism or normativity in relation to ordinary 'scientific', meaning social scientific, explanations of actions and beliefs, especially the empirical, observable, or empirically relevant aspects of human conduct. Call this the epistemic form of the naturalistic moment problem. It call this a 'naturalistic moment', a place wherenormativism makes factual assertions about real processes in the natural world. This pseudo argument boils down to a series of (...) equivocations. The normativist must claim that there is some super-added normative element that cannot be accounted for naturalistically or by social science. Transcendental arguments to the effect that they have to have such and such mental content are likely to fail the mosquito test. The default position of rationalistic normativists, well encapsulated by Korsgaard, who rejects it, is that normativity in particular, rightness is an objective property grasped by reason. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  85
    Positive Economics and the Normativistic Fallacy: Bridging the Two Sides of CSR.Philipp Schreck,Dominik van Aaken &Thomas Donaldson -2013 -Business Ethics Quarterly 23 (2):297-329.
    ABSTRACT:In response to criticism of empirical or “positive” approaches to corporate social responsibility (CSR), we defend the importance of these approaches for any CSR theory that seeks to have practical impact. Although we acknowledge limitations to positive approaches, we unpack the neglected but crucial relationships between positive knowledge on the one hand and normative knowledge on the other in the implementation of CSR principles. Using the structure of a practical syllogism, we construct a model that displays the key role of (...) empirical knowledge in fulfilling a firm’s responsibility to society, paying special attention to the implications of the “ought implies can” dictum. We also defend the importance of one particular class of empirical claims; namely, claims from the field of economics. Even positive economic theory, which is often criticized for endorsing profits rather than values, can cooperate in intriguing ways with non-economic concepts in the implementation of CSR goals. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  44.  113
    Mental disorder between naturalism andnormativism.Somogy Varga -2017 -Philosophy Compass 12 (6):e12422.
    Worries about the potential medicalization of social and moral problems has propelled the debate on the nature of mental disorder, with normativists insisting that psychiatric classification is inherently value-laden and naturalists maintaining that a purely descriptive account of disease is possible. In recent work, some authors take a different path, accepting that the concepts of disease and mental disorder are value-laden but maintaining that this does not prevent objective truths regarding mental disorder attribution. This paper explores two such accounts and (...) the important steps they provide toward rethinking the nature and metaphysical status of mental disorder. The challenges raised in this paper are meant to contribute to the further development of this stimulating work. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45. Legal Empiricism,Normativism, and the Institutional Theory of Law.George Mousourakis -2009 -Philosophia 37 (2).
    Much of contemporary British legal theory has its roots in the tradition of philosophical empiricism—the philosophical position that no theory or opinion can be accepted as valid unless verified by the test of experience. In this context normativity, both in law and morals, is understood and explained in terms of social practices observable in the world. The nineteenth-century jurist John Austin, for example, defined law in terms of a command supported by a sanction and as presupposing the habitual obedience of (...) the bulk of a community to the commands of a sovereign himself not habitually obedient to anyone else. Similarly, Hart's conception of legal obligation, although somewhat more complex, derived from the observation of people's actual practices analyzed in terms of "the internal point of view" crucial to their comprehension of and participation to these practices. It is within this framework that we must consider the distinction between is and ought as used by British positivist theories and which is so essential to positivist jurisprudence. In this respect a chief difference between the British and the Continental traditions in legal theory prevails. This paper aims to re-examine some main themes of contemporary jurisprudence and explore the extent to which contemporary theorists, both British and Continental, have succeeded in developing a theory of law that would create a workable marriage between the two traditions. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  16
    Hans Kelsen'sNormativism.Carsten Heidemann -2022 - Cambridge University Press.
    Hans Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law is the most prominent example of legalnormativism. This text traces its origins and its genesis. In philosophy,normativism started with Hume's distinction between Is- and Ought-propositions. Kant distinguished practical from theoretical judgments, while resting even the latter on normativity. Following him, Lotze and the Baden neo-Kantians instrumentalizednormativism to secure a sphere of knowledge which is not subject to the natural sciences. Even in his first major text, Kelsen claims that (...) law is solely a matter of Ought or normativity. In the second phase of his writings, he places himself into the neo-Kantian tradition, holding legal norms to be Ought-judgments of legal science. In the third phase, he advocates a barely coherent naive normative realism. In the fourth phase, he supplements the realist view with a strict will-theory of norms, coupled with set-pieces from linguistic philosophy; classicalnormativism is more or less dismantled. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  21
    Normative Reason, Primitiveness, and the Argument for SemanticNormativism.Joanna Klimczyk -2015 -Etyka 50:73-90.
    This paper sketches a particular line of criticism targeted at Scanlon’s account of a normative reason, which is purported to kill two birds with one stone: to raise doubts about the plausibility of Scanlon’s account of a normative reason and, next, to dismiss Scanlon’s conception of what a normative reason is in the role of an argument for semanticnormativism. Following Whiting I take semanticnormativism to be the view, according to which linguistic meaning is intrinsically normative. The (...) key argument for semanticnormativism is that a word or expression has conditions for its correct use which count, or speak in favour of using it in certain ways and not in others. Specifically, it has immediate implications for how a subject should or may employ that expression. I shall argue that if the favouring format of analysis of a normative reason is not a particularly happy proposal in itself, then it supplies a superficial support for semanticnormativism. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  44
    A case for limited prescriptivenormativism.Emmanuel M. Pothos &Jerome R. Busemeyer -2011 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (5):264-265.
    Understanding cognitive processes with a formal framework necessitates some limited, internal prescriptivenormativism. This is because it is not possible to endorse the psychological relevance of some axioms in a formal framework, but reject that of others. The empirical challenge then becomes identifying the remit of different formal frameworks, an objective consistent with the descriptivism Elqayam & Evans (E&E) advocate.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  373
    (A Little) Quantified Modal Logic for Normativists.Mark Povich -forthcoming -Analysis.
    Burgess (1997), building on Quine (1953), convincingly argued that claims in quantified modal logic cannot be understood as synonymous with or logically equivalent to claims about the analyticity of certain sentences. According to modalnormativism, metaphysically necessary claims instead express or convey our actual semantic rules. In this paper, I show how the normativist can use Sidelle’s (1992a, 1995) neglected work on rigidity to account for two important phenomena in quantified modal logic: the necessity of identity and the substitutivity (...) of identicals into modal contexts. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  26
    Addiction from a Normativist’s Point of View.Ondřej Beran -2018 -Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy 28:13-17.
    The paper discusses alternatives of philosophical approach to addiction. While not denying the central position of problems of will or craving, it focuses on the broader anthropological context of addiction, using Heidegger’s existential analyses. It appears that addiction – in some cases, because an essentialist exposition is not viable here – is characterized by a defective pattern of the agent’s choice among possibilities and of temporality. The anecdotic observations can be synthesized into a treatise of addiction as a normative disorder: (...) a systematic inability of the addict to function within usual normative practices of various social contexts. The relevance of this perspective is testified also by therapeutic practice: addicts are treated not exclusively with respect to problems concerning will, but as persons who have to be re-socialized, i.e. led to a responsible attitude both towards themselves and society. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 311
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp