Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs
Order:

1 filter applied
Disambiguations
Zahi Zalloua [21]Zahi Anbra Zalloua [8]
  1.  13
    Being posthuman: ontologies of the future.Zahi Anbra Zalloua -2021 - New York, NY, USA: Bloomsbury Academic.
    In Being Posthuman, Zahi Zalloua interrogates the notion that "post-" does not necessarily mean 'after' or that what comes after is more advanced than what has gone before. He pursues this line of inquiry across four distinct, yet interrelated, figures: cyborgs, animals, objects, and racialized and excluded 'others'. These figures disrupt the narrative of the 'human' and its singularity and by reading them together, Zalloua determines that it is only when posthumanist discourse is combined with psychoanalysis that subjectivity can be (...) properly examined. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  7
    Continental philosophy and the Palestinian question: beyond the Jew and the Greek.Zahi Zalloua -2017 - New York: Bloomsbury Academic, an imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing PIc.
    From Sartre to Levinas, continental philosophers have looked to the example of the Jew as the paradigmatic object of and model for ethical inquiry. Levinas, for example, powerfully dedicates his 1974 book Otherwise than Being to the victims of the Holocaust, and turns attention to the state of philosophy after Auschwitz. Such an ethics radically challenges prior notions of autonomy and comprehension-two key ideas for traditional ethical theory and, more generally, the Greek tradition. It seeks to respect the opacity of (...) the other and avoid the dangers of hermeneutic violence. But how does such an ethics of the other translate into real, everyday life? What is at stake in thinking the other as Jew? Is the alterity of the Jew simply a counter to Greek universalism? Is a rhetoric of exceptionalism, with its unavoidable ontological residue, at odds with shifting political realities? Within this paradigm, what then becomes of the Arab or Muslim, the other of the Jew, the other of the other, so to speak? This line of ethical thought-in its desire to bear witness to past suffering and come to terms with subjectivity after Auschwitz-arguably brackets from analysis present operations of power. Would, then, a more sensitive historical approach expose the Palestinian as the other of the Israeli? Here, Zahi Zalloua offers a challenging intervention into how we configure the contemporary. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  183
    Montaigne, skepticism and immortality.Zahi Anbra Zalloua -2003 -Philosophy and Literature 27 (1):40-61.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Literature 27.1 (2003) 40-61 [Access article in PDF] Montaigne, Skepticism and Immortality Zahi Zallou I IN THE LAST PAGES OF HIS ESSAY "Of Experience," Michel de Montaigne warns against the desire to "go outside ourselves." 1 While Montaigne apparently spares Christian mystics from his biting critique ("those venerable souls, exalted by ardent piety and religion to constant and conscientious meditation on divine things" [p. 856]), there is (...) no suggested criterion enabling one to discriminate between these "venerable souls" and those individuals dangerously engaging in similar practices, claiming to have similar mystical religious experiences. The latters' "care of the self" (cura sui) is a kind of caring that would paradoxically do violence to their human self (conceived by Montaigne as both mind and body): "That is madness: instead of changing into angels [in order to be closer to the divinitas of God], they change into beasts [a regression to the realm of animalitas]; instead of raising themselves, they lower themselves" (p. 856). With this conduplicatio, the repetition of the verb "to change," Montaigne emphasizes the role of agency, thus pointing out that they are to a large measure responsible for their condition, through their practices of self-care, or rather what Nietzsche has called their spiritual "incuria sui." 2 Neither the mind nor the body should be excluded from serious consideration, Montaigne stresses: "For it is indeed reasonable, as they say, that the body should not follow its appetites to the disadvantage of the mind; but why is it not also reasonable that the mind should not pursue its appetites to the disadvantage of the body?" (p. 681). Divorcing the mind from the body is, indeed, seen as an unwise, and potentially disastrous, practice: [End Page 40] Those who want to split up our two principal parts and sequester them from each other are wrong. (p. 484) To what purpose do we dismember by force a structure made up of such close and brotherly correspondence? On the contrary, let us bind it together again by mutual services. Let the mind arouse and quicken the heaviness of the body, and the body check and make fast the lightness of the mind. (p. 855) Montaigne's suspicion of claims pertaining to the transcendent realm is perhaps most forcefully expressed in his late additions to "Of Experience": "Between ourselves, these are two things that I have always observed to be in singular accord: supercelestial thoughts and subterranean conduct. [...] These transcendental humors frighten me, like lofty and inaccessible places" (p. 856). Not even Socrates, who is known to have engaged in excessive spiritual meditations, is spared from the essayist's critical reflections: "And nothing is so hard for me to stomach in the life of Socrates as his ecstasies and possessions by his daemon, nothing is so human in Plato as the qualities for which they say he is called divine" (p. 856). This should be seen as a qualification of his earlier discussion of Socrates's daimonion in "Of Prognostications": "The daemon of Socrates was perhaps a certain impulse of the will that came to him without awaiting the advice of his reason [discours]. In a well-purified soul such as his, prepared by a continual exercise of wisdom and virtue, it is likely that these inclinations, although instinctive and undigested, were always important and worth following" (pp. 29-30). What is at issue here is the contrast (yet without any tension) between reason's way and God's way, so to speak, between Socrates's "discours" (his reason, which dictates to him the appropriate and rational means of action) and his "demon" (Socrates's divine voice or "divine sign," 3 which informs him of what to do and, especially, not to do). 4 Due to Socrates's wise and virtuous character, the essayist speculates, the former never erred in acting on his impulses or undigested inclinations. Montaigne generalizes and is even tempted to translate some of his own past actions in terms of a Socratic-like divine inspiration: "Everyone feels within himself some likeness of such stirrings [...] And I have had some [...] by which I let myself... (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. (1 other version)alterity and 'Care of the Self'in Montaigne's essay 'Of Friendship.'.Zahi Zalloua -2002 -Intertexts. Spring 6 (2):22-8.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  44
    Žižek with French Feminism: Enjoyment and the Feminine Logic of the “Not-All”.Zahi Zalloua -2014 -Intertexts 18 (2):109-130.
  6. Introduction: Understanding Barthes, understanding modernism.Jeffrey R. Di Leo &Zahi Zalloua -2023 - In Jeffrey R. Di Leo & Zahi Anbra Zalloua,Understanding Žižek, understanding modernism. New York: Bloomsbury Academic.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Introduction: Understanding Barthes, understanding modernism.Jeffrey R. Di Leo &Zahi Zalloua -2023 - In Jeffrey R. Di Leo & Zahi Anbra Zalloua,Understanding Žižek, understanding modernism. New York: Bloomsbury Academic.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  27
    Understanding Žižek, understanding modernism.Jeffrey R. Di Leo &Zahi Anbra Zalloua (eds.) -2023 - New York: Bloomsbury Academic.
    Explores and illuminates Slavoj Žižek's impact on our understanding of literary and cultural modernism.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  48
    Michel de Montaigne: Accidental Philosopher (review).Zahi Anbra Zalloua -2004 -Philosophy and Literature 28 (2):441-443.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Michel de Montaigne: Accidental PhilosopherZahi ZallouaMichel de Montaigne: Accidental Philosopher, by Ann Hartle ; 303 pp. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003. $60.00.Ann Hartle's new book is arguably the clearest and most compelling interpretation of Montaigne as a genuine philosopher since Hugo Friedrich's masterful Montaigne (1949). Her study is indeed an emphatic response to Friedrich's call to read Montaigne philosophically. Hartle derives her almost oxymoronic title from Montaigne's own (...) self-description as "a new figure: an unpremeditated and accidental philosopher." Taking Montaigne's moment of self-discovery à la lettre, Hartle systematically proceeds to elucidate the full meaning of Montaigne's observation. What emerges from her reading is a radical thinker who breaks with ancient philosophy and medieval theology. Her Montaigne, however, does not disavow the past but ultimately enriches it, building upon prior models. In this respect, the essayist practices the Renaissance art of imitation—creative imitation that repeats but also alters its exemplary model in a move to rival it. While Hartle exhibits an outstanding knowledge of the history of philosophy—from Plato to Heidegger, passing through Machiavelli, Hume, and Rousseau—her book is not itself a historical study nor a work in the history of ideas: she insists that her interpretation is conceptual rather than historical.What is accidental philosophy? It is foremost a non-authoritative, thoroughly human philosophy, one which takes as a sine qua non the recognition of the world's contingency—an awareness that things might have been radically different. Accidental philosophy thus represents nothing short of a displacement and transformation of reason, a calling into question of its traditional sovereign and divine-like status. (One thinks here of Aristotle's notion of the active intellect [nous poetikos], which he considers to be divine in man in Book X of the Nicomachean Ethics.) Rejecting the belief in an autonomous reason, Montaigne renders problematic the possibility of "deliberative philosophy" (accidental philosophy's counterpart): "the exercise of reason as rule within the soul, a place and function that reason claims for itself on the basis of its superiority with the hierarchy of nature." In his critique of reason—most eloquently displayed in the "Apology for Raymond Sebond," chapter 12 of [End Page 441] Book II of the Essays—Montaigne might be seen as proto-postmodernist, occupying a similar position as Nietzsche in a history of counter-Enlightenment thought. But such an interpretation, argues Hartle, is on the whole inaccurate, given Montaigne's commitment to truth.As would be expected in a book about Montaigne's philosophy, skepticism plays a major role in Hartle's positive assessment of the essayist. Skepticism has traditionally been interpreted in Montaigne scholarship either as a stage in the evolution of the essayist's thought, or as an expression of his fideism. The evolutionary reading was first championed by Pierre Villey in Les Sources et l'évolution des "Essais" de Montaigne (1933), in which he argued that Montaigne's thought evolved through three stages: Stoicism, Skepticism, and Naturalism (or Epicureanism). This now unpopular view was nevertheless recently reaffirmed by David Quint in his well-received Montaigne and the Quality of Mercy (1998). The essayist's fideism, on the other hand, is more readily accepted in Montaigne circles. It is commonly accepted that Montaigne's skepticism functions in a way that undermines reason's authority while leaving room for faith in religious matters. Hartle's understanding of Montaigne's skepticism differs in a major way from both of these accounts. She asks: "Does skepticism provide us with a complete and adequate understanding of Montaigne's philosophical activity?" Hartle offers a seemingly definitive answer: "Montaigne is not a skeptic" (p. 15). Yet, she makes her response more nuanced in several passage of her study, arguing again not for a clean break with ancient skep-ticism but with a profound transformation of this dominant philosophical school.What we have, then, is a "skeptical moment" rather than a full-fledged skeptical suspension of judgment. And it is in this moment that an openness to the possible—such as the discovery of the strange in the familiar—is made manifest. Hartle rightly points to Montaigne's discovery of his own... (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  32
    Afro-Pessimism With Žižek.Zahi Zalloua -2019 -Intertexts 23 (1):44-64.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  58
    Betting on Ressentiment: Žižek with Nietzsche.Zahi Zalloua -2012 -Symploke 20 (1-2):53-63.
  12.  48
    Derek Attridge on the Ethical Debates in Literary Studies.Zahi Zalloua -2009 -Substance 38 (3):18-30.
  13.  26
    Decolonial Particularity or Abstract Universalism? No, Thanks!: The Case of the Palestinian Question.Zahi Zalloua -2019 -International Journal of Žižek Studies 13 (1).
    Taking “capitalism itself as the ultimate horizon of the political situation” enables us to reframe binationalism and the Palestinian question. It helps to underscore binationalism as a universalist project, engaged in a fight against domination and exploitation. Seeking economic justice at home invariably links the Palestinian plight to other labor movements in Israel and elsewhere in the region. The solidarity of workers can effectively challenge the interests of the few, de naturalize their exploitation, and foreground binationalism as a socio-economic project, (...) not limited to its own particularist interests, but “grounded in the ‘part of no-part,’ the singular universality exemplified in those who lack a determined place in the social totality, who are ‘out of place’ in it”. If decoloniality and others fetishize the enemy, over-emphasizing his or her exceptionality, and thus always risk reifying the antagonism, binationalism, if it is to be transformative, must embrace its role as a supplement to the Palestinian/Israeli antagonism, taking the task of co-existence, of living together with each other’s neighbor, as an urgent ethico-political challenge, fully cognizant that there is no guarantee of success. And each is killing the other by the window. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  54
    Ethics and the Inventive Work.Zahi Zalloua,Gaurav Majumdar,Paul Allen Miller,Gerald Bruns,Gabriel Riera,Lynne Huffer,Alan Singer &Steven Miller -2009 -Substance 38 (3):113-124.
  15.  23
    Foucault as Educator: The Question of Technology and Learning How to Read Differently.Zahi Anbra Zalloua -2004 -Symploke 12 (1):232-247.
  16.  28
    Filth: Dirt, Disgust, and Modern Life (review).Zahi Zalloua -2007 -Symploke 15 (1):390-392.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  41
    Fidelity to the Unruly.Zahi Zalloua -2009 -Substance 38 (3):3-17.
  18.  27
    Infant Figures: The Death of the Infants and Other Scenes of Origin (review).Zahi Zalloua -2001 -Symploke 9 (1):194-195.
  19.  11
    Montaigne and the ethics of skepticism.Zahi Anbra Zalloua -2005 - Charlottesville, Va.: Rookwood Press.
    Unique comprehensive anthology of standard and non-standard short fiction by Stael, Denon, Stendhal, Chateaubriand, Balzac, Sand, Mérimée, Desbordes-Valmore, Flaubert, Hugo, Zola, Huysmans, Rachilde, Schwob, Barbey-d'Aurevilly, and Villiers de l'Isle d'Adam. Important new theoretical/historical introduction; incisive critical preface to, and up-to-date bibliography on, each author and richly annotated work.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20. Objects of desire : chosisme after object-oriented ontology.Zahi Zalloua -2023 - In Jeffrey R. Di Leo & Zahi Anbra Zalloua,Understanding Žižek, understanding modernism. New York: Bloomsbury Academic.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  44
    Retrieving Experience: Subjectivity and Recognition in Feminist Politics (review).Zahi Zalloua -2002 -Symploke 10 (1):212-214.
  22. Theory's autoimmunity.Zahi Zalloua -2016 - In Jeffrey R. Di Leo,Dead theory: Derrida, death, and the afterlife of theory. New York, NY, USA: Bloomsbury Academic, an imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  7
    Theory's autoimmunity: skepticism, literature, and philosophy.Zahi Anbra Zalloua -2018 - Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press.
    Introduction. Toward a hermeneutics of skepticism -- Montaignean meditations -- Ideology, critique, and the event of literature -- Irony, power, and the death drive -- Queering difference, or the feminine logic of the "non-all" -- Immunizing ontology : the speculative turn -- Conclusion. Desire of the theorist.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  38
    The Cambridge Companion to Levinas (review).Zahi Anbra Zalloua -2005 -Symploke 13 (1):357-358.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  19
    The Ethics of Inscience in Montaigne's "Of Physiognomy".Zahi Zalloua -2008 -Mediaevalia 29 (2):125-135.
  26.  34
    The Future of an Ethics of Difference After Hardt and Negri’sEmpire.Zahi Zalloua -2008 -Symploke 16 (1-2):127-152.
  27.  28
    Theorizing Hunger.Zahi Zalloua -2011 -Symploke 19 (1-2):7-9.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp