Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'Species, Natural Kinds'

949 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  486
    Biological species:Naturalkinds, individuals, or what?Michael Ruse -1987 -British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (2):225-242.
    What are biological species? Aristotelians and Lockeans agree that they arenaturalkinds; but, evolutionary theory shows that neither traditional philosophical approach is truly adequate. Recently, Michael Ghiselin and David Hull have argued that species are individuals. This claim is shown to be against the spirit of much modern biology. It is concluded that species arenaturalkinds of a sort, and that any 'objectivity' they possess comes from their being at the focus of a consilience (...) of inductions. (shrink)
    Direct download(10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  2.  63
    NaturalKinds, Species, and Races.Yuichi Amitani -2015 -Kagaku Tetsugaku 48 (1):35-48.
    In _Realism and Naturalizing Knowledge_ (Keisho Shobo, 2013), Ryo Uehara carefully formulates the homeostatic property cluster theory ofnaturalkinds and expands it by applying this framework to artifacts and knowledge and thereby drawing them in the naturalistic picture of the world. This is a substantial addition to the development of naturalistic philosophy in Japan. In this essay I shall make general comments on his account ofnaturalkinds in the following respects: Uehara's distinction between real (...) and nominalkinds, his objection to the species-as-individual thesis, the relative lack of attention to the distinction between the realism ofnaturalkinds and the scientific realism, and finally, races as possiblenaturalkinds. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. NaturalKinds and Biological Species.Laurance J. Splitter -1982
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  111
    Biological Species AreNaturalKinds.Crawford L. Elder -2008 -Southern Journal of Philosophy 46 (3):339-362.
    This paper argues that typical biological species arenaturalkinds, on a familiar realist understanding ofnaturalkinds—classes of individuals across which certain properties cluster together, in virtue of the causal workings of the world. But the clustering is far from exceptionless. Virtually no properties, or property-combinations, characterize every last member of a typical species—unless they can also appear outside the species. This motivates some to hold that what ties together the members of a species is (...) the ability to interbreed, others that it is common descent. Yet others hold that species are scattered individuals,of which organisms are parts rather than members. But not one of these views absolves us of the need to posit a typical phenotypic profile. Vagueness is here to stay. Some seek to explain the vagueness by saying species are united by “homeostatic property clusters”; but this view collapses into the more familiar realist picture. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  5. NaturalKinds.Zdenka Brzović -2018 -Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    A large part of our exploration of the world consists in categorizing or classifying the objects and processes we encounter, both in scientific and everyday contexts. There are various, perhaps innumerable, ways to sort objects into differentkinds or categories, but it is commonly assumed that, among the countless possible types of classifications, one group is privileged. Philosophy refers to such categories asnaturalkinds. Standard examples of suchkinds include fundamental physical particles, chemical elements, and (...) biological species. The termnatural does not imply thatnaturalkinds ought to categorize only naturally occurring stuff or objects. Candidates fornaturalkinds can include man-made substances, such as synthetic elements, that can be created in a laboratory. The naturalness in question is not the naturalness of the entities being classified, but that of the groupings themselves. Groupings that are artificial or arbitrary are notnatural; they are invented or imposed on nature.Naturalkinds, on the other hand, are not invented, and many assume that scientific investigations should discover them. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  6.  135
    Biological species asnaturalkinds.David B. Kitts &David J. Kitts -1979 -Philosophy of Science 46 (4):613-622.
    The fact that the names of biological species refer independently of identifying descriptions does not support the view of Ghiselin and Hull that species are individuals. Species may be regarded asnaturalkinds whose members share an essence which distinguishes them from the members of other species and accounts for the fact that they are reproductively isolated from the members of other species. Because evolutionary theory requires that species be spatiotemporally localized their names cannot occur in scientific laws. (...) Ifnatural kind status is denied to species on this ground, it must also be denied to most classes of concrete entities which are now accorded such status. (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  7.  103
    Species, determinates andnaturalkinds.Richmond H. Thomason -1969 -Noûs 3 (1):95-101.
  8.  12
    The Mitonuclear Compatibility Species Concept, Intrinsic Essentialism, andNaturalKinds.Kyle Heine &Elay Shech -2025 -Philosophy of Science ( Issue 1):59 - 81.
    This essay introduces, develops, and appraises the mitonuclear compatibility species concept (MCSC), identifying advantages and limitations with respect to alternative species concepts. While the consensus amongst most philosophers of biology is that (kind) essentialism about species is mistaken, and that species at most have relational essences, we appeal to the MCSC to defend thoroughgoing intrinsic essentialism. Namely, the doctrine that species have fully intrinsic essences and, thus, arenaturalkinds (of sorts), while allowing that species aren’t categorically distinct.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  673
    Words, Species, andKinds.J. T. M. Miller -2021 -Metaphysics 4 (1):18–31.
    It has been widely argued that words are analogous to species such that words, like species, arenaturalkinds. In this paper, I consider the metaphysics of word-kinds. After arguing against an essentialist approach, I argue that word-kinds are homeostatic property clusters, in line with the dominant approach to other biological and psychologicalkinds.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  10.  191
    Natural Kind Semantics for a Classical Essentialist Theory ofKinds.Javier Belastegui -2024 -Review of Symbolic Logic 17 (2).
    The aim of this paper is to provide a completeNatural Kind Semantics for an Essentialist Theory ofKinds. The theory is formulated in two-sorted first order monadic modal logic with identity. Thenatural kind semantics is based on Rudolf Willes Theory of Concept Lattices. The semantics is then used to explain several consequences of the theory, including results about the specificity (species–genus) relations betweenkinds, the definitions ofkinds in terms of genera and specific (...) differences and the existence of negativekinds. First, I show under which conditions the Hierarchy principle, which has been subjected to counterexamples in the literature, holds. I also show that a different principle about the species–genus relations betweenkinds, namely Kant’s Law, follows from the essentialist theory. Second, I introduce two new operations forkinds and show that they can be used to provide traditional definitions ofkinds in terms of genera and specific differences. Finally, I show that these operations of specific difference induce, for each kind, a uniquely specified contrary kind and a uniquely specified subcontrary kind, which can be used as semantic values for non-classical predicate negations of kind terms. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Species andkinds: a critique of Rieppel’s “one of a kind” account of species.Thomas A. C. Reydon -2009 -Cladistics 25 (6):660-667.
    A major issue in philosophical debates on the species problem concerns the opposition between two seemingly incompatible views of the metaphysics of species: the view that species are individuals and the view that species arenaturalkinds. In two recent papers in this journal, Olivier Rieppel suggested that this opposition is much less deep than it seems at first sight. Rieppel used a recently developed philosophical account ofnatural kindhood, namely Richard Boyd’s “homeostatic property cluster” theory, to (...) argue that every species taxon can be conceived of as an individual that constitutes the single member of its own specificnatural kind. In this paper I criticize Rieppel’s approach and argue that it does not deliver what it is supposed to, namely an account of species askinds about which generalized statements can be made. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12.  191
    Is ‘Natural Kind’ aNatural Kind Term?John Dupré -2002 -The Monist 85 (1):29-49.
    The traditional home for the concept of anatural kind in biology is of course taxonomy, the sorting of organisms into a nested hierarchy ofkinds. Many taxonomists and most philosophers of biology now deny that it is possible to sort organisms intonaturalkinds. Many do not think that biological taxonomy sorts them intokinds at all, but rather identifies them as parts of historical individuals. But at any rate if the species, genera and (...) so on of biological taxonomy arekinds at all, there are various respects in which they fall short of the traditional requirements of naturalness. The members of biological taxa lack essential properties that make them members of a particular kind: any properties specific enough to belong only to members of the kind cannot be assumed to belong to all members of the kind. And if there are laws applying to members of biological taxa they are laws of very minor and local importance and, in view of the preceding point, at best probabilistic. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  13.  385
    NaturalKinds in Evolution and Systematics: Metaphysical and Epistemological Considerations.Ingo Brigandt -2009 -Acta Biotheoretica 57 (1-2):77-97.
    Despite the traditional focus on metaphysical issues in discussions ofnaturalkinds in biology, epistemological considerations are at least as important. By revisiting the debate as to whether taxa arekinds or individuals, I argue that both accounts are metaphysically compatible, but that one or the other approach can be pragmatically preferable depending on the epistemic context. Recent objections against construing species as homeostatic property clusterkinds are also addressed. The second part of the paper broadens (...) the perspective by considering homologues as another example ofnaturalkinds, comparing them with analogues as functionally definedkinds. Given that there are various types ofnaturalkinds, I discuss the different theoretical purposes served by diverse kind concepts, suggesting that there is no clear-cut distinction betweennaturalkinds and otherkinds, such as functionalkinds. Rather than attempting to offer a unique metaphysical account of ‘natural’ kind, a more fruitful approach consists in the epistemological study of how differentnatural kind concepts are employed in scientific reasoning. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  14.  19
    The idionomy ofnaturalkinds and the biological concept of a species.M. D. Stafleu -2000 -Philosophia Reformata 65 (2):154-169.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  84
    Species, essences and the names ofnaturalkinds.T. E. Wilkerson -1994 -Philosophical Quarterly 44 (170):1-19.
  16.  44
    Naturalkinds and a posteriori necessities: Putnam pro Kripke, Putnam versus Kripke.Dmytro Sepetyi -2023 -Filosofska Dumka (Philosophical Thought) 2:159-171.
    Most contemporary analytic philosophers of language and mind accept the view that there is a wide class of terms, “natural kind terms”, which includes names of substances (the most common example is “water”), of species of animals, and of many otherkinds of things in nature, whose meaning and reference is determined in the way explained by the theory developed in the 1970s by Saul Kripke and Hilary Putnam. The theory is often referred to as “the Kripke-Putnam theory” (...) and is supposed to have such achievements as the overthrow of the earlier dominant Fregean theory of word-meanings (dubbed “descriptivism” by Kripke) as determined by the concepts in our minds, providing support for the “externalist” approach to linguistic meanings (in line with Putnam’s claim that “"Meanings" just ain’t in the head”), and the discovery that there is a wide class of truths (such as that water is H20) that are both a posteriori and necessary. Although the priority in the development of this theory belongs to Kripke, it could hardly gain such a wide acceptance without contributions by Putnam, which turned out to be very influential. However, the habitual idea of “the Kripke-Putnam theory”, as one theory, tends to play down the differences between Putnam’s and Kripke’s approaches and to hush up the fact that in his late works, of 1983 and 1990, Putnam revised and abandoned pretty much of his “Kripkean” views of 1970-ies; in particular, repudiated the pride of Kripke’s theory, the idea of necessary a posteriori truths. This article makes critical analysis and evaluation of Putnam’s ideas and arguments usually credited as important contributions to “the Kripke-Putnam theory”, and highlights the main points of the revision in late Putnam’s works. The case is made that Putnam's famous argument for externalism about meanings, the Twin-Earth thought experiment, is question-begging, fails to do justice to likely changes in the meanings of words with the development of knowledge, and conflicts with the linguistic practice in the relevantly similar case of “jade”. Putnam's argument for externalism from the division of linguistic labour is not cogent too, because “semantic deference” is itself a matter of what is there in “heads” - of some (non-expert) heads deferring to other (recognised as expert) heads. Eventually, on close inspection and in the light of Putnam's later reexplanation and revision, his account of meaning and reference turns out to be a sophisticated variety of conceptualism/internalism. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Biological essentialism and the tidal change ofnaturalkinds.John S. Wilkins -2013 -Science & Education 22 (2):221-240.
    The vision ofnaturalkinds that is most common in the modern philosophy of biology, particularly with respect to the question whether species and other taxa arenaturalkinds, is based on a revision of the notion by Mill in A System of Logic. However, there was another conception that Whewell had previously captured well, which taxonomists have always employed, ofkinds as being types that need not have necessary and sufficient characters and properties, or (...) essences. These competing views employ different approaches to scientific methodologies: Mill’s class-kinds are not formed by induction but by deduction, while Whewell’s type-kinds are inductive. More recently, phylogenetickinds (clades, or monophyletic-kinds) are inductively projectible, and escape Mill’s strictures. Mill’s version represents a shift in the notions ofkinds from the biological to the physical sciences. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  18.  112
    NaturalKinds and Biological Realisms.Michael Devitt -2011 - In Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O'Rourke & Matthew H. Slater,Carving nature at its joints: natural kinds in metaphysics and science. Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.
    This chapter discusses issues regarding realism, specifically the realism issues in biology. The discussion starts with an issue that arises from the debate between “species monists” who argue that there exists only one good “species concept” and “species pluralists” who insist that there are many. The various species concepts are then summarized and the motivation for pluralism outlined. An overview of realism is provided here, specifically, of a“realism about the external world.” Finally, the central question, focusing on the apparent clash (...) between Marc Ereshefsky’s “pluralistic antirealism” and Philip Kitcher’s “pluralistic realism,” is addressed. The chapter concludes by considering “realism” issues about genera and higher categories in the Linnaean hierarchy. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  19.  41
    Money as aNatural Kind.Rico Hauswald -2018 -Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy 49:29-32.
    According to John Searle, money is an institutional entity; it is among the things “that exist only because we believe them to exist”. I believe that Searle’s view is correct in some important respects. At the same time, I argue that money is a real ornatural kind, much in the same way as biological species or chemical substances are realkinds about which empirical knowledge can be accumulated. The paper attempts to show the consistency of these assumptions. (...) My argument proceeds in two steps. First, I introduce homeostatic property cluster theory and characterize it as the most adequate account of realkinds that has been developed so far. Second, I reexamine, and to some extent reinterpret, money – one of Searle’s central examples of an institutional kind – and argue that it meets the conditions of a real kind as stated by HPC theory. An important part of the argument is a reconsideration of the circularity problem, i.e., the problem that Searle’s way of analyzing money already seems to presuppose the concept of money. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  687
    Cell Types asNaturalKinds.Matthew H. Slater -2013 -Biological Theory 7 (2):170-179.
    Talk of different types of cells is commonplace in the biological sciences. We know a great deal, for example, about human muscle cells by studying the same type of cells in mice. Information about cell type is apparently largely projectible across species boundaries. But what defines cell type? Do cells come pre-packaged into differentnaturalkinds? Philosophical attention to these questions has been extremely limited [see e.g., Wilson (Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays, pp 187–207, 1999; Genes and the Agents (...) of Life, 2005; Wilson et al. Philos Top 35(1/2):189–215, 2007)]. On the face of it, the problems we face in individuating cellularkinds resemble those biologists and philosophers of biology encountered in thinking about species: there are apparently many different (and interconnected) bases on which we might legitimately classify cells. We could, for example, focus on their developmental history (a sort of analogue to a species’ evolutionary history); or we might divide on the basis of certain structural features, functional role, location within larger systems, and so on. In this paper, I sketch an approach to cellularkinds inspired by Boyd’s Homeostatic Property Cluster Theory, applying some lessons from this application back to general questions about the nature ofnaturalkinds. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  21.  151
    Typology andNaturalKinds in Evo-Devo.Ingo Brigandt -2021 - In Nuño De La Rosa Laura & Müller Gerd,Evolutionary Developmental Biology: A Reference Guide. Springer. pp. 483-493.
    The traditional practice of establishing morphological types and investigating morphological organization has found new support from evolutionary developmental biology (evo-devo), especially with respect to the notion of body plans. Despite recurring claims that typology is at odds with evolutionary thinking, evo-devo offers mechanistic explanations of the evolutionary origin, transformation, and evolvability of morphological organization. In parallel, philosophers have developed non-essentialist conceptions ofnaturalkinds that permitkinds to exhibit variation and undergo change. This not only facilitates a (...) construal of species and higher taxa asnaturalkinds, but also broadens our perspective on the diversity ofkinds found in biology. There are many differentnaturalkinds relevant to the investigative and explanatory aims of evo-devo, including homologues and developmental modules. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  114
    Monophyly, paraphyly, andnaturalkinds.Olivier Rieppel -2005 -Biology and Philosophy 20 (2-3):465-487.
    A long-standing debate has dominated systematic biology and the ontological commitments made by its theories. The debate has contrasted individuals and the part – whole relationship with classes and the membership relation. This essay proposes to conceptualize the hierarchy of higher taxa is terms of a hierarchy of homeostatic property clusternaturalkinds (biological species remain largely excluded from the present discussion). The reference ofnatural kind terms that apply to supraspecific taxa is initially fixed descriptively; the (...) extension of thosenatural kind terms is subsequently established by empirical investigation. In that sense, classification precedes generalization, and description provides guidance to empirical investigation. The reconstruction of a hierarchy of (homeostatic property cluster)naturalkinds is discussed in the light of cladistic methods of phylogeny reconstruction. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  23.  76
    Biological Individuals andNaturalKinds.Olivier Rieppel -2013 -Biological Theory 7 (2):162-169.
    This paper takes a hierarchical approach to the question whether species are individuals ornaturalkinds. The thesis defended here is that species are spatiotemporally located complex wholes (individuals), that are composed of (i.e., include) causally interdependent parts, which collectively also instantiate a homeostatic property cluster (HPC)natural kind. Species may form open or closed genetic systems that are dynamic in nature, that have fuzzy boundaries due to the processual nature of speciation, that may have leaky boundaries (...) as is manifest in lateral gene transfer and introgression, that may be of multiple origins through hybridization, and that may split and merge and split again over time. The identity conditions of species qua individuals will have to be anchored in their history, rather than in their unique evolutionary origin. Species qua historically conditioned HPCnaturalkinds requires the kind to be mereologically structured, subject to the part-whole relation rather than the membership relation. This implies that there can be more than one kind ofnaturalkinds. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  813
    Group Minds andNaturalKinds.Robert D. Rupert -forthcoming -Avant: Trends in Interdisciplinary Studies.
    The claim is frequently made that structured collections of individuals who are themselves subjects of mental and cognitive states – such collections as courts, countries, and corporations – can be, and often are, subjects of mental or cognitive states. And, to be clear, advocates for this so-called group-minds hypothesis intend their view to be interpreted literally, not metaphorically. The existing critical literature casts substantial doubt on this view, at least on the assumption that groups are claimed to instantiate the same (...) species of mental and cognitive properties as individual humans. In this essay, I evaluate a defensive move made by some proponents of the group-oriented view: to concede that group states and individual states aren’t of the same specificnaturalkinds, while holding that groups instantiate different species of mental or cognitive states – perhaps a different species of cognition itself – from those instantiated by humans. In order to evaluate this defense of group cognition, I develop a view ofnaturalkinds – or at least of the sort of evidence that supports inferences to the sameness ofnatural kind – a view I have previous dubbed the ‘tweak-and-extend’ theory. Guided by the tweak-and-extend approach, I arrive at a tentative conclusion: that what is common to models of individual cognitive processing and models of group processing does not suffice to establish sameness of cognitive (or mental)kinds, properties, or state-types, not even at a generic or overarching level. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  229
    How to Philosophically TackleKinds without Talking About ‘NaturalKinds’.Ingo Brigandt -2020 -Canadian Journal of Philosophy 52 (3):356-379.
    Recent rival attempts in the philosophy of science to put forward a general theory of the properties that all (and only)naturalkinds across the sciences possess may have proven to be futile. Instead, I develop a general methodological framework for how to philosophically studykinds. Any kind has to be investigated and articulated together with the human aims that motivate referring to this kind, where differentkinds in the same scientific domain can answer to different (...) concrete aims. My core contention is that non-epistemic aims, including environmental, ethical, and political aims, matter as well. This is defended and illustrated based on several examples ofkinds, with particular attention to the role of social-political aims: species, race, gender, as well as personality disorders and oppositional defiant disorder as psychiatrickinds. Such non-epistemic aims and values need not always be those personally favoured by scientists, but may have to reflect values that matter to relevant societal stakeholders. Despite the general agenda to study ‘kinds,’ I argue that philosophers should stop using the term ‘naturalkinds,’ as this label obscures the relevance of humans interests and the way in which manykinds are based on contingent social processes subject to human responsibility. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  26. NaturalKinds & Symbiosis.Emma Tobin -unknown
    Biological species are often taken as counterexamples to essentialist accounts ofnaturalkinds. Essentialists like Ellis (2001) agree with nominalists that because biologicalkinds evolve, any distinctions betweenkinds of biological kind must ultimately be arbitrary. The resulting vagueness in the extension ofnatural kind predicates in the case of species has led to the claim that species ought to be construed as individuals rather thankinds (Ghiselin 1974, 1987; Hull 1976, 1978). I examine (...) the possibility that causal features extrinsic to the properties ofnaturalkinds are responsible for establishing the unity of the properties of anatural kind. I reject the intuitive idea that laws of nature might act as such an external mechanism because this would entail an account of ceteris paribus biological laws, where there are no plausible truthmakers in terms ofkinds or properties. I suggest instead that symbiosis is a plausible external causal mechanism, which explains the evolution of homeostasis innatural kind clusters. This involves the acceptance of an expanded account of evolutionary development as cooperative symbiosis. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Gender Is aNatural Kind with a Historical Essence.Theodore Bach -2012 -Ethics 122 (2):231-272.
    Traditional debate on the metaphysics of gender has been a contrast of essentialist and social-constructionist positions. The standard reaction to this opposition is that neither position alone has the theoretical resources required to satisfy an equitable politics. This has caused a number of theorists to suggest ways in which gender is unified on the basis of social rather than biological characteristics but is “real” or “objective” nonetheless – a position I term social objectivism. This essay begins by making explicit the (...) motivations for, and central assumptions of, social objectivism. I then propose that gender is better understood as a real kind with a historical essence, analogous to the biologist’s claim that species are historical entities. I argue that this proposal achieves a better solution to the problems that motivate social objectivism. Moreover, the account is consistent with a post-positivist understanding of the classificatory practices employed within thenatural and social sciences. (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  28.  241
    On the logic ofnaturalkinds.Nino Cocchiarella -1976 -Philosophy of Science 43 (2):202-222.
    A minimal second order modal logic ofnaturalkinds is formulated. Concepts are distinguished from properties and relations in the conceptual-logistic background of the logic through a distinction between free and bound predicate variables. Not all concepts (as indicated by free predicate variables) need have a property or relation corresponding to them (as values of bound predicate variables). Issues pertaining to identity and existence as impredicative concepts are examined and an analysis of mass terms as nominalized predicates for (...)kinds of stuff is proposed. The minimal logic is extendible through a summum genus, an infima species or a partition principle fornaturalkinds. (shrink)
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  29. Are sexesnaturalkinds?Muhammad Ali Khalidi -2017 - In Shamik Dasgupta, Brad Weslake & Ravit Dotan,Current Controversies in Philosophy of Science. London: Routledge. pp. 163-176.
    Asking whether the sexes arenaturalkinds amounts to asking whether the categories, female and male, identify real divisions in nature, like the distinctions between biological species, or whether they mark merely artificial or arbitrary distinctions. The distinction between females and males in the animal kingdom is based on the relative size of the gametes they produce, with females producing larger gametes (ova) and males producing smaller gametes (sperm). This chapter argues that the properties of producing relatively large (...) and small gametes are causally correlated with a range of other properties in a wide variety of organisms, and this is what makes females and malesnaturalkinds in the animal kingdom. The chapter concludes with a discussion of the relationship between sex and gender: while the difference between the sexes is biologically grounded, the difference between genders is socially based. Since gender depends in part on the perception of sex, whether or not gender is real or not does not depend on whether sex is, since social reality is constituted in part by our perceptions. The claim that sexes arenaturalkinds in the animal kingdom does not imply that the biological differences among female and male humans do and should have social consequences. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  30.  107
    Naturalkinds and ecological niches — response to Johnson's paper.Melinda Hogan -1992 -Biology and Philosophy 7 (2):203-208.
  31.  172
    Locke onNaturalKinds and Essential Properties.Christopher Hughes Conn -2002 -Journal of Philosophical Research 27:475-497.
    The two opinions concerning real essences that Locke mentions in III.iii.17 represent competing theories about the way in which naturally occurring objects are divided into species. In this paper I explain what these competing theories amount to, why he denies the theory ofkinds that is embodied in the first of these opinions, and how this denial is related to his general critique of essentialism. I argue first, that we cannot meaningfully ask whether Locke accepts the existence of (...) class='Hi'>naturalkinds, per se, since he affirms the theory ofkinds that is embodied in the second opinion, while he denies the theory that is embodied in the first opinion. Second, I show that his denial of this theory is not solely or even primarily directed against the scholastic/Aristotelian theory of substantial forms, since he is most interested in refuting a corpuscularian version of this theory. And third, I argue that Locke’s anti-essentialism does not follow solely from his denial of (deeply objective)naturalkinds, since one could consistently make this denial and affirm the existence of de re essential properties. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  32.  41
    (1 other version)Synthetic Biology andNaturalKinds.Caleb Hazelwood -2017 -Stance 10:49-57.
    In the life sciences, biologists and philosophers lack a unifying concept of species—one that will reconcile intuitive demarcations of taxa with the fluidity of phenotypes found in nature. One such attempt at solving this “species problem” is known as Homeostatic Property Cluster theory (HPC), which suggests that species are not defined by singular essences, but by clusters of properties that a species tends to possess. I contend that the arbitrary nature of HPC’s kind criteria would permit a biological brand of (...) functionalism to inform species boundaries, thereby validating synthetic organisms as members of a species that do not belong. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  54
    Reflection onnaturalkinds. Introduction to the special issue onnaturalkinds: language, science, and metaphysics.Luis Fernández Moreno -2019 -Synthese 198 (Suppl 12):2853-2862.
    This article is an introduction to the Synthese Special Issue,NaturalKinds: Language, Science, and Metaphysics. The issue includes new contributions to some of the main questions involved in the present philosophical debates onnaturalkinds and onnatural kind terms. Those debates are relevant to philosophy of language, philosophy of science, and metaphysics. In philosophy of language it is highly debated what the meaning ofnatural kind terms is, how their reference is determined, (...) as well as whether there are differences and similarities between the semantics ofnatural kind terms and that of other sorts of kind terms. In philosophy of science,naturalkinds are relevant because they are the basis for scientific classifications and play an explanatory role in scientific theories; thus one aim of science is to discovernaturalkinds and theorize about them.Naturalkinds are also relevant in metaphysics, where many questions involvingnaturalkinds are debated and especially those concerning the sort of entities we refer to when usingnatural kind terms, i.e., the ontological status ofnaturalkinds; in this regard there are different views, such as conventionalism, realism and essentialism. Another metaphysical question is what it is that characterizes the naturalness of kind divisions. The introduction sketches the antecedents of some of the present views onnaturalkinds andnatural kind terms, and indicates some of the topics dealt with in the articles that make up the issue, which can be classified in the following groups: the metaphysics and epistemology ofnaturalkinds the semantics ofnatural kind terms and other kind terms questions on species and other related issues onnaturalkinds. However, many of the articles cover more than just one of these topics. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  140
    Smaller than a Breadbox: Scale andNaturalKinds.Julia R. Bursten -2018 -British Journal for Philosophy of Science 69 (1):1-23.
    ABSTRACT I propose a division of the literature onnaturalkinds into metaphysical worries, semantic worries, and methodological worries. I argue that the latter set of worries, which concern how classification influences scientific practices, should occupy centre stage in philosophy of science discussions aboutnaturalkinds. I apply this methodological framework to the problems of classifying chemical species and nanomaterials. I show that classification in nanoscience differs from classification in chemistry because the latter relies heavily on (...) compositional identity, whereas the former must consider additional properties, namely, size, shape, and surface chemistry. I use this difference to argue for a scale-dependent theory of scientific classification. _1_ Introduction _2_ The Methodological Problem ofKinds _3_ Chemical Kindhood: Reactivity, Microstructure, and the Structure–Property Paradigm _4_ Scale-Dependence and NanoscaleKinds _5_ Conclusion. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  35.  70
    Semantics forNatural Kind Terms.Harry Deutsch -1993 -Canadian Journal of Philosophy 23 (3):389 - 411.
    According to the well-known Kripke-Putnam view developed in Naming and Necessity and ‘The Meaning of Meaning’, proper names and ‘natural kind terms’ - words fornatural substances, species, and phenomena - are non-descriptional and rigid. A singular term is rigid if it has the same referent in every possible world, and is non-descriptional if, roughly speaking, its referent is not secured by purely descriptive conditions analytically tied to the term. Thus, ‘the inventor of bifocals’ is nonrigid and descriptional, (...) while ‘the unique even and prime integer’ is rigid and descriptional, and ‘Noam Chomsky’ is rigid and non-descriptional. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36.  89
    Limitations ofNatural Kind Talk in the Life Sciences: Homology and Other Cases. [REVIEW]Miles MacLeod -2013 -Biological Theory 7 (2):109-120.
    The aim of this article is to detail some reservations against the beliefs, claims, or presuppositions that current essentialistnatural kind concepts (including homeostatic property clusterkinds) model grouping practices in the life sciences accurately and generally. Such concepts fit reasoning into particular preconceived epistemic and semantic patterns. The ability of these patterns to fit scientific practice is often argued in support of homeostatic property cluster accounts, yet there are reasons to think that in the life sciences kind (...) concepts exhibit a diversity of grouping practices that are flattened out by conceptualizing them asnaturalkinds. Instead this article argues that the process of understanding grouping practices needs to start from a more neutral position independent of any ontological account. Following Love (Acta Biotheor 57:51–75, 2009) this paper suggests that typicalnatural kind concepts should be broached in the first place as grouping strategies that use a variety of semantic and epistemic tactics to apply group-bound information to tasks of explanation and understanding. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37. Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays.Robert Andrew Wilson (ed.) -1999 - MIT Press.
    This collection of original essays--by philosophers of biology, biologists, and cognitive scientists--provides a wide range of perspectives on species. Including contributions from David Hull, John Dupre, David Nanney, Kevin de Queiroz, and Kim Sterelny, amongst others, this book has become especially well-known for the three essays it contains on the homeostatic property cluster view ofnaturalkinds, papers by Richard Boyd, Paul Griffiths, and Robert A. Wilson.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  38.  146
    Definition and the Epistemology ofNaturalKinds in Aristotle.Nathanael Stein -2018 -Metaphysics 1 (1):33–51.
    We have reason to think that a fundamental goal ofnatural science, on Aristotle’s view, is to discover the essence-specifying definitions ofnaturalkinds—with biological species as perhaps the most obvious case. However, we have in the end precious little evidence regarding what an Aristotelian definition of the form of anatural kind would look like, and so Aristotle’s view remains especially obscure precisely where it seems to be most applicable. I argue that if we can (...) get a better understanding of how the forms ofnaturalkinds are or come to be known, and how they make things intelligible, we can get a better appreciation of the nature of form in general, as well as solve certain puzzles about form and definition. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  227
    Leibniz and Locke onnaturalkinds.Brandon C. Look -2009 - In Vlad Alexandrescu,Branching Off: The Early Moderns in Quest for the Unity of Knowledge. Bucharest: Zeta Books.
    One of the more interesting topics debated by Leibniz and Locke and one that has received comparatively little critical commentary is the nature of essences and the classification of thenatural world.1 This topic, moreover, is of tremendous importance, occupying a position at the intersection of the metaphysics of individual beings, modality, epistemology, and philosophy of language. And, while it goes back to Plato, who wondered if we could cut nature at its joints, as Nicholas Jolley has pointed out, (...) the debate between Leibniz and Locke has very clear similarities to the topic that has dominated the philosophy of language from the 1970s on: namely, the challenge mounted by Kripke, Kaplan, Putnam, and others against Russellian and Fregean descriptivist accounts of meaning. Yet, this topic is also, as Jolley writes, one of the “most elusive” in the debate between Leibniz and Locke.2 The purpose of this paper is to examine in detail Leibniz’s critique of Locke’s distinction between real and nominal essences. In doing so, I hope to show certain virtues in Leibniz’s account of metaphysics and philosophy of language that usually escape notice. While I wish to provide a general account of Leibniz’s disagreement with Locke, I also plan to focus on the nature of species andnaturalkinds. In my opinion, those who have treated this topic have not paid sufficient attention to Leibniz’s claims that “Essence is fundamentally nothing but the possibility of the thing under consideration” and “essences are everlasting because they only concern. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40. Locke on Real Essences, Intelligibility, andNaturalKinds.Jan-Erik Jones -2010 -Journal of Philosophical Research 35:147-172.
    In this paper I criticize arguments by Pauline Phemister and Matthew Stuart that John Locke's position in his An Essay Concerning Human Understanding allows fornaturalkinds based on similarities among real essences. On my reading of Locke, not only are similarities among real essences irrelevant to species, butnatural kind theories based on them are unintelligible.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41.  239
    Squaring the Circle:NaturalKinds with Historical Essences.Paul E. Griffiths -1999 - In Robert Andrew Wilson,Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays. MIT Press. pp. 209-228.
  42.  61
    NaturalKinds and Conceptual Change. [REVIEW]Jochen Faseler -2005 -Review of Metaphysics 59 (2):438-440.
    In chapter 1 it is argued that species and other biological taxa arenaturalkinds. This view is defended against accounts according to which biological taxa are notkinds at all, but individuals, and against accounts according to which biological taxa arekinds but notnatural. With regard to, LaPorte argues for the minimalist position that both the species-as-individuals interpretation as well as the species-as-kinds interpretation can be viewed as an adequate reconstruction of scientific (...) species-talk. With regard to, he first adopts the liberal conception that anatural kind is a kind with explanatory value—thus allowing for naturalness to come in degrees and respects—and he then shows that, unsurprisingly, biologicalkinds qualify asnatural. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Species:kinds of individuals or individuals of a kind.Olivier Rieppel -2007 -Cladistics 23:373-384.
    The “species-as-individuals” thesis takes species, or taxa, to be individuals. On grounds of spatiotemporal boundedness, any biological entity at any level of complexity subject to evolutionary processes is an individual. From evolutionary theory flows an ontology that does not countenance universal properties shared by evolving entities. If austere nominalism were applied to evolving entities, however, nature would be reduced to a mere flow of passing events, each one a blob in space–time and hence of passing interest only. Yet if there (...) is genuine biodiversity in nature, if nature is genuinely carved into species, and taxa, then these evolutionary entities will be genuinely differentiated into specifickinds, each species being one of its kind. Given the fact that evolving entities have un-sharp boundaries, an appropriately weak, “non-essentialist” concept ofnatural kind has to be invoked that does not allow for strong identity conditions. The thesis of this paper is that species are not either individuals, ornaturalkinds. Instead, species are complex wholes (particulars, individuals) that instantiate a specificnatural kind. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  44.  81
    The species category as a scientific kind.Caleb C. Hazelwood -2018 -Synthese 198 (Suppl 12):3027-3040.
    Marc Ereshefsky’s project of eliminative pluralism holds that, as there is no unifying feature among all species concepts, we ought to doubt the existence of the species category. Here, I argue that one promising strategy for saving the species category is to reframe it as anatural kind after the practice turn. I suggest situating the species category within a recent account ofnaturalkinds proposed by Marc Ereshefsky and Thomas Reydon called “scientifickinds”. Scientific (...) class='Hi'>kinds highlight ontological boundaries. More importantly, they recognize boundaries drawn from the lab and the field, not only from the armchair. The point of this exercise is to situate the species category within an account ofnaturalkinds that is sensitive to scientific practice. In order to argue for a realist interpretation of the species category, and not merely a pragmatic one, I rely on an approach to scientific metaphysics from Ken Waters that shifts the attention from “theory focused” to “practice-centered” analysis. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  70
    Mineral misbehavior: why mineralogists don’t deal innaturalkinds.Carlos Santana -2019 -Foundations of Chemistry 21 (3):333-343.
    Mineral species are, at first glance, an excellent candidate for an ideal set ofnaturalkinds somewhere beyond the periodic table. Mineralogists have a detailed set of rules and formal procedure for ratifying new species, and minerals are a less messy subject matter than biological species, psychological disorders, or even chemicals more broadly—all areas of taxonomy where the status of species asnaturalkinds has been disputed. After explaining how philosophers have tended to get mineralogy wrong (...) in discussions ofnaturalkinds, I show how minerals species don’t behave likenaturalkinds. They are defined on the basis of human intentionality, not merelynatural distinctions. They aren’t ideal grounds for inductive inference. And they don’t form a system that divides nature along a set of equivalent joints. While this is a regrettable outcome to those of us who like the idea of science relying onnaturalkinds, I contend that mineralogy is doing just fine without anatural kind-based taxonomy, and may in fact be better off without one. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  46.  102
    Review of Laporte onnaturalkinds[REVIEW]Robert Wilson -2004 -Philosophy in Review 24:423-426.
    NaturalKinds and Conceptual Change is a refreshingly direct book that challenges a range of orthodox views in the philosophy of science (especially biology), the philosophy of language, and metaphysics. Amongst these are the views that species are individuals rather thannaturalkinds; that scientists discover the essences ofnaturalkinds; that the causal theory of reference has commonly-ascribed implications for realism and analyticity; that there is an unacceptable form of incommensurability entailed by descriptivism (...) about reference; and that there are good grounds, familiar since Quine, for thinking that there is no distinction of significance to be drawn between changes in meaning and changes in theory. LaPorte argues against all of these claims, and if you are curious about just how he does it, then this is a book for you. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  278
    Locke on Real Essence and Water as aNatural Kind: A Qualified Defence.E. J. Lowe -2011 -Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 85 (1):1-19.
    ‘Water is H2O’ is one of the most frequently cited sentences in analytic philosophy, thanks to the seminal work of Saul Kripke and Hilary Putnam in the 1970s on the semantics ofnatural kind terms. Both of these philosophers owe an intellectual debt to the empiricist metaphysics of John Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding, while disagreeing profoundly with Locke about the reality ofnaturalkinds. Locke employs an intriguing example involving water to support his view that (...) class='Hi'>kinds (or ‘species’), such as water and gold, are the workmanship of the human mind. This is the point of his story about a winter visitor to England from Jamaica, who is astonished to find that the water in his basin has turned solid overnight, and proceeds to call it ‘hardened water’. Locke criticizes this judgement, maintaining that it is more consonant with common sense to regard water and ice as differentkinds of substance. Putnam, by implication, disagrees. Deploying his imaginary example of Twin Earth—a distant planet where a watery-looking substance, XYZ, rather than H2O, fills the oceans and rivers—he maintains that common sense supports the judgement that XYZ and H2O, despite their superficial similarity, are not the same kind of substance, precisely because their molecular compositions are different. Here it will be argued that both views are mistaken, but that, in this dispute, Locke has more right on his side than his modern opponents do. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  48. Using semantic deference to test an extension of indexical externalism beyondnatural-kind terms.Philippe De Brabanter &Bruno Leclercq -unknown
    We offer a new outlook on the vexed question of the reference ofnatural-kind terms. Since Kripke and Putnam, there is a widespread assumption thatnatural-kind terms function just like proper names: they designate their referents directly and they are rigid designators: their reference is unchanged even in worlds in which the referent lacks some or all the properties associated with it in the actual world, and which are useful to us in identifying that referent. There have, however, (...) been heated debates about what should be taken as anatural-kind term. Some challenge the very existence of a separate category ofnatural-kind terms ; some their being directly referential ; some raise the possibility that direct reference extends to terms beyond those usually assumed to fall under the category, e.g. to ‘polemical’ terms. When these debates turn on the question of whatnaturalkinds are, they take on a strong epistemological or metaphysical dimension. We think the issues can be clarified within the limits of the philosophy of language: by looking into what ranges of general terms are perceived by speakers as rigid designators ofnaturalkinds. The first step to take is to ground the variouskinds of semantic externalism in distinct brands of semantic deference. This we define as speakers’ being disposed to use words in line with the norms of their linguistic community and as consenting to being corrected when it is manifest that their use and understanding of a word does not match common practice. When those dispositions are present, speakers defer semantically to something beyond themselves. Here, our focus is on spotting the words for which speakers would defer not to the current usage of the word in the linguistic community, nor to the current experts of the field to which the word pertains, but ultimately to the very nature of the referent of the term. When speakers’ deference conforms to that pattern, we argue, that is evidence that indexical externalism provides the right metasemantic account of how the meaning of the word is determined. In other words, one can say that the word is treated like anatural-kind term. But how can patterns of deference be measured? In an ongoing survey, participants are confronted with conditions that may prompt them to revise certain classificatory statements, e.g. An emu is a bird. Each condition makes salient one of the targets we have identified for deference: the community usage, the experts, the ‘world as it is’. In the condition that seeks to tap into the latter kind of deference, participants are presented with a scenario in which future scientific discoveries result in excluding from the extension of a term certain members currently thought to fall under that extension, e.g. discoveries that require excluding certain species now thought to be birds from the Aves class. The scenario is such that it is clear that the ‘discoveries’ bring us closer to the actual essence, if there is one, of birds. Our reasoning is that, if participants significantly modify their statements in the light of that scenario, they can be taken to ‘defer’ to the nature of the referent, thus vindicating indexical externalism. We test if words not normally assumed to benatural-kind terms – for instance summer, contract or rape – exhibit patterns of deference similar to those for bird. If so, then there’s a case for an extension of indexical externalism beyond the usual set of terms. What would be shown in this way is that speakers have something like realist intuitions with respect to words whose meaning is usually taken to be purely conventional or polemical. We are at the pre-test stage for the survey. We cannot yet report on our results. We should, however, have initial results by March, which, we believe, will enrich the observations made by previous empirical studies. References: Braisby, N., Franks, B. & Hampton, J. 1996. Essentialism, word use, and concepts. Cognition 59, 247-74./Genone, J. & Lombrozo, T. 2012. Concept possession, experimental semantics, and hybrid theories of reference. Philosophical Psychology 25, 717-742./Häggqvist, S. & Wikforss, Å. 2015. Experimental semantics: the case ofnatural kind terms, in J. Haukioja, Experimental Philosophy of Language, London, Bloomsbury./Jylkkä, J., Railo, H. & Haukioja, J. 2009. Psychological essentialism and semantic externalism: Evidence for externalism in lay speakers’ language use. Philosophical Psychology 22, 37-60./Mallon, R., Machery, E., Nichols, S. & Stich, S. 2009. Against arguments from reference, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79, 332-356./ Marconi, D. 1997. Language, Speech, and Communication. Lexical Competence. Cambridge : MIT Press./Moravcsik, J. 2016. Meaning, Creativity, and the Partial Inscrutability of the Human Mind, 2nd ed. Stanford: CSLI./Schroeter, L. & Schroeter, F. 2014. Normative concepts: a connectedness model, Philosophers’ Imprint 14, 1-26./ Wikforss, Å. 2010. Arenatural kind terms special?, in H. Beebee and N. Sabbarton-Leary, The Semantics and Metaphysics ofNaturalKinds, New York, Routledge, 64-83. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  38
    Natural Categories and HumanKinds: Classification in theNatural and Social Sciences by Muhammad Ali Khalidi.Stephen Braude -2015 -Journal of Scientific Exploration 29 (2).
    How do-or how should-we parse the world intokinds of things? Going back at least to Plato, most philosophers have done so with respect to some notion or other ofnaturalkinds. And many analyses ofnaturalkinds have been essentialistic-that is defining thosekinds with respect to universals, or some set of intrinsic properties, or necessary and sufficient conditions. And there's a long-standing dispute between thinkers who regard scientific categories asnatural (...) class='Hi'>kinds with essential properties fixed by nature-those that "cut nature at its joints"-and thinkers who maintain that our classifications and categories have no essence and instead merely reflect human interests and values. A typical example of the former would be "having a mass of 1.7 × 10-27," and examples of the latter would be the categories of "ADHD," "race," or "child abuse." Khalidi aims for an epistemic, naturalistic, non-essentialist, account ofnaturalkinds, one which comfortably embraces not only the usual candidates favored by essentialists (e.g., elementary particles, chemical elements, biological species), but also categories in the social and behavioral sciences. Drawing on cases from many scientific fields, from fluid mechanics and polymer science to virology and psychiatry, Khalidi argues that "naturalkinds are investigative or epistemickinds, in the sense that they are the categories revealed by our systematic attempts to gain knowledge of nature" (p. 43). Moreover, he claims thatnaturalkinds can be "fuzzy" (i.e. have indefinite boundaries), satisfy epistemic virtues to varying degrees, and be mind-dependent in a way that doesn't detract from their reality or objectivity. Although the book is pitched for a sophisticated and philosophically informed audience (and, needless to say, too complex to be adequately summarized in a brief notice such as this), it's clearly written, nuanced, compellingly argued, and worth the effort for JSE readers curious about the unavoidable metaphysical dimensions of doing science of any kind. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  548
    Realism, Essence, and Kind: Resuscitating Species Essentialism?Robert A. Wilson -1999 - In Robert Andrew Wilson,Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays. MIT Press. pp. 187-207.
    This paper offers an overview of "the species problem", arguing for a view of species as homeostatic property clusterkinds, positioning the resulting form of realism about species as an alternative to the claim that species are individuals and pluralistic views of species. It draws on taxonomic practice in the neurosciences, especially of neural crest cells and retinal ganglion cells, to motivate both the rejection of the species-as-individuals thesis and species pluralism.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
1 — 50 / 949
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp