Doesreliabilism have a temporality problem?Jeffrey Tolly -2019 -Philosophical Studies 176 (8):2203-2220.detailsMatthew Frise claims that reliabilist theories of justification have a temporality problem—the problem of providing a principled account of the temporal parameters of a process’s performance that determine whether that process is reliable at a given time. Frise considers a representative sample of principled temporal parameters and argues that there are serious problems with all of them. He concludes that the prospects for solving the temporality problem are bleak. Importantly, Frise argues that the temporality problem constitutes a new reason to (...) rejectreliabilism. On this point, I argue that Frise is mistaken. There are serious interpretive difficulties with Frise’s argument. In this essay, I show that there are principled and reasonable temporal parameters for the reliabilist to adopt that successfully undermine the interpretations of Frise’s argument that only invoke plausible premises. There are interpretations of Frise’s argument that leavereliabilism without a clear parameter solution. However, I argue that these interpretations invoke controversial premises that are at best unmotivated, and at worst they merely re-raise older disputes aboutreliabilism. In any event, the temporality problem fails to constitute a new reason to rejectreliabilism. (shrink)
Genericreliabilism and virtue epistemology.Ernest Sosa -1991 -Philosophical Issues 2:79-92.detailsProblems for GenericReliabilism lead to a more specific account of knowledge as involving the exercise of intellectual virtues or faculties.
Reliabilism and safety.Kelly Becker -2006 -Metaphilosophy 37 (5):691-704.details: Duncan Pritchard has recently highlighted the problem of veritic epistemic luck and claimed that a safety‐based account of knowledge succeeds in eliminating veritic luck where virtue‐based accounts and processreliabilism fail. He then claims that if one accepts a safety‐based account, there is no longer a motivation for retaining a commitment toreliabilism. In this article, I delineate several distinct safety principles, and I argue that those that eliminate veritic luck do so only if at least implicitly (...) committed toreliabilism. (shrink)
Reliabilism and imprecise credences.Weng Hong Tang -2020 -Philosophical Studies 178 (5):1463-1480.detailsWhat is it for an imprecise credence to be justified? It might be thought that this is not a particularly urgent question for friends of imprecise credences to answer. For one might think that its answer just depends on how a well-trodden issue in epistemology plays out—namely, that of which theory of doxastic justification, be itreliabilism, evidentialism, or some other theory, is correct. I’ll argue, however, that it’s difficult for reliabilists to accommodate imprecise credences, at least if we (...) understand such credences to be determinate first-order attitudes. If I’m right, reliabilists will have to reject imprecise credences, and friends of imprecise credences will have to rejectreliabilism. Near the end of the paper, I’ll also consider whetherreliabilism can accommodate indeterminate credences. (shrink)
StrategicReliabilism: Robust Reliability.J. D. Trout &Michael A. Bishop -2004 - In Michael A. Bishop & J. D. Trout,Epistemology and the Psychology of Human Judgment. New York: OUP USA.detailsThis chapter discusses StrategicReliabilism. The epistemological theory underlying Ameliorative Psychology is a view called StrategicReliabilism: Epistemic excellence involves the efficient allocation of cognitive resources to robustly reliable reasoning strategies applied to significant problems. StrategicReliabilism gives a systematic voice and a theoretical foundation to the long-standing success of SPRs while at the same time avoiding the most serious objections to traditional processreliabilism.
No categories
Reliabilist responses to the value of knowledge problem.Christian Piller -2009 -Grazer Philosophische Studien 79 (1):121-135.detailsAfter sketching my own solution to the Value of Knowledge Problem, which argues for a deontological understanding of justification and understands the value of knowing interesting propositions by the value we place on believing as we ought to believe, I discuss Alvin Goldman's and Erik Olsson's recent attempts to explain the value of knowledge within the framework of their reliabilist epistemology.
Reliabilism, scepticism, and evidentia in Ockham.Philip Choi -2019 -British Journal for the History of Philosophy 27 (1):23-45.detailsABSTRACTThe aim of this paper is to challenge the reliabilist interpretation of William Ockham 's epistemology. The discussion proceeds as follows. First, I analyse the reliabilist interpretation into two theses: a negative thesis I call the Anti-Internalism Thesis, according to which, for Ockham, epistemic justification does not depend on any internal factors that are accessible by reflection; a positive thesis I call the Reliability Thesis, according to which epistemic justification in Ockham depends on the reliability of a causal process through (...) which a given judgment is produced. Secondly, I argue that the Anti-Internalism Thesis fails since Ockham's notion of evidentness, which is at the heart of his theory of justification, strongly suggests that he posits an indispensable, internalist element of justification. Lastly, I argue that the Reliability Thesis also fails since not only can there be a reliable but inevident judgment in Ockham's framework, his emphasis on causality is best read not as talk of reliability, but as his emphasis on the relation between reason and what is based on reason. (shrink)
Internalism,Reliabilism, and Deontology.Michael Williams -2016 - In Hilary Kornblith & Brian McLaughlin,Goldman and his Critics. Malden, MA: Blackwell. pp. 1–21.detailsThis chapter focuses on a central element in all versions: the shift from an “internalist” to an “externalist” approach to understanding knowledge and justification. According to Goldman's version, knowledge is true belief acquired and sustained by some reliable cognitive process. As Goldman notes, the guidance‐deontological (GD) approach was the dominant approach prior to the Reliabilist Revolution. This chapter argues for two lemmas. The first is that Goldman has not adequately diagnosed the sources of the untenable internalism that is his principal (...) target: additional commitments must be brought to light. The second is that dispensing with these commitments opens the way to an approach to knowledge and justification that is “internalist” by a standard that Goldman himself recognizes, yet free of the drawbacks he brings to attention. The chapter concludes that internalist justification needs refinement, not rejection. This means, in turn, that the GD conception of justification also survives. (shrink)
No categories
Should Reliabilists Be Worried About Demon Worlds?Jack C. Lyons -2012 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 86 (1):1-40.detailsThe New Evil Demon Problem is supposed to show that straightforward versions ofreliabilism are false: reliability is not necessary for justification after all. I argue that it does no such thing. The reliabilist can count a number of beliefs as justified even in demon worlds, others as unjustified but having positive epistemic status nonetheless. The remaining beliefs---primarily perceptual beliefs---are not, on further reflection, intuitively justified after all. The reliabilist is right to count these beliefs as unjustified in demon (...) worlds, and it is a challenge for the internalist to be able to do so as well. (shrink)
Structuralreliabilism: inductive logic as a theory of justification.Kawalec Pawel -2002 - Kluwer Academic Publishers.detailsThis book revives inductive logic by bringing out the underlying epistemology. The resulting structural reliabilist theory propounds the view that justification supervenes on syntactic and semantic properties of sentences as justification-bearers. It is claimed to set up a genuine alternative to the prevailing theories of justification. Kawalec substantiates this claim by confronting structuralreliabilism with a number of epistemological problems. While the book is addressed to both professionals and students of philosophical logic, probability, epistemology, and philosophy of science, it (...) also surveys ideas central to the development of philosophy in the 20th century. It will be a valuable companion to multifarious graduate and postgraduate courses. (shrink)
Processreliabilism's Troubles with Defeat.Bob Beddor -2015 -Philosophical Quarterly 65 (259):145-159.detailsOne attractive feature of processreliabilism is its reductive potential: it promises to explain justification in entirely non-epistemic terms. In this paper, I argue that the phenomenon of epistemic defeat poses a serious challenge for processreliabilism’s reductive ambitions. The standard process reliabilist analysis of defeat is the ‘Alternative Reliable Process Account’ (ARP). According to ARP, whether S’s belief is defeated depends on whether S has certain reliable processes available to her which, if they had been used, would (...) have resulted in S not holding the belief in question. Unfortunately, ARP proves untenable. I show, by way of counterexample, that ARP fails to articulate either necessary or sufficient conditions on defeat. Process reliabilists must either provide an alternative reductive account of defeat or renounce their reductive aspirations. (shrink)
Reliabilism and Contemporary Epistemology: Essays.Alvin I. Goldman -2012 - New York: Oxford University Press.detailsThis is a collection of chapters by the leading proponent of processreliabilism, explaining its relation to rival and/or neighboring theories including evidentialism, other forms ofreliabilism, and virtue epistemology. It addresses other prominent themes in contemporary epistemology, such as the internalism/externalism debate, the epistemological upshots of experimental challenges to intuitional methodology, the source of epistemic value, and social epistemology. The Introduction addresses late-breaking responses to ongoing exchanges with friends, rivals, and critics ofreliabilism.
Reliabilism and the Suspension of Belief.Weng Hong Tang -2016 -Australasian Journal of Philosophy 94 (2):362-377.detailsWhat are the conditions under which suspension of belief—or suspension, for short—is justified? Process reliabilists hold that our beliefs are justified if and only if these are produced or sustained by reliable cognitive processes. But they have said relatively little about suspension. Perhaps they think that we may easily extend an account of justified belief to deal with justified suspension. But it's not immediately clear how we may do so; in which case, evidentialism has a distinct advantage overreliabilism. (...) In this paper, I consider some proposals as to how process reliabilists might seek to account for justified suspension. Although several of these proposals do not work, two are promising. The first such proposal appeals to the notion of propositional justification; the second involves weaving evidentialist elements intoreliabilism. I'll argue that the second proposal is better than the first. (shrink)
EsotericReliabilism.Kristoffer Ahlstrom-Vij -2021 -Episteme 18 (4):603-623.detailsSurvey data suggest that many philosophers arereliabilists, in believing that beliefs are justified iff produced by a reliable process. This is bad news ifreliabilism is true. Empirical results suggest that a commitment to reliable belief-formation leads to overconfident second-guessing of reliable heuristics. Hence, a widespread belief inreliabilism is likely to be epistemically detrimental by the reliabilist's own standard. The solution is a form of two-level epistemic consequentialism, where an esoteric commitment toreliabilism will be appropriate (...) for an enlightened few, while a form of epistemic fetishism – on which some heuristics are treated as fundamental epistemic norms – is appropriate for the rest of us. (shrink)
Reliabilism and the Testimony of Robots.Billy Wheeler -2020 -Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology 24 (3):332-356.detailsWe are becoming increasingly dependent on robots and other forms of artificial intelligence for our beliefs. But how should the knowledge gained from the “say-so” of a robot be classified? Should it be understood as testimonial knowledge, similar to knowledge gained in conversation with another person? Or should it be understood as a form of instrument-based knowledge, such as that gained from a calculator or a sundial? There is more at stake here than terminology, for how we treat objects as (...) sources of knowledge often has important social and legal consequences. In this paper, I argue that at least some robots are capable of testimony. I make my argument by exploring the differences between instruments and testifiers on a well-known account of knowledge:reliabilism. On this approach, I claim that the difference between instruments and testifiers as sources of knowledge is that only the latter are capable of deception. As some robots can be designed to deceive, so they too should be recognized as testimonial sources of knowledge. (shrink)
StrategicReliabilism: Epistemic Significance.J. D. Trout &Michael A. Bishop -2004 - In Michael A. Bishop & J. D. Trout,Epistemology and the Psychology of Human Judgment. New York: OUP USA.detailsThis chapter offers a framework for understanding significance that tolerates our incomplete knowledge of the conditions for human well-being. Topics discussed include the role of significance in StrategicReliabilism, a reason-based approach to significance, and the potential unavailability of objective reasons. It is argued that a proper understanding of the notion of epistemic significance is a core problem for any epistemological theory that claims to be able to guide reason, and that any epistemological view that gives a central place (...) to the notion of significance is bound to be deeply empirical. (shrink)
No categories
Isreliabilism a form of consequentialism?Jeffrey Dunn &Kristoffer Ahlstrom-Vij -2017 -American Philosophical Quarterly 54 (2):183-194.detailsReliabilism—the view that a belief is justified iff it is produced by a reliable process—is often characterized as a form of consequentialism. Recently, critics ofreliabilism have suggested that since it is a form of consequentialism,reliabilism condones a variety of problematic trade-offs involving cases where someone forms an epistemically deficient belief now that will lead her to more epistemic value later. In the present paper, we argue that the relevant argument againstreliabilism fails because it (...) equivocates. While there is a sense in whichreliabilism is a kind of consequentialism, it is not of a kind on which we should expect problematic trade-offs. (shrink)
Reliabilist justification (or knowledge) as a good truth-ratio.Jonathan E. Adler -2005 -Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86 (4):445–458.detailsFair lotteries offer familiar ways to pose a number of epistemological problems, prominently those of closure and of scepticism. Although these problems apply to many epistemological positions, in this paper I develop a variant of a lottery case to raise a difficulty with the reliabilist's fundamental claim that justification or knowledge is to be analyzed as a high truth-ratio (of the relevant belief-forming processes). In developing the difficulty broader issues are joined including fallibility and the relation of reliability to understanding.
FromReliabilism to Virtue Epistemology.Linda Zagzebski -2000 -The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 5:173-179.detailsIn Virtues of the Mind I object to processreliabilism on the grounds that it does not explain the good of knowledge in addition to the good of true belief. In this paper I wish to develop this objection in more detail, and will then argue that this problem pushes us first in the direction of two offspring of processreliabilism—facultyreliabilism and proper functionalism, and, finally, to a true virtue epistemology.
Reliabilism Defended.Jeffrey Tolly -2021 -Canadian Journal of Philosophy 51 (8):619-635.detailsReliabilism about knowledge states that a belief-forming process generates knowledge only if its likelihood of generating true belief exceeds 50 percent. Despite the prominence ofreliabilism today, there are very few if any explicit arguments forreliabilism in the literature. In this essay, I address this lacuna by formulating a new independent argument forreliabilism. As I explain,reliabilism can be derived from certain key knowledge-closure principles. Furthermore, I show how this argument can withstand John (...) Turri’s two recent objections toreliabilism: the argument from explanatory inference and the argument from achievements. (shrink)
Reliabilism and the Meliorative Project.Murray Clarke -2000 -The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 5:75-82.detailsIt has been suggested, recently and not so recently, by a number of analytic epistemologists that reliabilist and externalist accounts of justification and knowledge are inadequate responses to the goals of traditional epistemology and other goals of inquiry. But philosophers of science decryreliabilism and externalism because they are connected to traditional, analytic epistemology, an outmoded and utopian form of inquiry. Clearly, both groups of critics cannot be right. I think both groups are guilty of conceptual confusions that, once (...) clarified, should allow the naturalization project to stand forth in a rather attractive light. (shrink)
Reliabilism without Epistemic Consequentialism.Kurt L. Sylvan -2018 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (3):525-555.detailsPhilosophy and Phenomenological Research, EarlyView.
ProcessReliabilism, Prime Numbers and the Generality Problem.Frederik J. Andersen &Klemens Kappel -2020 -Logos and Episteme 11 (2):231-236.detailsThis paper aims to show that Selim Berker’s widely discussed prime number case is merely an instance of the well-known generality problem for processreliabilism and thus arguably not as interesting a case as one might have thought. Initially, Berker’s case is introduced and interpreted. Then the most recent response to the case from the literature is presented. Eventually, it is argued that Berker’s case is nothing but a straightforward consequence of the generality problem, i.e., the problematic aspect of (...) the case for processreliabilism (if any) is already captured by the generality problem. (shrink)
ProcessReliabilism and Virtue Epistemology.Ernest Sosa -2016 - In Hilary Kornblith & Brian McLaughlin,Goldman and his Critics. Malden, MA: Blackwell. pp. 125–148.detailsThis chapter explores the possibilities for rapprochement betweenreliabilism and evidentialism. It argues that the prospects for any such rapprochement betweenreliabilism and evidentialism are dim, and that the appearance to the contrary is mostly an illusion. The chapter draws on a paper by Jack Lyons, “Perception and virtuereliabilism”, so as to focus on the prospects for rapprochement through virtuereliabilism more specifically. Goldman's paper stops short of a full bipartisan theory of epistemic justification. The (...) chapter includes a subtle and detailed critique of evidentialism. The positive contribution of the chapter is divided into two parts. First it offers a way to think of “inferential” justification, and next it offers a way to understand “experiential” justification. According to processreliabilism, the epistemic justification of a belief derives from the reliability of the causal process that produces it. An attractive bipartisan avenue opens with a bi‐level epistemology. (shrink)
No categories
Reliabilism’s Memory Loss.Matthew Frise -2021 -Philosophical Quarterly 71 (3):565-585.detailsGenerativism about memory justification is the view that memory can generate epistemic justification. Generativism is gaining popularity, but process reliabilists tend to resist it. Processreliabilism explains the justification of beliefs by way of the reliability of the processes they result from. Some advocates ofreliabilism deny various forms of generativism. Other reliabilists reject or remain neutral about only the more extreme forms. I argue that an extreme form of generativism follows fromreliabilism. This result weakens a (...) long-standing argument forreliabilism. (shrink)
StrategicReliabilism: A Naturalistic Approach to Epistemology.Michael A. Bishop &J. D. Trout -2008 -Philosophy Compass 3 (5):1049-1065.detailsStrategicReliabilism is a framework that yields relative epistemic evaluations of belief-producing cognitive processes. It is a theory of cognitive excellence, or more colloquially, a theory of reasoning excellence (where 'reasoning' is understood very broadly as any sort of cognitive process for coming to judgments or beliefs). First introduced in our book, Epistemology and the Psychology of Human Judgment (henceforth EPHJ), the basic idea behind SR is that epistemically excellent reasoning is efficient reasoning that leads in a robustly reliable (...) fashion to significant, true beliefs. It differs from most contemporary epistemological theories in two ways. First, it is not a theory of justification or knowledge – a theory of epistemically worthy belief. StrategicReliabilism is a theory of epistemically worthy ways of forming beliefs. And second, StrategicReliabilism does not attempt to account for an epistemological property that is assumed to be faithfully reflected in the epistemic judgments and intuitions of philosophers. If SR makes recommendations that accord with our reflective epistemic judgments and intuitions, great. If not, then so much the worse for our reflective epistemic judgments and intuitions. (shrink)
Reliabilism, Lotteries, and Safaris.Mark V. McEvoy -2018 -Philosophical Forum 49 (3):325-333.detailsLottery puzzles involve an ordinary piece of knowledge which seems to imply knowledge of a so-called “lottery proposition,” which itself seems unknown: I might be said to know that I won’t be going on safari next year. But if I were to win the lottery, I would go, and I don’t know that I won’t win the lottery. Examples can be multiplied. Thus we seem left either with the paradoxical position of knowing certain ordinary propositions, but failing to know the (...) lottery propositions they imply, or else conceding to the skeptic. I present a version ofreliabilism according to which empirical knowledge is true belief produced by a reliable process causally connecting belief and fact. According to this theory, if my ordinary belief and my belief in the lottery proposition are suitably connected to the facts that render them true, both count as knowledge. In cases where my ordinary belief and my belief in the lottery proposition are not suitably connected to the relevant facts, neither count as knowledge. Thus the paradoxical air of lottery puzzles is removed, and skepticism is avoided. (shrink)
No categories
(1 other version)Virtue-Reliabilism and the Value of Knowledge: Classical and New Problems.Anne Meylan -2018 - In Heather D. Battaly,The Routledge Handbook of Virtue Epistemology. Routledge. pp. 317-329.detailsThis first part of this chapter presents the virtue-reliabilist answer to the classical value problems of knowledge. According to this solution, the reason why knowledge is a better cognitive state than what falls short of it —viz. mere true and true+Gettierized beliefs— is as follows: when a subject knows, she deserves credit for her true belief. The second part of this chapter is devoted to showing that this solution cannot be extended to solve the " new " value problem, that (...) is to say, the problem of explaining why some higher form of knowledge — what Sosa calls full knowledge— is better than some lower form of knowledge, viz. Sosa's animal knowledge. The basic problem for Sosa is that, when a subject fully knows, it is not necessarily the case that she deserves more credit than when she merely has animal knowledge. (shrink)
Export citation
Bookmark
Reliabilism 'naturalized'.Steven Miller &Marcel Fredericks -2002 -Social Epistemology 16 (4):367 – 376.detailsThe article is an attempt to better understand the objections to the doctrine of 'reliabilism' made by prominent epistemologists. The view argued for here is that while one extreme case of anti-reliabilism seems to be the paradigm case against the entire concept, this very case points out some additional, and implicit, problems with the standard account of epistemic justification. The most notable is that the standard view attacksreliabilism on the grounds that it lacks a means of (...) giving adequate reasons or evidence for its claims. We argue that the standard view, while correct on its paradigm case againstreliabilism, is itself weakened by its lack of recognition of the central role theories of evidence must play in its basic account. Since theories of evidence are themselves divergent and problematic in terms of explaining how claims are justified, the standard account needs to address the issues of which account of evidence is 'adequate' and why it is. It is finally suggested that traditional epistemology might be more accurately described as a branch of confirmation theory. (shrink)
EvidentialistReliabilism.Juan Comesaña -2010 -Noûs 44 (4):571-600.detailsI argue for a theory that combines elements ofreliabilism and evidentialism.
IndexicalReliabilism and the New Evil Demon.Brian Ball &Michael Blome-Tillmann -2013 -Erkenntnis 78 (6):1317-1336.detailsStewart Cohen’s New Evil Demon argument raises familiar and widely discussed concerns for reliabilist accounts of epistemic justification. A now standard response to this argument, initiated by Alvin Goldman and Ernest Sosa, involves distinguishing different notions of justification. Juan Comesaña has recently and prominently claimed that his IndexicalReliabilism (IR) offers a novel solution in this tradition. We argue, however, that Comesaña’s proposal suffers serious difficulties from the perspective of the philosophy of language. More specifically, we show that the (...) two readings of sentences involving the word ‘justified’ which are required for Comesaña’s solution to the problem are not recoverable within the two-dimensional framework of Robert Stalnaker to which he appeals. We then consider, and reject, an attempt to overcome this difficulty by appeal to a complication of the theory involving counterfactuals, and conclude the paper by sketching our own preferred solution to Cohen’s New Evil Demon. (shrink)
Reliabilism and Privileged Access.Kourken Michaelian -2009 -Journal of Philosophical Research 34:69-109.detailsReliabilism is invoked by a standard causal response to the slow switching argument for incompatibilism about mental content externalism and privileged access. Though the response in question is negative, in that it only establishes that, given such an epistemology, externalism does not rule privileged access out, the appeal toreliabilism involves an assumption about the reliability of introspection, an assumption that in turn grounds a simple argument for the positive conclusion thatreliabilism itself implies privileged access. This (...) paper offers a two-part defense of that conclusion: the reliabilist account of privileged access is defended both againstarguments in favor of the rival content inheritance strategy and against an argument turning on empirical considerations concerning the individuation of the belief-producing process of introspection. (shrink)
ContraReliabilism.Carl Ginet -1985 -The Monist 68 (2):175-187.detailsThe reliability of a belief-producing process is a matter of how likely it is that the process will produce beliefs that are true. The termreliabilism may be used to refer to any position that makes this idea of reliability central to the explication of some important epistemic concept. I know of three such positions that appeal to some epistemologists: a reliabilist account of what makes a belief justified, a reliabilist account of what makes a true belief knowledge, and (...) a reliabilist answer to the question of the fourth condition, the question of what must be added to justified true belief to make knowledge. Obviously these are alternative positions rather than parts of a single coherent whole. I think of the first asreliabilism’s boldest stand, the second as the position to which it may retreat when the first is found untenable, and the third as its last refuge. I will criticize only the first two positions. (shrink)
TransglobalReliabilism.David Henderson &Terry Horgan -2006 -Croatian Journal of Philosophy 6 (2):171-195.detailsWe here propose an account of what it is for an agent to be objectively justified in holding some belief. We present in outline this approach, which we call transglobalreliabilism, and we discuss how it is motivated by various thought experiments. While transglobalreliabilism is an externalist epistemology, we think that it accommodates traditional internalist concerns and objections in a uniquely natural and respectful way.
VI-Reliabilism, Knowledge, and Mental Content.Jessica Brown -2000 -Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (2):115-135.detailsI consider whether one particular anti-individualist claim, the doctrine of object-dependent thoughts (DODT), is compatible with the Principle of Privileged Access, or PPA, which states that, in general, a subject can have non-empirical knowledge of her thought contents. The standard defence of the compatibility of anti-individualism and PPA emphasises the reliability of the process which produces a subject's second order beliefs about her thought contents. I examine whether this defence can be applied to DODT, given that DODT generates the possibility (...) of illusions of thought. Drawing on general epistemological literature, I distinguish several senses of reliability, and argue that in the relevant sense-'global reliability'-DODT does sometimes threaten reliability and hence PPA. (shrink)
Reliabilism and the extra value of knowledge.Wayne A. Davis &Christoph Jäger -2012 -Philosophical Studies 157 (1):93-105.detailsGoldman and Olsson ( 2009 ) have responded to the common charge that reliabilist theories of knowledge are incapable of accounting for the value knowledge has beyond mere true belief. We examine their “conditional probability solution” in detail, and show that it does not succeed. The conditional probability relation is too weak to support instrumental value, and the specific relation they describe is inessential to the value of knowledge. At best, they have described conditions in which knowledge indicates that additional (...) epistemic value is likely to be forthcoming in the future. We also argue that their motive analogy breaks down. The problem, we conclude, is that being produced by a reliable process is not sufficient for a belief to be justified. (shrink)
Reliabilism, Intuition, and Mathematical Knowledge.Jennifer Wilson Mulnix -2008 -Filozofia 62 (8):715-723.detailsIt is alleged that the causal inertness of abstract objects and the causal conditions of certain naturalized epistemologies precludes the possibility of mathematical know- ledge. This paper rejects this alleged incompatibility, while also maintaining that the objects of mathematical beliefs are abstract objects, by incorporating a naturalistically acceptable account of ‘rational intuition.’ On this view, rational intuition consists in a non-inferential belief-forming process where the entertaining of propositions or certain contemplations results in true beliefs. This view is free of any (...) conditions incompatible with abstract objects, for the reason that it is not necessary that S stand in some causal relation to the entities in virtue of which p is true. Mathematical intuition is simply one kind of reliable process type, whose inputs are not abstract numbers, but rather, contemplations of abstract numbers. (shrink)
Reliabilism and the problem of defeaters.Thomas Grundmann -2009 -Grazer Philosophische Studien 79 (1):65-76.detailsIt is widely assumed that justification is defeasible, e.g. that under certain conditions counterevidence removes prior justification of beliefs. In this paper I will first (sect. 1) explain why this feature of justification poses a prima facie problem forreliabilism. I then will try out different reliabilist strategies to deal with the problem. Among them I will discuss conservative strategies (sect. 2), eliminativist stragies (sect. 3) and revisionist strategies (sect. 4). In the final section I will present an improved (...) revisionist approach to defeaters that is able to overcome the main shortcomings of the other approaches. (shrink)
Systemreliabilism and basic beliefs: defeasible, undefeated and likely to be true.Spyridon Orestis Palermos -2021 -Synthese 199 (3):6733-6759.detailsTo avoid the problem of regress, externalists have put forward defeaters-based accounts of justification. The paper argues that existing proposals face two serious concerns: (i) They fail to accommodate related counterexamples such as Norman the clairvoyant, and, more worryingly, (ii) they fail to explain how one can be epistemically responsible in holding basic beliefs—i.e., they fail to explain how basic beliefs can avoid being arbitrary from the agent’s point of view. To solve both of these problems, a new, externalist, defeaters-based (...) account of justification is offered—viz., SystemReliabilism. The core message of the view—and the way it deals with both (i) and (ii)—is the claim that the justificatory status of justified basic beliefs originates from being the undefeated outputs of a reliable, cognitively integrated system that is capable of defeating them. Simply put, to be candidates for being justified, basic beliefs must be epistemically responsible and to be so they must be undefeated while being defeasible. The paper also offers a detailed, naturalistic analysis of the notion of cognitive integration. This long-due, mechanistic account of cognitive integration is then used to argue that an additional advantage of SystemReliabilism is its unique position to account for the as yet unexplained intuition that responsible beliefs are also likely to be true. (shrink)
No categories
Reliabilism and Relativism.Robin McKenna -2015 - In McKenna Robin,Proceedings of the 38th International Wittgenstein Society Conference.detailsProcessreliabilism says that a belief is justified iff the belief-forming process that produced it is sufficiently reliable. But any token belief-forming process is an instance of a number of different belief-forming process types. The problem of specifying the relevant type is known as the ‘generality problem’ for processreliabilism. This paper proposes a broadly relativist solution to the generality problem. The thought is that the relevant belief-forming process type is relative to the context. While the basic idea (...) behind the solution is from Mark Heller (1995), the solution defended here departs from Heller on a crucial point. Because of this departure, my solution avoids a serious problem with Heller’s solution. (shrink)
Reliabilist epistemology meets bounded rationality.Giovanni Dusi -2024 -Synthese 203 (4):1-21.detailsEpistemicreliabilism holds that a belief is justified if and only if it is produced by a reliable or truth-conducive process. I argue thatreliabilism offers an epistemology for bounded rationality. This latter concept refers to normative and descriptive accounts of real-world reasoning instead of some ideal reasoning. However, as initially formulated,reliabilism involves an absolute, context-independent assessment of rationality that does not do justice to the fact that several processes are reliable in some reasoning environments but (...) not in others, as is widely reported in the cognitive sciences literature. I consider possible solutions to this problem. Resorting to ‘normalityreliabilism’, a variant of the theory, is one; but I find it insufficient. Therefore, in addition, I propose to relativise the reliability assessment to reasoning environments. This novel version ofreliabilism fits bounded rationality better than the original one does. (shrink)
The Reliabilist Theory of Rational Belief.Steven Luper-Foy -1985 -The Monist 68 (2):203-225.detailsNiceties aside,Reliabilism is the claim that a belief is justified or rational if and only if it has a reliable source. One way to arrive at a belief is by inferring it from others through the application of a rule of inference. HenceReliabilism has the consequence that a belief arrived at by applying a given rule of inference is rational if and only if arriving at that belief by applying the rule is reliable. This consequence of (...)Reliabilism I will call the Reliabilist’s Thesis. (shrink)
Reliabilism and First- and Second-Order Skepticism.Byeong D. Lee -2016 -Philosophical Analysis 35:27-49.detailsOne reliabilist option against the problem of bootstrapping is to argue that circular reasoning is bad, butreliabilism can avoid circular reasoning. Vogel dismisses this option on the grounds that reliabilists need circular reasoning in order to circumvent skepticism. Briesen argues, however, that although reliabilists need circular reasoning to block second-order skepticism, they do not need it to block first-order skepticism. But I argue in this paper that reliabilists cannot legitimately reject first-order skepticism unless they can block second-order skepticism. (...) In particular, I argue that reliabilists cannot meet the non-undermining provision for justification unless they can somehow block second-order skepticism. (shrink)
The numbers don't fit: a problem forreliabilism.Jan-Hendrik Heinrichs -2014 -Epistemologia 37 (1):96-105.detailsReliabilism suffers from a problem with long sequences of justifications. The theory of justification provided in processreliabilism allows for an implausibly large extension of ‘justified belief’. According to process reliabilist theory, it is possible that a justifying cognitive process has an arbitrarily low probability of being successful and a justified belief an arbitrarily low probability of being true. This result violatesreliabilism’s aims as well as our ordinary standards of justification.
Reliabilism.Alvin Goldman -2008 -Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.detailsReliabilism is a general approach to epistemology that emphasizes the truth conduciveness of a belief forming process, method, or other epistemologically relevant factor. The reliability theme appears both in theories of knowledge and theories of justification. ‘Reliabilism’ is sometimes used broadly to refer to any theory of knowledge or justification that emphasizes truth getting or truth indicating properties. These include theories originally proposed under different labels, such as ‘tracking’ theories. More commonly, ‘reliabilism’ is used narrowly to refer (...) to processreliabilism about justification. This entry discussesreliabilism in both broad and narrow senses but concentrates on reliability theories of justified belief, especially processreliabilism. (shrink)
Reliabilism and circularity.Markus Lammenranta -1996 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (1):111-124.detailsHow can we ever find out whether our psychological processes are reliable? According to many reliabilists—e.g. Alston, Goldman, Papineau, and Van Cleve —there is no problem: We just use our psychological processes and then arrive at the belief that these very same processes are reliable. If our psychological processes are actually reliable, we can arrive in this way at a justified belief. And, indeed, we can even come to know that they are reliable.