Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'Matthew C. Wood'

971 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  18
    Interest and deferred consumption in the rat.James Allison &Matthew C.Wood -1991 -Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 29 (2):168-170.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  44
    Johann Gottlieb Fichte, AllenWood (ed.),Attempt at a Critique of All Revelation[REVIEW]Matthew C. Altman -2010 -Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2010 (5).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  62
    Kant and Applied Ethics: The Uses and Limits of Kant's Practical Philosophy.Matthew C. Altman -2011 - Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell.
    _Kant and Applied Ethics_ makes an important contribution to Kant scholarship, illuminating the vital moral parameters of key ethical debates. Offers a critical analysis of Kant’s ethics, interrogating the theoretical bases of his theory and evaluating their strengths and weaknesses Examines the controversies surrounding the most important ethical discussions taking place today, including abortion, the death penalty, and same-sex marriage Joins innovative thinkers in contemporary Kantian scholarship, including Christine Korsgaard, AllenWood, and Barbara Herman, in taking Kant’s philosophy in (...) new and interesting directions Clarifies Kant’s legacy for applied ethics, helping us to understand how these debates have been structured historically and providing us with the philosophical tools to address them. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  4.  19
    Animal Suffering and Moral Character.Matthew C. Altman -2011 - InKant and Applied Ethics: The Uses and Limits of Kant's Practical Philosophy. Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 13–44.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Kant's Logocentrism Kant's Justification for Our Duties (with Regard) to Nonrational Animals Implications of Kant's View for Our Treatment of Animals Kantians Revising Kant:Wood and Korsgaard Problems withWood and Korsgaard Kant's Response to Wolff: The Difference between Animal Choice and Moral Agency Evaluating Pain and Pleasure Kant's Practical Appeal Final Thoughts for the Nonanthropocentrist.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  23
    Matthew C. Canfield: Translating food sovereignty: Cultivating justice in an age of transnational governance.Tiffany K. Woods -2023 -Agriculture and Human Values 40 (2):781-782.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  72
    Beyond “Monologicality”? Exploring Conspiracist Worldviews.Bradley Franks,Adrian Bangerter,Martin W. Bauer,Matthew Hall &Mark C. Noort -2017 -Frontiers in Psychology 8:250235.
    Conspiracy theories (CTs) are widespread ways by which people make sense of unsettling or disturbing cultural events. Belief in CTs is often connected to problematic consequences, such as decreased engagement with conventional political action or even political extremism, so understanding the psychological and social qualities of CTs belief is important. CTs have often been understood to be “monological”, displaying the tendency for belief in one conspiracy theory to be correlated with belief in (many) others. Explanations of monologicality invoke a nomothetical (...) or “closed” mindset whereby mutually supporting beliefs based on mistrust of official explanations are used to interpret public events as conspiracies, independent of the facts about those events (which they may ignore or deny). But research on monologicality offers little discussion of the content of monological beliefs and reasoning from the standpoint of the CT believers. This is due in part to the “access problem” (Wood & Douglas, 2015): CT believers are averse to being researched because they often distrust researchers and what they appear to represent. We used several strategies to address the access problem, and investigated the symbolic resources underlying CTs by reconstructing a conspiracy worldview - a set of beliefs held by CT believers about important dimensions of ontology, epistemology, and human agency. To do this, we analysed media documents, conducted field observation, and engaged in semi-structured interviews,. We describe six main dimensions of a conspiracy worldview: Views of the nature of reality, the self, the outgroup, the ingroup, action, and the future. We also describe a typology of five types of CT believers, which vary according to their positions on each of these dimensions. Our findings converge with prior explorations of CT beliefs but also revealed novel aspects: A sense of community among CT believers, a highly differentiated representation of the outgroup, a personal journey of conversion, variegated kinds of political action, and optimistic belief in future change. These findings are at odds with the typical image of monological CT believers as paranoid, cynical, anomic and irrational. For many, the CT worldview may rather constitute the ideological underpinning of a nascent pre-figurative social movement. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  7.  52
    Scientism: Philosophy and the Infatuation with Science. [REVIEW]Roger Harris,Kevin Magill,Vincent Geoghegan,Anthony Elliott,Chris Arthur,Michael Gardiner,David Macey,Nöel Parker,Alex Klaushofer,Gary Kitchen,Tom Furniss,Christopher J. Arthur,Sadie Plant,Fred Inglis,Matthew Rampley,Alison Ainley,Daryl Glaser,Jean-Jacques Lecercle,Sean Sayers,Keith Ansell-Pearson &Lucy Frith -1992 -Radical Philosophy 61 (61).
  8.  114
    Critical Notice Ecumenicalism and Perennialism Revisited:MATTHEW C. BAGGER.Matthew C. Bagger -1991 -Religious Studies 27 (3):399-411.
    Recently Robert Forman has attempted to muster support for the largely abandoned position that mystical experiences cross-culturally include an unmediated, non-relative core. To reopen the debate he has solicited essays from likeminded scholars for his book, The Problem of Pure Consciousness. Predictably the focus of the volume rests on the refutation of the position most notably expounded by Steven Katz in his influential article of 1978, ‘Language, Epistemology and Mysticism’.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  13
    Ecology and Existence: Bringing Sartre to the Water's Edge.Matthew C. Ally -2017 - Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
    In this book,Matthew C. Ally explores the changing and increasingly troubled relationship between humankind and planet Earth. Oriented by the seemingly simple example of a woodland pond, he draws together insights from existential philosophy, scientific ecology, and several disciplines in the social sciences and humanities to articulate a strong sense of human belonging in the living Earth community and a binding imperative of participation in the struggle to preserve a habitable planet and build a livable world.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  133
    The Decomposition of the Corporate Body: What Kant Cannot Contribute to Business Ethics.Matthew C. Altman -2007 -Journal of Business Ethics 74 (3):253-266.
    Kant is gaining popularity in business ethics because the categorical imperative rules out actions such as deceptive advertising and exploitative working conditions, both of which treat people merely as means to an end. However, those who apply Kant in this way often hold businesses themselves morally accountable, and this conception of collective responsibility contradicts the kind of moral agency that underlies Kant's ethics. A business has neither inclinations nor the capacity to reason, so it lacks the conditions necessary for constraint (...) by the moral law. Instead, corporate policies ought to be understood as analogous to legal constraints. They may encourage or discourage certain actions, but they cannot determine a person's maxim - which for Kant is the focus of moral judgment. Because there is no collective intention apart from any intentions of the individual agents who act as members of the corporation, an organization itself has no moral obligations. This poses a dilemma: either apply the categorical imperative to the actions of particular businesspeople and surrender the notion of collective responsibility, or apply a different moral theory to the actions of businesses themselves. Given the diffusion of responsibility in a bureaucracy, the explanatory usefulness of collective responsibility may force business ethicists to abandon Kant's moral philosophy. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  11.  43
    A Theory of Legal Punishment: Deterrence, Retribution, and the Aims of the State.Matthew C. Altman -2021 - New York, NY: Routledge.
    "This book argues for a mixed view of punishment that balances consequentialism and retributivism. He has published extensively on philosophy and applied ethics. A central question in the philosophy of law is why the state's punishment of its own citizens is justified. Traditionally, two theories of punishment have dominated the field: consequentialism and retributivism. According to consequentialism, punishment is justified when it maximizes positive outcomes. According to retributivism, criminals should be punished because they deserve it. This book defends a mixed (...) view that recognizes the strength of both of these intuitions. By this account, the legislature should develop institutional policies and statutory penalties that maintain the social order, that is, consequentialism. It establishes punishment policies to deter criminal activity. By contrast, the criminal judiciary should give individual defendants what they deserve, that is, retributivism and thus expressing the community's appropriate sense of resentment at being wronged. The book justifies the two-tiered model by showing how it accords with our moral intuitions, our assumptions about how what we know affects our moral obligations, and a commonly held theory of freedom. This approach is developed by engaging classic and contemporary work in the philosophy of law, and shows its advantages over competing approaches from contemporary retributivists and other mixed theorists. The work also defends consequentialism against a longstanding objection that the social sciences give us little guidance regarding which policies to adopt. It draws on cutting-edge criminological research to show how punishment theory can help us to address some of our most pressing social issues, including the death penalty, drug laws, and mass incarceration. The book will also be of interest to legal philosophers, social scientists, especially criminologists, sociologists, economists, and political scientists"--. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  12.  143
    An obligation to provide abortion services: what happens when physicians refuse?C. Meyers &R. D. Woods -1996 -Journal of Medical Ethics 22 (2):115-120.
    Access to abortion services in the United States continues to decline. It does so not because of significant changes in legislation or court rulings but because fewer and fewer physicians wish to perform abortions and because most states now have "conscientious objection" legislation that makes it easy for physicians to refuse to do so. We argue in this paper that physicians have an obligation to perform all socially sanctioned medical services, including abortions, and thus that the burden of justification lies (...) upon those who wish to be excused from that obligation. That is, such persons should have to show how requiring them to perform abortions would represent a serious threat to their fundamental moral or religious beliefs. We use current California law as an example of legislation that does not take physicians' obligations into account and thus allows them too easily to declare conscientious objection. (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  13.  19
    Transfer of triceps motor branches of the radial nerve to the axillary nerve with or without other nerve transfers provides antigravity shoulder abduction in pediatric brachial plexus injury.Matthew C. McRae &Gregory H. Borschel -2012 - In Zdravko Radman,The Hand. MIT Press. pp. 7--2.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  38
    Fast, Cheap, and Unethical? The Interplay of Morality and Methodology in Crowdsourced Survey Research.Matthew C. Haug -2018 -Review of Philosophy and Psychology 9 (2):363-379.
    Crowdsourcing is an increasingly popular method for researchers in the social and behavioral sciences, including experimental philosophy, to recruit survey respondents. Crowdsourcing platforms, such as Amazon’s Mechanical Turk (MTurk), have been seen as a way to produce high quality survey data both quickly and cheaply. However, in the last few years, a number of authors have claimed that the low pay rates on MTurk are morally unacceptable. In this paper, I explore some of the methodological implications for online experimental philosophy (...) research if, in fact, typical pay practices on MTurk are morally impermissible. I argue that the most straightforward solution to this apparent moral problem—paying survey respondents more and relying only on “high reputation” respondents—will likely increase the number of subjects who have previous experience with survey materials and thus are “non-naïve” with respect to those materials. I then discuss some likely effects that this increase in experimental non-naivete will have on some aspects of the “negative” program in experimental philosophy, focusing in particular on recent debates about philosophical expertise. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  55
    The Palgrave Kant Handbook.Matthew C. Altman (ed.) -2017 - London: Palgrave Macmillan.
    This remarkably comprehensive Handbook provides a multifaceted yet carefully crafted investigation into the work of Immanuel Kant, one of the greatest philosophers the world has ever seen. With original contributions from leading international scholars in the field, this authoritative volume first sets Kant’s work in its biographical and historical context. It then proceeds to explain and evaluate his revolutionary work in metaphysics and epistemology, logic, ethics, aesthetics, philosophy of science, philosophy of religion, political philosophy, philosophy of history, philosophy of education, (...) and anthropology. Key Features: • Draws attention to the foundations of Kant’s varied philosophical insights — transcendental idealism, logic, and the bridge between theoretical and practical reason • Considers hitherto neglected topics such as sexuality and the philosophy of education • Explores the immense impact of his ground-breaking work on subsequent intellectual movements Serving as a touchstone for meaningful discussion about Kant’s philosophical and historical importance, this definitive Handbook is essential reading for Kant scholars who want to keep abreast of the field and for advanced students wishing to explore the frontiers of the subject. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  16.  13
    So what? now what?: the anthropology of consciousness responds to a world in crisis.Matthew C. Bronson &Tina R. Fields (eds.) -2009 - Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Press.
    "The greatest crisis of our times in a failure of the human imagination." -Editors The world is currently undergoing a period of unprecedented crises on virtually every front: economic, ecological, and humanitarian. It is starkly apparent that a shift is needed in our dominant structural systems - and that by addressing the collective thinking that has created and maintained these systems, scholars can do their part to catalyze such a shift. The interdisciplinary field known as the Anthropology of Consciousness offers (...) important insights for enacting this necessary shift. This book draws on the work of a group of diverse scholars to explore what the intersection of anthropology and consciousness studies can contribute to the "public turn" within anthropology and the academy in general. Its twelve chapters span disparate geographies and disciplinary frameworks, yet cohere in their focus on common themes such as imagination, empathy, agency, dialogue, and ethics. The answers to the question "So What? Now What?" differ for a linguistic anthropologist in the South Pacific, an environmental educator in Hawai'i, a grant-writing anthropologist serving a refugee agency in Portland, Oregon and the founder of a girls' school in Brazil. Nevertheless, they are united in the desire to reframe the anthropology of consciousness as an "anthropology of conscience," and this pioneering volume is the result. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  21
    Religious Experience, Justification, and History.Matthew C. Bagger -1999 - Cambridge University Press.
    Recently, many philosophers of religion have sought to defend the rationality of religious belief by shifting the burden of proof onto the critic of religious belief. Some have appealed to extraordinary religious experience in making their case. Religious Experience, Justification, and History restores neglected explanatory and historical considerations to the debate. Through a study of William James, it contests the accounts of religious experience offered in recent works. Through reflection on the history of philosophy, it also unravels the philosophical use (...) of the term justification.Matthew Bagger argues that the commitment to supernatural explanations implicit in the religious experiences employed to justify religious belief contradicts the modern ideal of human flourishing. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  18.  20
    In Defense of a Mixed Theory of Punishment.Matthew C. Altman -2022 - InThe Palgrave Handbook on the Philosophy of Punishment. Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 195-219.
    In this chapter, Altman gives two separate arguments that, in conjunction, support a mixed theory of punishment. First, he shows that consequentialism is insufficient on its own because it cannot capture the condemnatory function of the law as an expression of the community’s resentment. Second, he shows that retributivism is insufficient on its own because any plausible legal arrangement must be committed to some non-retributivist values. He then argues that the institution of punishment is justified by its costs and benefits, (...) and the distribution of punishment—who is punished and how much—is justified by what offenders deserve. This two-tiered model of punishment makes more sense than an alternative scheme, according to which retributivist reasoning informs criminal lawmaking and consequentialist reasoning informs criminal judgments and sentencing. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  291
    Philosophical Methodology: The Armchair or the Laboratory?Matthew C. Haug (ed.) -2013 - New York: Routledge.
    What methodology should philosophers follow? Should they rely on methods that can be conducted from the armchair? Or should they leave the armchair and turn to the methods of the natural sciences, such as experiments in the laboratory? Or is this opposition itself a false one? Arguments about philosophical methodology are raging in the wake of a number of often conflicting currents, such as the growth of experimental philosophy, the resurgence of interest in metaphysical questions, and the use of formal (...) methods. This outstanding collection of specially-commissioned chapters by leading international philosophers discusses these questions and many more. It provides a comprehensive survey of philosophical methodology in the most important philosophical subjects: metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, phenomenology, philosophy of science, ethics, and aesthetics. A key feature of the collection is that philosophers discuss and evaluate contrasting approaches in each subject, offering a superb overview of the variety of methodological approaches - both naturalistic and non-naturalistic - in each of these areas. They examine important topics at the heart of methodological argument, including the role of intuitions and conceptual analysis, thought experiments, introspection, and the place that results from the natural sciences should have in philosophical theorizing. The collection begins with a fascinating exchange about philosophical naturalism between Timothy Williamson and Alexander Rosenberg, and also includes contributions from the following philosophers: Lynne Rudder Baker, Matt Bedke, Greg Currie, Michael Devitt,Matthew C. Haug, Jenann Ismael, Hilary Kornblith, Neil Levy, E.J. Lowe, Kirk Ludwig, Marie McGinn, David Papineau,Matthew Ratcliffe, Georges Rey, Jeffrey W. Roland, Barry C. Smith, Amie L. Thomasson, Valerie Tiberius, Jessica Wilson, and David W. Smith. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  20.  42
    The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism.Matthew C. Altman (ed.) -2014 - London: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    German Idealism was without doubt one of the most fruitful, influential, and exciting periods in the history of philosophy. The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism covers this revolutionary philosophical movement in remarkable detail and includes contributions from 36 of the leading scholars in the field, including Paul Guyer, Terry Pinkard, Violetta Waibel, Jason Wirth, and Günter Zöller. In his introduction,Matthew Altman investigates the meaning of idealism and sets the historical context. Ensuing chapters then consider the philosophical importance of (...) the movement’s four most important thinkers (Kant, Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel) and explore the areas of philosophy on which they had their greatest impact. A concluding chapter examines the legacy of German Idealism from the nineteenth century to the present day. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  57
    The Limits of Kant’s Cosmopolitanism: Theory, Practice, and the Crisis in Syria.Matthew C. Altman -2017 -Kantian Review 22 (2):179-204.
    Although Kant defends a cosmopolitan ideal, his philosophy is problematically vague regarding how to achieve it, which lends support to the empty formalism charge. How Kant would respond to the crisis in Syria reveals that judgement plays too central a role, because Kantian principles lead to equally reasonable but opposite conclusions on how to weigh the duty of hospitality to refugees against a state’s duty to its own citizens, the right of prevention towards ISIS against the duty not to harm (...) non-combatants, and the responsibility to protect the people of Syria against the duty of non-interference in its internal affairs. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  64
    Can Suicide Preserve One’s Dignity? Kant and Kantians on the Moral Response to Cognitive Loss.Matthew C. Altman -2020 -Kant Studien 111 (4):593-611.
    Kantian defenders of suicide for the soon-to-be demented claim that killing oneself would protect rather than violate a person’s inherent worth. The loss of cognitive functions reduces someone to a lower moral status, so they believe that suicide is a way of preserving or preventing the loss of dignity. I argue that they misinterpret Kant’s examples and fail to appreciate the reasons behind his absolute prohibition on suicide. Although Kant says that one may have to sacrifice one’s life to fulfill (...) a moral duty, suicide is not morally equivalent to self-sacrifice because it involves treating oneself merely as a means. Furthermore, people facing the onset of dementia would not protect their dignity by killing themselves while they are still rational and would not avoid a demeaning existence. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  23
    Introduction: Why Kant Now.Matthew C. Altman -2011 - InKant and Applied Ethics: The Uses and Limits of Kant's Practical Philosophy. Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 1–9.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  22
    Consent, Mail‐Order Brides, and the Marriage Contract.Matthew C. Altman -2011 - InKant and Applied Ethics: The Uses and Limits of Kant's Practical Philosophy. Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 167–193.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The Purpose of Marriage Consent and Coercion Mail‐Order Marriages as the Kantian Ideal Treating Mail‐Order Brides Merely as Means Attempts to Criticize Mail‐Order Marriages from a Kantian Perspective Are Mail‐Order Brides Coerced? Questioning the a priori Basis of Kant's Ethics Notes toward a Genealogy of Kantianism.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  74
    Ecologizing Sartre’s Ontology.Matthew C. Ally -2012 -Environmental Philosophy 9 (2):95-121.
    I argue that Sartre’s philosophy can be both broadened in its aspirations and deepened in its implications through dialogue with the life sciences. Section 1 introduces the philosophical terrain. Section 2 explores Sartre’s evolving understanding of nature and human relations with nature. Section 3 explores Sartre’s perspectives on scientific inquiry, natural history, and dialectical reason. Section 4 outlines recent developments in the life sciences that bear directly on Sartre’s quiet curiosity about a naturalistic dialectics. Section 5 suggests how these developments (...) constitute progress toward an “ecologized” dialectical philosophy consistent with Sartre’s mature ontology of praxis and pertinent to addressing the burgeoning socioecological crisis. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  18
    Kant’s Compatibilism and the Two-Tiered Model of Punishment.Matthew C. Altman -2021 - In Camilla Serck-Hanssen & Beatrix Himmelmann,The Court of Reason: Proceedings of the 13th International Kant Congress. De Gruyter. pp. 1679-1688.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  138
    Of mice and metaphysics: Natural selection and realized population‐level properties.Matthew C. Haug -2007 -Philosophy of Science 74 (4):431-451.
    In this paper, I answer a fundamental question facing any view according to which natural selection is a population‐level causal process—namely, how is the causal process of natural selection related to, yet not preempted by, causal processes that occur at the level of individual organisms? Without an answer to this grounding question, the population‐level causal view appears unstable—collapsing into either an individual‐level causal interpretation or the claim that selection is a purely formal, statistical phenomenon. I argue that a causal account (...) of realization provides an answer to the grounding question. By applying this account of realization to the natural selection of melanism in rock pocket mice, I show how an alternative, formal account of realization, favored by proponents of the statistical interpretation, misses biologically important features. More generally, this paper shows how metaphysical issues about realization normally discussed in the philosophy of mind apply to debates in philosophy of biology. Thus, it is a first step toward fleshing out the oft‐noted similarities between debates in these areas. (shrink)
    Direct download(9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  28.  35
    Comportment, not cognition: Contributions to a phenomenology of judgment.Matthew C. Weidenfeld -2011 -Contemporary Political Theory 10 (2):232-254.
    Current theoretical account of judgment has a difficult time saying anything positive about the experience of judging and, when they do offer positive accounts, they seem to overlook much that we know about the capacity already in our daily lives. Following the work of Martin Heidegger and Hubert Dreyfus, this article provides a phenomenological consideration of the structure of judging that considers judgment not as an intellectual act, but as a comportment. The article proceeds in two parts. The first offers (...) a brief consideration of the assumptions of intellectualist accounts and shows why, ultimately, they may be unable to bring judging into focus. The second section offers a phenomenological account of judging. The argument of section two is that deliberate judgment is a continuation of the structure of judgment understood as comportment and, in turn, that intellectualist accounts come onto the scene too late. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  29.  72
    Against Inefficacy Objections: the Real Economic Impact of Individual Consumer Choices on Animal Agriculture.Matthew C. Halteman &Steven McMullen -2019 -Food Ethics 2 (2-3):93-110.
    When consumers choose to abstain from purchasing meat, they face some uncertainty about whether their decisions will have an impact on the number of animals raised and killed. Consequentialists have argued that this uncertainty should not dissuade consumers from a vegetarian diet because the “expected” impact, or average impact, will be predictable. Recently, however, critics have argued that the expected marginal impact of a consumer change is likely to be much smaller or more radically unpredictable than previously thought. This objection (...) to the consequentialist case for vegetarianism is known as the “causal inefficacy” (or “causal impotence”) objection. In this paper, we argue that the inefficacy objection fails. First, we summarize the contours of the objection and the standard “expected impact” response to it. Second, we examine and rebut two contemporary attempts (by Mark Budolfson and Ted Warfield) to defeat the expected impact reply through alleged demonstrations of the inefficacy of abstaining from meat consumption. Third, we argue that there are good reasons to believe that single individual consumers—not just consumers in aggregate—really do make a positive difference when they choose to abstain from meat consumption. Our case rests on three economic observations: (i) animal producers operate in a highly competitive environment, (ii) complex supply chains efficiently communicate some information about product demand, and (iii) consumers of plant-based meat alternatives have positive consumption spillover effects on other consumers. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  30.  39
    4 Beauvoir and Sartre on Freedom, Intersubjectivity, and Normative Justification.Matthew C. Eshleman -2009 - In Christine Daigle & Jacob Golomb,Beauvoir and Sartre: The Riddle of Influence. Indiana University Press. pp. 65--89.
  31.  43
    Nishida Among the Idealists.Matthew C. Altman -2020 -Philosophy East and West 70 (4):860-880.
    In his theoretical philosophy, Immanuel Kant argues that experience comes from two sources that are radically different but equally necessary: the rule-governed activity of thinking and the givenness of sensations. He supposes that both could be traced to some common root but concludes that whatever it is, is in principle unknowable. Kant's idealist successors, J.G. Fichte and F.W.J. Schelling, each attempt to provide a unified account of experience by identifying the ultimate basis of subject and object—Fichte by referring to the (...) I's activity and Schelling by referring to the Absolute. Because we can know only appearances, an implication of Kant's transcendental inquiry, Fichte and Schelling have difficulty... (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  70
    Heidegger’s appropriation of Aristotle: Phronesis, conscience, and seeing through the one.Matthew C. Weidenfeld -2011 -European Journal of Political Theory 10 (2):254-276.
    This article attempts to show that Heidegger’s phenomenology may shed light on political phenomena. It pursues this project by arguing that Heidegger’s phenomenology is an appropriation of Aristotle’s practical philosophy and his conceptualization of phronesis. I argue that, in Being and Time, Heidegger’s ‘circumspection’, which is a capacity for making sense of practical situations, is a translation of phronesis. Heidegger argues, though, that the sight of circumspection is foreshortened by the rules and norms of ‘the one’. In division 2, ‘conscience’ (...) becomes a sharpening of the vision of phronesis, which sees through the one. I then defend Heidegger’s appropriation of phronesis and argue that Heidegger’s concept of conscience, which takes up a critical stance toward plurality, may actually be a proper vision of practical wisdom under modern conditions. I substantiate this claim by turning to an unlikely source to bolster Heidegger’s reading of phronesis and the modern public, Hannah Arendt. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33.  944
    Kant on sex and marriage: The implications for the same-sex marriage debate.Matthew C. Altman -2010 -Kant Studien 101 (3):309-330.
    When examined critically, Kant's views on sex and marriage give us the tools to defend same-sex marriage on moral grounds. The sexual objectification of one's partner can only be overcome when two people take responsibility for one another's overall well-being, and this commitment is enforced through legal coercion. Kant's views on the unnaturalness of homosexuality do not stand up to scrutiny, and he cannot (as he often tries to) restrict the purpose of sex to procreation. Kant himself rules out marriage (...) only when the partners cannot give themselves to one another equally – that is, if there is inequality of exchange. Because same-sex marriage would be between equals and would allow homosexuals to express their desire in a morally appropriate way, it ought to be legalized. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  34.  67
    Derrida, Stengers, Latour, and Subalternist Cosmopolitics.Matthew C. Watson -2014 -Theory, Culture and Society 31 (1):75-98.
    Postcolonial science studies entails ostensibly contradictory critical and empirical commitments. Science studies scholars influenced by Bruno Latour and Isabelle Stengers embrace forms of realist, radical empiricism, while postcolonial studies scholars influenced by Jacques Derrida trace the limits of the knowable. This essay takes their common use of the term cosmopolitics as an unexpected point of departure for reconciling Derrida’s program with Stengers’s and Latour’s. I read Derrida’s critique of hospitality and Stengers’s and Latour’s ontological politics as necessary complements for conceiving (...) a care-oriented subalternist cosmopolitics, a process of composing common worlds that remains attentive to the limits of representation. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  35.  149
    Abstraction and Explanatory Relevance; or, Why Do the Special Sciences Exist?Matthew C. Haug -2011 -Philosophy of Science 78 (5):1143-1155.
    Non-reductive physicalists have long held that the special sciences offer explanations of some phenomena that are objectively superior to physical explanations. This explanatory “autonomy” has largely been based on the multiple realizability argument. Recently, in the face of the local reduction and disjunctive property responses to multiple realizability, some defenders of non-reductive physicalism have suggested that autonomy can be grounded merely in human cognitive limitations. In this paper, I argue that this is mistaken. By distinguishing between two kinds of abstraction (...) I show that the greater explanatory relevance of some special science predicates (to certain explananda) is both non-anthropocentric and not solely based on considerations of multiple realizability. This shows that the explanatory autonomy of the special sciences is safe from the local reduction and disjunctive property strategies, even if they are successful responses to the multiple realizability argument. (shrink)
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  36.  72
    Non-Ideal Virtue and Situationism.Matthew C. Taylor -2021 -The Journal of Ethics 26 (1):41-68.
    Several philosophers, known as situationists, have argued that evidence in social psychology threatens to undermine Aristotelian virtue ethics. An impressively large amount of empirical evidence suggests that most people do not consistently act virtuously and lack the ability to exercise rational control over their behavior. Since possessing moral virtues requires these features, situationists have argued that Aristotelianism does not accurately describe the character traits possessed by most people, and so the theory cannot lay claim to various theoretical advantages such as (...) explanatory power and egalitarian character education. In contrast to previous defenses which either downplay the relevance of psychological evidence or revise philosophical conceptions of virtue to fit the data, this paper appeals to previously neglected psychological evidence on self-efficacy and mental contrasting in combination with “non-idealized” interpretations of Aristotelian moral virtue to support the view that the available empirical evidence is compatible with widespread possession of virtuous character. These “non-idealized” interpretations of virtuous character allow for serious deviations from virtuous conduct, especially in the contexts described by the psychology experiments. Furthermore, decades of research on mental contrasting and self-efficacy suggest that subjects in the psychology experiments acted for reasons and possessed the ability to exercise rational control over their behavior. Hence, situationists are mistaken in thinking that, based on the empirical data, Aristotelianism is deprived of various theoretical advantages. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  15
    Are Older Adults Less Embodied? A Review of Age Effects through the Lens of Embodied Cognition.Matthew C. Costello &Emily K. Bloesch -2017 -Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  38.  118
    Toward a Continental Philosophy of Religion: Derrida, Responsibility, and Non-dogmatic Faith.Matthew C. Halteman -2002 - In Philip Goodchild,Rethinking philosophy of religion: approaches from continental philosophy. New York: Fordham University Press.
    From its inception in Kant's efforts to articulate a "religion within the limits of reason alone," the Continental tradition has maintained a strict division of labor between theological and philosophical reflection on religion. In what follows, I examine this continental legacy in the context of Jacques Derrida's recent work on the concept of responsibility. First I discuss three guiding themes (the limits of speculative analysis, the idea of nondogmatic religion, and the importance of the other) that characterize the continental tradition's (...) general orientation toward philosophy of religion, as well as Derrida's approach to the concept of responsibility. I turn next to elucidating Derrida's account of responsibility as developed in "Force of Law: The Mystical Foundations of Authority" and The Gift of Death. I conclude with a discussion of the uses and limits of this account for religious (and theological) reflection, as well as for the task of articulating a contemporary continental philosophy of religion. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  151
    On the distinction between reductive and nonreductive physicalism.Matthew C. Haug -2011 -Metaphilosophy 42 (4):451-469.
    Abtract: This article argues that the debate between reductive and nonreductive physicalists is best characterized as a disagreement about which properties are natural. Among other things, natural properties are those that characterize the world completely. All physicalists accept the “completeness of physics,” but this claim contains a subtle ambiguity, which results in two conceptions of natural properties. Reductive physicalists should assert, while nonreductive physicalists should deny, that a single set of low-level physical properties is natural in both of these senses. (...) This way of drawing the distinction succeeds where previous approaches have failed and illuminates why the debate about reductionism is important. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  37
    Jean-Paul Sartre and Phenomenological Ontology.Matthew C. Eshleman -2012 - In Lester Embree & Thomas Nenon,Husserl’s Ideen. Dordrecht: Springer. pp. 327--349.
  41. On the problematic origin of the forms: Plotinus, Derrida, and the neoplatonic subtext of deconstruction's critique of ontology.Matthew C. Halteman -2006 -Continental Philosophy Review 39 (1):35-58.
    My aim in this paper is to draw Plotinus and Derrida together in a comparison of their respective appropriations of the famous “receptacle” passage in Plato's Timaeus (specifically, Plotinus' discussion of intelligible matter in Enneads 2.4 and Derrida's essay on Timaeus entitled “Kh ō ra”). After setting the stage with a discussion of several instructive similarities between their general philosophical projects, I contend that Plotinus and Derrida take comparable approaches both to thinking the origin of the forms and to problematizing (...) the stability of the sensible/intelligible opposition. With these parallels in focus, I go on to explain how examining such points of contact can help us to dismantle the canonical constructs of “Plotinus the metaphysician” and “Derrida the anti-metaphysician” that have obscured important connections between Neoplatonism and deconstruction, and suppressed latent resources within the Platonic tradition itself for deconstructing the dualistic ontology of so-called “Platonic metaphysics.”. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  24
    Is Philosophy a Choice? An Exploration via Parable with Nishitani, Heidegger, and Derrida.Matthew C. Kruger -2021 -Philosophy East and West 71 (4):919-937.
  43.  14
    Becoming a Person.Matthew C. Altman -2011 - InKant and Applied Ethics: The Uses and Limits of Kant's Practical Philosophy. Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 241–282.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The Ancient Practice of Abortion, and Continuing Controversies Universalized Maxims Are Not Retroactive The Formula of Humanity: Appealing to Personhood Thomson and Boonin: The Personhood of the Fetus Does Not Matter The Elements of Personhood: Self‐Consciousness, Humanity, Responsibility An Attempt to Bring Fetuses into Kant's Moral Community: The Appeal to Kind Another Common Strategy: The Argument from Potential Do We Have Indirect Duties to Fetuses? No Fetuses, No Children The Need for a Pragmatic Concept of (...) Personhood The Specter of Infanticide Kant's Appeal to God Problematic Implications of the Appeal to Personhood Our Kantian Heritage: Trouble with Those at the Margins of Personhood. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  59
    Ethics beyond the Academy: Service-Learning as Professional Development.Matthew C. Altman -2010 -Teaching Philosophy 33 (2):149-171.
    In addition to preparing students for graduate school or emphasizing transferable skills that are useful in any career, philosophy departments ought to give majors the education and work experience that will train them to become ethics officers outside of academia. This is a growing field that allows students to engage non-philosophers in setting corporate policies and addressing morally significant social issues. Using a course in medical ethics as an example, I show how incorporating service-learning into philosophy classes benefits students both (...) academically and professionally, and also demonstrates the value of philosophy to the community and to academic administrators. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  19
    Individual Maxims and Social Justice.Matthew C. Altman -2011 - InKant and Applied Ethics: The Uses and Limits of Kant's Practical Philosophy. Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 194–216.
    This chapter contains sections titled: How Kant Answers Hegel's Formalism Charge Basic Principles versus Particular Duties: Kant and Rawls What Is My Obligation to Reduce Poverty? Social Contexts Specify the Content of Maxims Herman's Rules of Moral Salience The Humanity of Others Is Not Simply Given Developing Moral Judgment: The Case of Kant Himself The Return of Hegel.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  42
    The Significance of the Other in Moral Education: Fichte on the Birth of Subjectivity.Matthew C. Altman -2008 -History of Philosophy Quarterly 25 (2):175 - 186.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  158
    Natural Properties and the Special Sciences: Nonreductive Physicalism without Levels of Reality or Multiple Realizability.Matthew C. Haug -2011 -The Monist 94 (2):244-266.
    In this paper, I investigate how different views about the vertical and horizontal structure of reality affect the debate between reductive and nonreductive physicalism. This debate is commonly assumed to hinge on whether there are high-level, special-science properties that are distinct from low-level physical properties and whether the alleged multiple realizability of high-level properties establishes this. I defend a metaphysical interpretation of nonreductive physicalismin the absence of both of these assumptions. Adopting an independently motivated, discipline-relative account of natural properties and (...) appealing to a phenomenon I call “multiple determinativity,” in which a single physical property simultaneously realizes different kinds of special-science properties, is sufficient to show that some special-science properties are irreducible to physical properties and that nonreductive physicalism is not merely a terminological variant of reductive physicalism. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48.  294
    Intellectual virtues: an essay in regulative epistemology.Robert C. Roberts &W. JayWood -2007 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by W. Jay Wood.
    From the ferment of recent debates about the intellectual virtues, Roberts andWood develop an approach they call 'regulative epistemology', exploring the connection between knowledge and intellectual virtue. In the course of their argument they analyse particular virtues of intellectual life - such as courage, generosity, and humility - in detail.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   159 citations  
  49.  116
    Situationism and the problem of moral improvement.Matthew C. Taylor -2019 -Philosophical Explorations 22 (3):312-327.
    A wealth of research in social psychology indicates that various ethically arbitrary situational factors exert a surprisingly powerful influence on moral conduct. Empirically-minded philosophers have argued over the last two decades that this evidence challenges Aristotelian virtue ethics. John Doris, Gilbert Harman, and Maria Merritt have argued that situationist moral psychology – as opposed to Aristotelian moral psychology – is better suited to the practical aim of helping agents act better. The Aristotelian account, with its emphasis on individual factors, invites (...) too much risk of morally bad conduct insofar as it ignores the power of situational factors which lead us astray. Moral agents are often better off detecting and intervening on situational factors to help themselves act better. This paper offers an argument against the claim that situationism enjoys practical advantages over Aristotelian virtue ethics. There is empirical evidence suggesting that people can improve their behavior via Aristotelian strategies of deliberate self-improvement. This evidence also suggests that focusing our ethical attention on morally trivial factors may result in worse overall conduct. Accordingly, Aristotelianism may fare better than situationism on the practical issue of moral improvement. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  57
    (1 other version)The Cartesian Unconscious.Matthew C. Eshleman -2007 -History of Philosophy Quarterly 24 (3):297 - 315.
1 — 50 / 971
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp