Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs
Order:

1 filter applied
Disambiguations
Mark T. Nelson [47]Mark Nelson [8]Mark D. Nelson [1]Mark W. Nelson [1]
Mark Douglas Nelson [1]
  1.  422
    We Have No Positive Epistemic Duties.Mark T. Nelson -2010 -Mind 119 (473):83-102.
    In ethics, it is commonly supposed that we have both positive duties and negative duties, things we ought to do and things we ought not to do. Given the many parallels between ethics and epistemology, we might suppose that the same is true in epistemology, and that we have both positive epistemic duties and negative epistemic duties. I argue that this is false; that is, that we have negative epistemic duties, but no positive ones. There are things that we ought (...) not to believe, but there is nothing that we ought to believe, on purely epistemic grounds. I also consider why the parallels between ethics and epistemology break down at this particular point, suggesting that it is due to what I call the infinite justificational ‘fecundity’ of perceptual and propositional evidence. (shrink)
    Direct download(9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   116 citations  
  2.  105
    Utilitarian Eschatology.Mark T. Nelson -1991 -American Philosophical Quarterly 28 (4):339-47.
    Traditional utilitarianism, when applied, implies a surprising prediction about the future, viz., that all experience of pleasure and pain must end once and for all, or infinitely dwindle. Not only is this implication surprising, it should render utilitarianism unacceptable to persons who hold any of the following theses: that evaluative propositions may not imply descriptive, factual propositions; that evaluative propositions may not imply contingent factual propositions about the future; that there will always exist beings who experience pleasure or pain.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  3.  330
    Paley before Hume: How Not to Teach the Design Argument.Mark T. Nelson -2024 -American Philosophical Association Studies on Teaching Philosophy 24 (1):2-10.
    Abstract: “Paley before Hume: How Not to Teach the Design Argument” Most philosophy of religion classes discuss the classic design argument for the existence of God, and many of these treat Paley’s Natural Theology (1802) before Hume’s Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (1779). Following the syllabus of several leading anthologies, I did this for many years, but I now think that is a mistake, because it creates the impression that Hume was responding to Paley. Not only is it obvious on chronological (...) grounds that Hume could not have been responding to Paley; it is just as obvious on textual grounds that the reverse was true: Paley was in fact responding to Hume, and, e.g., carefully crafted a non-analogical version of the argument so as to avoid Hume’s famous criticisms of analogical arguments. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  164
    Moral realism and program explanation.Mark T. Nelson -2006 -Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (3):417 – 428.
    Alexander Miller has recently considered an ingenious extension of Frank Jackson and Philip Pettit's account of 'program explanation' as a way of defending non-reductive naturalist versions of moral realism against Harman's explanatory criticism. Despite the ingenuity of this extension, Miller concludes that program explanation cannot help such moral realists in their attempt to defend moral properties. Specifically, he argues that such moral program explanations are dispensable from an epistemically unlimited point of view. I show that Miller's argument for this negative (...) claim is inadequate, and that he has, in spite of himself, identified a promising defence of moral realism. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  5.  96
    Is it Always Fallacious to Derive Values From Facts?Mark T. Nelson -1995 -Argumentation 9 (4):553-562.
    Charles Pigden has argued for a logical Is/Ought gap on the grounds of the conservativeness of logic. I offer a counter-example which shows that Pigden’s argument is unsound and that there need be no logical gap between Is-premises and an Ought-conclusion. My counter-example is an argument which is logically valid, has only Is-premises and an Ought-conclusion, does not purport to violate the conservativeness of logic, and does not rely on controversial assumptions about Aristotelian biology or 'institutional facts.'.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  6.  260
    More bad news for the logical autonomy of ethics.Mark T. Nelson -2007 -Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (2):203-216.
    Are there good arguments from Is to Ought? Toomas Karmo has claimed that there are trivially valid arguments from Is to Ought, but no sound ones. I call into question some key elements of Karmo’s argument for the “logical autonomy of ethics”, and show that attempts to use it as part of an overall case for moral skepticism would be self-defeating.
    Direct download(9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  7.  79
    What justification could not be.Mark T. Nelson -2002 -International Journal of Philosophical Studies 10 (3):265 – 281.
    I begin by asking the meta-epistemological question, 'What is justification?', analogous to the meta-ethical question, 'What is rightness?' I introduce the possibility of non-cognitivist, naturalist, non-naturalist, and eliminativist answers in meta-epistemology,corresponding to those in meta-ethics. I devote special attention to the naturalistic hypothesis that epistemic justification is identical to probability, showing its antecedent plausibility. I argue that despite this plausibility, justification cannot be identical with probability, under the standard interpretation of the probability calculus, for the simple reason that justification can (...) increase indefinitely but probability cannot. I then propose an alternative model for prima facie justification, based on an analogy with Ross's account of prima facie obligation, arguing that this model illuminates the differences between justification and probability and, given the plausible assumption of epistemic pluralism, explains them as well. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  8.  96
    Who Needs Valid Moral Arguments?Mark T. Nelson -2003 -Argumentation 17 (1):35-42.
    Why have so many philosophers agonised over the possibility of valid arguments from factual premises to moral conclusions? I suggest that they have done so, because of worries over a sceptical argument that has as one of its premises, `All moral knowledge must be non-inferential, or, if inferential, based on valid arguments or strong inductive arguments from factual premises'. I argue that this premise is false.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  9.  119
    The Morality of a Free Market for Transplant Organs.Mark T. Nelson -1991 -Public Affairs Quarterly 5 (1):63-79.
    There is a world-wide shortage of kidneys for transplantation. Many people will have to endure lengthy and unpleasant dialysis treatments, or die before an organ becomes available. Given this chronic shortage, some doctors and health economists have proposed offering financial incentives to potential donors to increase the supply of transplantable organs. In this paper, I explore objections to the practice of buying and selling organs from the point of view 1) justice, 2) beneficence and 3) Commodification. Regarding objection to the (...) Commodification of transplant organs, I examine a number of possible justifications of this objection but conclude that each of these would, if true, rule out the donation of transplant organs or the selling of numerous accepted commodities, or is implausible for some other reason. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10.  131
    Morally serious critics of moral intuitions.Mark Nelson -1999 -Ratio 12 (1):54–79.
    I characterise moral intuitionism as the methodological claim that one may legitimately appeal to moral judgments in the course of moral reasoning even when those judgments are not supported by inference from other judgments. I describe two patterns of criticism of this method: ‘morally unserious’ criticisms, which hold that ‘morality is bunk’, so appeals to moral intuitions are bunk as well; and ‘morally serious’ criticisms, which hold that morality is not bunk, but that appeals to moral intuition are nonetheless misguided. (...) I consider morally serious criticisms of Kantian and Aristotelian provenance, but defend the intuitionist method from both. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11.  413
    Absolutism, Utilitarianism and Agent-Relative Constraints.Mark T. Nelson -2022 -International Philosophical Quarterly 62 (2):243-252.
    Absolutism—the idea that some kinds of acts are absolutely wrong and must never be done—plays an important role in medical ethics. Nicholas Denyer has defended it from some influential consequentialist critics who have alleged that absolutism is committed to “agent-relative constraints” and therefore intolerably complex and messy. Denyer ingeniously argues that, if there are problems with agent-relative constraints, then they are problems for consequentialism, since it contains agent-relative constraints, too. I show that, despite its ingenuity, Denyer’s argument does not succeed. (...) The defense of absolutism must move to other grounds. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  67
    Intuitionism and conservatism.Mark T. Nelson -1990 -Metaphilosophy 21 (3):282-293.
    I define ethical intuitionism as the view that it is appropriate to appeal to inferentially unsupported moral beliefs in the course of moral reasoning. I mention four common objections to this view, including the view that all such appeals to intuition make ethical theory politically and noetically conservative. I defend intuitionism from versions of this criticism expressed by R.B. Brandt, R.M. Hare and Richard Miller.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13.  88
    An aristotelian business ethics?Mark T. Nelson -1998 -Journal of Applied Philosophy 15 (1):89–104.
    Elaine Sternberg's Just Business is one of the first book-length Aristotelian treatments of business ethics. It is Aristotelian in the sense that Sternberg begins by defining the nature of business in order to identify its end, and, thence, normative principles to regulate it. According to Sternberg, the nature of business is 'the selling of goods or services in order to maximise long-term owner value', therefore all business behaviour must be evaluated with reference to the maximisation of long-term owner value, constrained (...) only by considerations of ordinary decency and distributive justice. This stands in sharp contrast to recently popular 'stakeholder' approaches to business decision making. I argue that Sternberg's definition of business, particularly in its maximising and long-term conditions, is flawed, that her teleological method raises more questions than it solves, and that her Aristotelianism cannot be wedded happily to her libertarianism. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  50
    Who are the best judges of theistic arguments?Mark T. Nelson -1996 -Sophia 35 (2):1-12.
    The best judge of the soundness of a philosophical argument is the philosopher with the greatest philosophical aptitude, the deepest knowledge of the relevant subject matter, the most scrupulous character, and a disinterested position with respect to the subject matter. This last feature is important because even a highly intelligent and scrupulous judge may find it hard to reach the right conclusion about a subject in which he or she has a vested interest. When the subject of inquiry is the (...) soundness of theistic arguments, the best judge will be the most intelligent and scrupulous philosopher who is also disinterested in the soundness of the theistic argument under consideration. I argue that, in this case, the disinterestedness requirement is best satisfied by the theist whose belief in God is “properly basic”, and in the course of defending this argument I uncover a little-recognized desideratum for theistic arguments. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  35
    Peace Data Standard: A Practical and Theoretical Framework for Using Technology to Examine Intergroup Interactions.Rosanna E. Guadagno,Mark Nelson &Laurence Lock Lee -2018 -Frontiers in Psychology 9.
  16.  36
    Introduction to Special Issue on the Problem of the Criterion.Mark T. Nelson -2011 -Philosophical Papers 40 (3):279-283.
    Philosophical Papers, Volume 40, Issue 3, Page 279-283, November 2011.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  50
    Is/Ought Fallacy.Mark T. Nelson -2018-05-09 - In Robert Arp, Steven Barbone & Michael Bruce,Bad Arguments. Wiley. pp. 360–363.
    This chapter focuses on one of the common fallacies in Western philosophy called the 'is/ought fallacy (IOF)'. Some philosophers conclude that the IOF is not a logical problem but an epistemological one, meaning that even if inferences like this one are logically valid, they cannot be used epistemologically to warrant anyone's real‐life moral beliefs. Arguments do not warrant their conclusions unless the premises of those arguments are themselves warranted, and in the real world, they say, no one would ever be (...) warranted in believing premise. Charles Pigden argues for the illegitimacy of the move from is to ought, saying that we should understand David Hume as pointing to the conservativeness of logic. According to Pigden, logic is conservative in that “the conclusions of a valid inference are contained within the premises. You do not get out what you have not put in”. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  370
    The Principle of Sufficient Reason: A Moral Argument.Mark T. Nelson -1996 -Religious Studies 32 (1):15-26.
    The Clarke/Rowe version of the Cosmological Argument is sound only if the Principle of Sufficient Reason (PSR) is true, but many philosophers, including Rowe, think that there is not adequate evidence for the principle of sufficient reason. I argue that there may be indirect evidence for PSR on the grounds that if we do not accept it, we lose our best justification for an important principle of metaethics, namely, the Principle of Universalizability. To show this, I argue that all the (...) other justifications of the Principle of Universalizability on offer, including Richard Hare's, are inadequate. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  356
    Bertrand Russell's Defence of the Cosmological Argument.Mark T. Nelson -1998 -American Philosophical Quarterly 35 (1):87-100.
    According to the cosmological argument, there must be a self-existent being, because, if every being were a dependent being, we would lack an explanation of the fact that there are any dependent beings at all, rather than nothing. This argument faces an important, but little-noticed objection: If self-existent beings may exist, why may not also self-explanatory facts also exist? And if self-explanatory facts may exist, why may not the fact that there are any dependent beings be a self-explanatory fact? And (...) if that fact is self-explanatory, why make recourse to self-existent beings? This line of questioning is surprisingly hard to answer, but I find resources for an answer in Bertrand Russell's logical atomism. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  37
    The Contingency Cosmological Argument.Mark T. Nelson -2011 - In Michael Bruce & Steven Barbone,Just the Arguments. Chichester, West Sussex, U.K.: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 18–21.
    A brief synopsis of the "contingency" version of the cosmological argument for theism, as developed by Samuel Clarke and explained/examined by William Rowe.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  223
    Non-contradiction: Oh Yeah and So What?Mark T. Nelson -2013 -Think 12 (34):87-91.
    The logical Law of Non-contradiction – that a proposition cannot be both true and false – enjoys a special, perhaps uniquely privileged, status in philosophy. Most philosophers think that finding a contradiction – the assertion of both P and not-P – in one's reasoning is the best possible evidence that something has gone wrong, the ultimate refutation of a position. But why should this be so? What reason do we have to believe it? In this paper, I address these questions.
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  106
    Promises and Material Conditionals.Mark T. Nelson -1993 -Teaching Philosophy 16 (2):155-156.
    Some beginning logic students find it hard to understand why a material conditional is true when its antecedent is false. I draw an analogy between conditional statements and conditional promises (especially between true conditional statements and unbroken conditional promises) that makes this point of logic less counter-intuitive.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  82
    Telling it like it is: Philosophy as Descriptive Manifestation.Mark T. Nelson -2005 -American Philosophical Quarterly 42 (3):2005.
    What do Ross’s The Right and the Good; Chisholm’s Theory of Knowledge; Kripke’s Naming and Necessity; and Audi’s The Architecture of Reason have in common? They all advance important philosophical positions, but not so much via analytic arguments as via formal schemas, distinctions, examples, and analogies. They use such formal schemas, etc, to describe the world so as to make some aspect of it manifest. That is, they simply try to ‘tell it like it is’. This ‘method of descriptive manifestation’ (...) is less commonly recognized than it should be given its divergence from the self-image of analytic philosophy. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  104
    What the Utilitarian Cannot Think.Mark T. Nelson -2015 -Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18 (4):717-729.
    I argue that utilitarianism cannot accommodate a basic sort of moral judgment that many people want to make. I raise a real-life example of shockingly bad behavior and ask what can the utilitarian say about it. I concede that the utilitarian can say that this behavior caused pain to the victim; that pain is bad; that the agent’s behavior was impermissible; even that the agent’s treatment of the victim was vicious. However, there is still one thing the utilitarian cannot say, (...) namely that the agent wronged the victim, that they violated her. According to utilitarianism, moral offenses are offenses against global utility, right reason or the totality of sentient beings, but never against individual victims, yet this aspect of the action – that it is an offense against a particular person –is highlighted when we say that this action wronged that woman. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  123
    Naturalistic Ethics and the Argument from Evil.Mark T. Nelson -1991 -Faith and Philosophy 8 (3):368-379.
    Philosophical naturalism is a cluster of views and impulses typically taken to include atheism, physicalism, radical empiricism or naturalized epistemology, and some sort of relativism, subjectivism or nihilism about morality. I argue that a problem arises when the naturalist offers the argument from evil for atheism. Since the argument from evil is a moral argument, it cannot be effectively deployed by anyone who holds the denatured ethical theories that the naturalist typically holds. In the context of these naturalistic ethical theories, (...) the argument from evil typically fails to provide good reason for either the naturalist or the theist to disbelieve in the God of theism. This does not prove that naturalism is false, or that the argument from evil is unsound, but rather that certain naturalists’ use of the argument has been misguided. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  125
    Sinnott–Armstrong's Moral Scepticism.Mark T. Nelson -2003 -Ratio 16 (1):63-82.
    Walter Sinnott-Armstrong’s recent defence of moral scepticism raises the debate to a new level, but I argue that it is unsatisfactory because of problems with its assumption of global scepticism, with its use of the Sceptical Hypothesis Argument, and with its use of the idea of contrast classes and the correlative distinction between ‘everyday’ justification and ‘philosophical’ justification. I draw on Chisholm’s treatment of the Problem of the Criterion to show that my claim that I know that, e.g., baby-torture is (...) wrong, is no more question-begging than Sinnott-Armstrong’s denial that I know this. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  167
    Y and Z Are Not Off the Hook: The Survival Lottery Made Fairer.Mark T. Nelson -2010 -Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 35 (4):396-401.
    In this article I show that the argument in John Harris's famous "Survival Lottery" paper cannot be right. Even if we grant Harris's assumptions—of the justifiability of such a lottery, the correctness of maximizing consequentialism, the indistinguishability between killing and letting die, the practical and political feasibility of such a scheme—the argument still will not yield the conclusion that Harris wants. On his own terms, the medically needy should be less favored (and more vulnerable to being killed), than Harris suggests.
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  177
    A problem for conservatism.Mark T. Nelson -2009 -Analysis 69 (4):620-630.
    I present a problem for a prominent kind of conservatism, viz., the combination of traditional moral & religious values, patriotic nationalism, and libertarian capitalism. The problem is that these elements sometimes conflict. In particular, I show how libertarian capitalism and patriotic nationalism conflict via a scenario in which the thing that libertarian capitalists love – unregulated market activity – threatens what American patriots love – a strong, independent America. Unrestricted libertarian rights to buy and sell land would permit the sale (...) of all American territory by private individuals to foreign powers. Patriotic nationalists regard this as outrageous, but libertarian capitalists cannot refuse it. (shrink)
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  31
    Christian theism and moral philosophy.Michael D. Beaty,Carlton D. Fisher &Mark Nelson (eds.) -1998 - Macon, Ga.: Mercer University Press.
    These essays exhibit explanation and argument regarding some of the possible answers to these fundamental questions in moral philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  66
    Culture and Character Education: Problems of Interpretation in a Multicultural Society.John Chambers Christopher,Tamara Nelson &Mark D. Nelson -2003 -Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 23 (2):81-101.
    In response to a growing perception that America's youth lack the necessary values to grow and develop into adulthood in a socially healthy manner, character education has emerged as a rapidly growing proactive approach that serves to develop good character among young people. The authors examine several of the virtues thought to underlie good character from Character Counts!, a popular character education program, and emphasize the cultural complexities involved when promoting character education in a pluralistic society. 2012 APA, all rights (...) reserved). (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  82
    The Possibility of Inductive Moral Arguments.Mark T. Nelson -2006 -Philosophical Papers 35 (2):231-246.
    Is it possible to have moral knowledge? ‘Moral justification skeptics’ hold it is not, because moral beliefs cannot have the sort of epistemic justification necessary for knowledge. This skeptical stance can be summed up in a single, neat argument, which includes the premise that ‘Inductive arguments from non-moral premises to moral conclusions are not possible.’ Other premises in the argument may rejected, but only at some cost. It would be noteworthy, therefore, if ‘inductive inferentialism’ about morals were shown to be (...) at least possible. Some philosophers may suppose that inductive moral arguments from non-moral premises cannot get off the ground, but I show that a perfectly legitimate inductive moral argument exists. This argument has non-moral premises and a moral conclusion, its premises are related to its conclusion in the right way, and it avoids some of the problems of other, better-known arguments from ‘Is’ to ‘Ought’. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  63
    Bald Lies.Mark Nelson -1996 -Cogito 10 (3):235-237.
    I present a short, informal vignette that poses the question of whether altering one's appearance by wearing a wig counts as deception, since in both cases one (apparently) tries to bring about false beliefs in others. The bald-headed wig-wearer tries to get others to believe falsely that he has a thick head of hair. If deception is generally wrong, why isn't wig-wearing wrong also?
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  40
    Commentary: Practical Wisdom and Theory.Mark T. Nelson -2012 -Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 21 (3):404-408.
    This paper is an ethical reflection on the real-life case of "Angela", a highly intelligent but severely anorexic young woman who wishes to refuse all but palliative treatment. It is part of CQHE's "Ethics Committees and Consultants at Work" series, in response to the essay, "Starving for Perfection.".
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  19
    Could there be an Atheistic Political Theology?Mark T. Nelson -2021 -Forum Philosophicum: International Journal for Philosophy 26 (2):303-327.
    “Only a God can save us.” So says Martin Heidegger in his pessimistic assessment of merely human philosophy’s ability to change the world. The thought is not unique to Heidegger: another thinker who arrived at a similar conclusion was Heidegger’s contemporary and sometime admirer, Carl Schmitt, in his idea of “political theology.” I take up Schmitt’s version of the idea and use it to examine the New Atheism, a relatively recent polemical critique of religion by an informal coalition of English-speaking (...) scientists, philosophers, and writers. Taking Sam Har­ris’s book The End of Faith (2005) as my test case, I ask whether the New Atheism can instructively be read as a Schmittian “political theology”, not least because of its strongly anti-liberal implications for toleration of religious belief and practice. I close by posing the question of what sort of theory would deserve to be called an atheistic political theology and whether such a theory exists, or could exist. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  45
    (1 other version)Eliminative materialism and substantive commitments.Mark T. Nelson -1991 -International Philosophical Quarterly (March) 39 (March):39-49.
    This paper is an attempt to bring some order to a classic debate over the mind/body problem. I formulate the dualist, identity, and eliminativist positions and then examine the disagreement between eliminativists and their critics. I show how the apparent impasse between eliminativists and non-eliminativists can be helpfully interpreted in the light of the higher-order debate over methodological versus substantive commitments in philosophy. I argue that non-eliminativist positions can be defended using Roderick Chisholm's defense of what he calls "particularism" in (...) the problem of the criterion. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  95
    Intuitionism and subjectivism.Mark T. Nelson -1991 -Metaphilosophy 22 (1-2):115-121.
    I define ethical intuitionism as the view that it is appropriate to appeal to inferentially unsupported moral beliefs in the course of moral reasoning. I mention four common objections to this view, including the view that all such appeals to intuitionism collapse into “subjectivism”, i.e., that they make truth in ethical theory depend on what people believe. I defend intuitionism from versions of this criticism expressed by R.M. Hare and Peter Singer.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  86
    Must we argue?Mark T. Nelson -2004 -The Philosophers' Magazine 26 (26):41-42.
    Analytic philosophers often claim that the giving and criticizing of deductive arguments is the main or only business of philosophy. I argue that this is mistaken and show analytic philosophers also use formal schemas, distinctions, examples, and analogies so as to make some aspect of reality manifest. That is, some analytic philosophers sometimes simply try to ‘tell it like it is’. This ‘method of descriptive manifestation’ is less commonly recognized than it should be given its divergence from the self-image of (...) analytic philosophy. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  69
    On the lack of ‘true philosophic spirit’ in Aquinas: Commitment V. tracking in philosophic method.Mark T. Nelson -2001 -Philosophy 76 (2):283-296.
    Bertrand Russell famously disparaged Thomas Aquinas as having ‘little of the true philosophic spirit’, because ‘he does not, like the Platonic Socrates, set out to follow wherever the argument may lead.’ Like many of Russell's pronouncements, this is breathtakingly supercilious and unfair. Still, even an enthusiastic admirer of Aquinas may worry that there is something in it, that there is something wrong with religious ‘commitments’ in philosophy. I examine Russell's objection by comparing standards of permissibility in epistemology with standards of (...) permissibility in ethics, where these issues are better understood. I conclude that the epistemic standard behind Russell's criticism is no less contentious in epistemology than, say, direct utilitarianism is in ethics. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  37
    Redeeming the Time.Mark Nelson -1995 -The Personalist Forum 11 (1):17-32.
    I borrow an idea from the fiction of C. S. Lewis that future outcomes may affect the value of past events. I then defend this idea via the concept of a “temporal whole”, and show its promise as a partial theodicy and its resonance with both Christian theism and a robust personalism.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. The contingency cosmological argument.Mark T. Nelson -2011 - In Michael Bruce & Steven Barbone,Just the Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    I present and explain a brief version of the "contingency" cosmological argument earlier developed by Samuel Clarke and then updated by William Rowe.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  97
    Temporal Wholes and the Problem of Evil.Mark T. Nelson -1993 -Religious Studies 29 (3):313 - 324.
    I borrow an idea from the fiction of C. S. Lewis that future outcomes may affect the value of past events, defend this idea via the concept of a 'temporal whole' and show its promise as a part of a theodicy and its resonance with Christian theism.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Featured reports.Justin Stebbing,Rachaei Jones,Alan Winston,Mark Nelson,Stefan Mauss,Guenther Schmutz,Jonathan A. Winston,David M. Margolis,Alan D. Tice &Judith Feinberg -2005 -Contagion: Journal of Violence, Mimesis, and Culture 2 (7).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  21
    Knowledge and Evidence. [REVIEW]Mark T. Nelson -1993 -Philosophical Quarterly 43 (171):242-244.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  44.  56
    Just Business. [REVIEW]Mark Nelson -1996 -Philosophical Quarterly 46 (185):554.
  45.  156
    Review: Sabina Lovibond, Ethical Formation (Harvard, 2002). [REVIEW]Mark T. Nelson -2004 -Mind 113 (449):189-192.
    A critical review of Sabina Lovibond's book Ethical Formation (2004).
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  53
    Review of Robert Almeder Blind Realism: An Essay on Human Knowledge and Natural Science. [REVIEW]Mark T. Nelson -1995 -Philosophical Quarterly 45 (178):127-129.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47. A review of experimental and archival conflicts-of-interest research in auditing. [REVIEW]Mark W. Nelson -2005 - In Don A. Moore,Conflicts of interest: challenges and solutions in business, law, medicine, and public policy. New York: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  17
    Review of Charles Talliaferro Consciousness and the Mind of God. [REVIEW]Mark Nelson -1996 -Philosophical Books 37 (1):70-72.
  49.  47
    Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar, and Duncan Pritchard. [REVIEW]Mark T. Nelson -2014 -Mind 123 (490):609-612.
  50.  66
    John Hare God's call: Moral realism, God's commands, and human autonomy. (William B. Eerdmans, 2001). [REVIEW]Mark T. Nelson -2002 -Religious Studies 38 (2):225-246.
1 — 50 / 56
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp