Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'LaKisha Simmons'

597 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  14
    Conjure Feminism: Toward a Genealogy.Kinitra Brooks,Kameelah L. Martin &LaKishaSimmons -2021 -Hypatia 36 (3):452-461.
  2.  42
    Hypatia Special Issue: Conjure Feminism: Tracing the Genealogy of a Black Women's Intellectual Tradition: Volume 36, Issue 1, Winter 2021.Kinitra Brooks,Kameelah L. Martin &LaKishaSimmons -2019 -Hypatia 34 (1):170-171.
  3. Embedded EthiCS: Integrating Ethics Across CS Education.Barbara J. Grosz,David Gray Grant,Kate Vredenburgh,Jeff Behrends,Lily Hu,AlisonSimmons &Jim Waldo -2019 -Communications of the Acm 62 (8):54-61.
    The particular design of any technology may have profound social implications. Computing technologies are deeply intermeshed with the activities of daily life, playing an ever more central role in how we work, learn, communicate, socialize, and participate in government. Despite the many ways they have improved life, they cannot be regarded as unambiguously beneficial or even value-neutral. Recent experience shows they can lead to unintended but harmful consequences. Some technologies are thought to threaten democracy through the spread of propaganda on (...) online social networks, or to threaten privacy through the aggregation of datasets that include increasingly personal information, or to threaten justice when machine learning is used in such high-stakes, decision-making contexts as loan application reviews, employment procedures, or parole hearings. It is insufficient to ethically assess technology after it has produced negative social impacts, as has happened, for example, with facial recognition software that discriminates against people of color and with self-driving cars that are unable to cope with pedestrians who jay-walk. Developers of new technologies should aim to identify potential harmful consequences early in the design process and take steps to eliminate or mitigate them. This task is not easy. Designers will often have to negotiate among competing values—for instance, between efficiency and accessibility for a diverse user population, or between maximizing benefits and avoiding harm. There is no simple recipe for identifying and solving ethical problems. -/- Computer science education can help meet these challenges by making ethical reasoning about computing technologies a central element in the curriculum. Students can learn to think not only about what technology they could create, but also whether they should create that technology. Learning to reason this way requires courses unlike those currently standard in computer science curricula. A range of university courses on topics in areas of computing, ethics, society and public policy are emerging to meet this need. Some cover computer science broadly, while others focus on specific problems like privacy and security; typically, these classes exist as stand-alone courses in the computer science curriculum. Others have integrated ethics into the teaching of introductory courses on programming, artificial intelligence, and human-computer interaction. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  4.  91
    Universality and the Liar: An Essay on Truth and the Diagonal Argument.KeithSimmons -1993 - Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
    This book is about one of the most baffling of all paradoxes – the famous Liar paradox. Suppose we say: 'We are lying now'. Then if we are lying, we are telling the truth; and if we are telling the truth we are lying. This paradox is more than an intriguing puzzle, since it involves the concept of truth. Thus any coherent theory of truth must deal with the Liar. KeithSimmons discusses the solutions proposed by medieval philosophers and (...) offers his own solutions and in the process assesses other attempts to solve the paradox. Unlike such attempts,Simmons' 'singularity' solution does not abandon classical semantics and does not appeal to the kind of hierarchical view found in Barwise's and Etchemendy's The Liar. Moreover,Simmons' solution resolves the vexing problem of semantic universality – the problem of whether there are semantic concepts beyond the expressive reach of a natural language such as English. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  5.  170
    Sensible ends: Latent teleology in Descartes' account of sensation.Alison J.Simmons -2001 -Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (1):49-75.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 39.1 (2001) 49-75 [Access article in PDF] Sensible Ends:Latent Teleology in Descartes' Account of Sensation AlisonSimmons One of Descartes' hallmark contributions to natural philosophy is his denunciation of teleology. It is puzzling, then, to find him arguing in Meditation VI that human beings have sensations in order to preserve the union of mind and body (AT VII 83). 1 This appears (...) to be just the sort of teleological explanation that he proscribes. Descartes' Anglo-American commentators have had little to say about the teleological overtones of his claims about sensation. His French commentators acknowledge these overtones, but seem largely untroubled by them. 2 It is worth pausing to be troubled, for a closer analysis reveals that Descartes' famous proscription against teleology is not as simple as it is generally thought to be. In the first half of this essay, I argue that Descartes advocates a genuinely teleological conception of the senses. My aim is not to charge Descartes with employing illicit teleology, but to argue that there is a place for teleology even in his revisionist natural philosophy. Accordingly, in the second half of this essay, I argue that Descartes' assault on teleological explanation is [End Page 49] not a sweeping assault on finality, but a more directed attack on particular uses of ends in natural philosophy. Descartes' assault leaves standing a form of teleological explanation that proves crucial to his own treatment of sensation. 1. Descartes' Rejection of Teleological Explanation at a Glance A teleological explanation is one that purports to account for something in terms of its ends or its function relative to the ends of the system of which it is a part. Aristotle's physics provides many classic examples: plants produce leaves for the protection of their fruit; spiders spin webs in order to catch food; animals grow sharp front teeth and dull back teeth in order to facilitate biting and chewing respectively; eyes are for seeing. According to Aristotle, all natural phenomena are directed toward ends and no explanation is complete without a teleological component that specifies the end for the sake of which the phenomenon occurs. Indeed ends take explanatory priorityover other causes: "Both causes [the end and the matter] must be stated by the student of nature, but especially the end; for that is the cause of the matter, not vice versa." 3 And: [T]he causes concerned in natural generation are, as we see, more than one. There is the cause for the sake of which [the end], and the cause whence the beginning of motion comes [the efficient cause]. Now we must decide which of these two causes comes first, which second. Plainly, however, that cause is the first which we call that for the sake of which. For this is the account of the thing, and the account forms the starting-point.4In other words, Aristotle argues that natural substances have the matter they do, have the parts or organs they do, are organized as they are and act as they do for the sake of their ends. To explain why things are as they are, the natural philosopher must therefore explain the ways in which they contribute to ends.Among the late scholastic Aristotelians familiar to Descartes there is considerable debate concerning the causal efficacy of ends. Genuine final causation, in which something is said to be acted on by an end, is limited to the intentional behavior of rational agents who consciously recognize their ends: only something that recognizes an end can be "moved" by one. Even here the sort of causation involved is peculiar: a rational agent is "moved" by an end insofar as the end induces a "metaphorical motion" toward (or desire for) the end in the agent's will. 5 While these scholastic Aristotelians resist attributing final causation [End Page 50] to non-rational creatures, they nevertheless persist in attributing ends to them. When Toletus, Rubio, the Coimbrans and Suarez take up the question whether nature acts propter finem, each answers it affirmatively: natural... (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  6.  23
    Robert Cummings Neville, Defining Religion: Essays in Philosophy of Religion.J. AaronSimmons -2019 -International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 85 (2):271-277.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  9
    The Good Suburb.Simmons B. Buntin -2000 -Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 20 (4):331-332.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  252
    Are cartesian sensations representational?AlisonSimmons -1999 -Noûs 33 (3):347-369.
  9.  13
    Revitalizing the classics: what past social theorists can teach us today.Anthony MichaelSimmons -2013 - Halifax & Winnipeg: Fernwood Publishing.
    Revitalizing the Classics is a lively introductory text that relates classical social theories to contemporary social events. This updated definition of "the classics" avoids the Eurocentrism and androcentrism of many textbooks of social theory by including both non-European and women social thinkers. Besides highlighting the work of Ibn Khaldun and first wave feminist scholars, this book utilizes interactive figures, original source sidebars and current illustrative examples to provide a critical alternative to the standard texts in the field. In the process, (...) TonySimmons shows just how relevant classical social theories are in our present world, offering us analysis and clarification of a range of issues, from war, poverty and environmental destruction, to the sensory overload experienced in the digital age and even our personal relationships and interactions. Social theories are helpful - even necessary - to help us understand and, most importantly, be critical of the issues, systems and institutions in our world today. Revitalizing the Classics introduces students to a wide range of classical theorists and applies their theories to present-day examples: thus Durkheim's ideas are invoked to explore "anomie" in the digital world as well as the "altruistic" elements of suicide bombings in contemporary combat zones. Similarly, Ibn Khaldun's concept of "asabiyya" is used to explain the tribal code of the Taliban; Marx is summoned to explain the ever-widening gap between the rich and poor in Canada and around the world; and Pareto is enlisted to describe the "circulation of elites" in post-communist and post-colonial societies. Other sections explore and analyze the global war on terrorism and the Arab Spring. The book also includes a glossary of key concepts, giving readers an instant explanation of major terms and ideas used in each chapter. The combination of accessible writing and contemporary analysis provides a text that will empower readers to theorize and analyze many current events for themselves. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  744
    Ideal and nonideal theory.A. JohnSimmons -2010 -Philosophy and Public Affairs 38 (1):5-36.
  11.  507
    Moral Principles and Political Obligations.A. JohnSimmons -1979 - Princeton University Press.
    Every political theorist will need this book . . . . It is more 'important' than 90% of the work published in philosophy."--Joel Feinberg, University of Arizona.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  12.  38
    Whitehead's Metaphysics; an Introductory Exposition.James R.Simmons -1959 -Journal of Philosophy 56 (12):550-552.
  13. Disjunction and alternatives.M.Simmons -2002 -Linguistics and Philosophy 25.
  14. Locating'immaterialisation'in the sustainable development debate.StephenSimmons -2002 -Communication and Cognition. Monographies 35 (1-2):65-74.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  23
    Latina/o Social Ethics: Moving beyond Eurocentric Moral Thinking, and:Racism and God-Talk: A Latino/a Perspective.Kevin N. York-Simmons -2012 -Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 32 (1):199-201.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Latina/o Social Ethics: Moving beyond Eurocentric Moral Thinking, and: Racism and God-Talk: A Latino/a PerspectiveKevin N. York-SimmonsLatina/o Social Ethics: Moving beyond Eurocentric Moral Thinking Miguel A. de La Torre, Waco Tex.: Baylor University Press, 2010. 160 pp. $24.95.Racism and God-Talk: A Latino/a Perspective Rubén Rosario Rodríguez New York: New York University Press, 2008. 320 pp. $24.00Although Latina/o theologians have contributed much to Christian moral discourse in recent decades, (...) the impact of these contributions has too often remained limited to other Latina/os and those with particular interests in liberation theologies. Miguel de La Torre and Rubén Rosario Rodríguez build on the contributions of theologians before them while challenging the broader theological community to take notice of these rich and provocative works.In four concise chapters, Miguel de La Torre’s Latina/o Social Ethics delivers a forceful criticism of prominent thinkers in the field of Christian ethics and offers a creative reconstruction of ethics from a Latina/o perspective. De La Torre offers a critique of “Euroamerican” Christian ethicists whose works have greatly influenced contemporary Christian moral discourse. He addresses the writings of Walter Rauschenbusch, Reinhold Niebuhr, Stanley Hauerwas, Anthony Campolo, Ron Sider, and Jim Wallis. De La Torre faults these theologians for the ways in which their moral thinking participates in the oppression and marginalization of Latina/os, either through their silence or through their endorsement of specific polices. De La Torre concludes that the legacy of cultural and economic privilege and the oppression of Latinas/os are so [End Page 199] deeply embedded in the Eurocentric thinking that has dominated the field of Christian ethics that it cannot be the foundation for Latino social ethics.De La Torre’s aim is to “move beyond” Eurocentric modes of thinking rather than dwell on critique. This eagerness to move forward to the creative and constructive aspects of Latina/o ethics, however, limits the forcefulness of his critique of Euroamerican ethicists. De La Torre’s reading of Euroamerican ethics—and even the application of that term—is highly selective, both in terms of the thinkers chosen and the writings examined. While De La Torre’s criticisms of these thinkers are generally insightful and serve to illustrate his basic criticism of Eurocentric ethics, these criticisms are limited in their depth of analysis. De La Torre is less concerned with the broader historical and theological considerations at work in these Euroamerican ethicists than with their failures to adequately address issues of concern to Latinas/os.The second half of Latina/o Social Ethics moves to his constructive, or “reconstructive,” project. De La Torre reviews central concepts in the methodology of Latina/o social ethics, including lo cotidiano, nepantla, la lucha, en conjunto, and acompañamiento. De La Torre’s explanation of these terms is brief and accessible. Moving beyond these concepts, the fourth chapter of Latina/o Social Ethics offers a creative approach to a liberative ethics that draws on Christian tradition as well as broader Hispanic cultural resources, including folk characters and themes of the trickster found in Afro-Caribbean religious traditions. De La Torre addresses the concern for how to imagine a Christian ethics with a role for the trickster, including identifying trickster characters and themes in the Bible. His “disruptive ethics” challenges the preference for order over justice that has characterized Eurocentric ethics, for which he provides helpful examples. De La Torre is clearly concerned with imperialism, immigration, and free trade, yet it is unclear what justice means in those contexts. Perhaps due to the powerlessness of marginalized Latina/os, criticisms of injustice weigh far more heavily than visions of justice.The concise length of this book broadens its appeal. Academics unfamiliar with some of the concepts and methodologies of Latina/o theologians will find this short introduction a useful starting point. This provocative book would also be a welcome addition to the classroom, either in part or in its entirety.In contrast to De La Torre’s short work, Rubén Rosario Rodríguez sets a broader and more ambitious task in his Racism and God-Talk. His project... (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Territorial Rights: Justificatory Strategies.A. JohnSimmons -2015 - In David Sobel, Peter Vallentyne & Steven Wall,Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy, Volume 1. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK. pp. 145-72.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  18
    Grammar of Mandarin. By Jeroen Wiedenhof.Richard VanNessSimmons -2022 -Journal of the American Oriental Society 140 (3).
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  17
    History of the Chinese Language. By Hongyuan Dong.Richard VanNessSimmons -2021 -Journal of the American Oriental Society 137 (3).
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Essays on knowledge and methodology.Edward DwyerSimmons (ed.) -1965 - Milwaukee,: K. Cook Co..
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  13
    Francis Suarez on the Ontological Status of Individual Unity Vis-a-Vis the Aristotelian Doctrine of Primary Substance.John W.Simmons -2004 - Dissertation, Marquette University
    The present dissertation consists of a developmental account of the problem of the ontological status of individuality as manifested initially in the metaphysical thought of Aristotle and subsequently developed by Thomas Aquinas, Duns Scotus, and Francis Suarez. ;The philosophical context for the problem of individuality's ontological status is set by the theme, prominent in Greek philosophy, of unity as a mark of what is most real and most perfect. The historical precedent for viewing individuality as fitting under this theme, and (...) thus as having ontological importance, is provided by Aristotle's doctrine of primary substance, which characterizes individuality as a type of unity that pertains to the most fundamental aspects of reality such as this man or this horse. Though this doctrine highlights the ontological primacy of individual entities, the specific issues of where individuality fits on the ontological map, and what role it plays in constituting substances, are discussed only indirectly by Aristotle. These matters remain mostly unaddressed until the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries, in which individuality becomes a focal point of philosophical discussion due to the integration of Aristotelian metaphysical thought into Christian doctrine and the accompanying recognition of individuality as a topic of critical importance. ;The problem of individuality's ontological status can be summarized in terms of two questions. First, what kind of thing is individuality, i.e., where does it fit on the ontological map? Second, how is individuality related to the other metaphysical aspects of a thing, such as their form, common nature, etc.? Aquinas's treatment of this problem reveals strong roots in the Aristotelian doctrines of substance and of unity as a transcendental attribute of being. Scotus's account likewise is developed in the context of the aforementioned Aristotelian notions, but is more extensive than Aquinas's and more suggestive of individuality's importance given Scotus's identification of metaphysics as the science of the transcendentals and of individuality as a transcendental. Suarez's treatment of the ontological status of individuality builds upon these notions, synthesizing the insights of his predecessors to formulate an account that is more explicit, more precise, and in many ways more rigorous than his predecessors' accounts. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  8
    Kierkegaard's God and the good life.J. AaronSimmons (ed.) -2017 - Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press.
    Collected critical essays analyzing Kierkegaard’s work in regards to theology and social-moral thought. Kierkegaard’s God and the Good Life focuses on faith and love, two central topics in Kierkegaard’s writings, to grapple with complex questions at the intersection of religion and ethics. Here, leading scholars reflect on Kierkegaard’s understanding of God, the religious life, and what it means to exist ethically. The contributors then shift to psychology, hope, knowledge, and the emotions as they offer critical and constructive readings for contemporary (...) philosophical debates in the philosophy of religion, moral philosophy, and epistemology. Together, they show how Kierkegaard continues to be an important resource for understandings of religious existence, public discourse, social life, and how to live virtuously. “All in all, the editors of this volume have put together a thoughtful and sometimes provocative collection of essays by a number of Kierkegaard scholars and philosophers for the reader’s consideration.... The volume undoubtedly makes a contribution to contemporary philosophical debates in the philosophy of religion, moral philosophy, and epistemology, especially with regard to the importance of faith and love for leading a good and meaningful human life.” —International Journal for Philosophy of Religion “Invites the reader to think anew about what Kierkegaard was saying and what we can learn from him in the context of our time, particularly what it means to become a Christian in terms of the moral task of love and living a life worthy of a human being.” —Sylvia Walsh, translator of Kierkegaard’s Discourses at the Communion on Fridays. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Phenomenology for the 21st Century.J. AaronSimmons &James Hackett (eds.) -2016 - Palgrave-Macmillan.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  7
    Santiago F. Puglia, an early Philadelphia propagandist for Spanish American independence.Merle EdwinSimmons -1977 - Chapel Hill: U.N.C. Dept. of Romance Languages : distributed by University of North Carolina Press.
    Volume 195 in the North Carolina Studies in the Romance Languages and Literatures series.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  8
    The scientific art of logic.Edward DwyerSimmons -1961 - Milwaukee,: Bruce Pub. Co..
    This set is a selection of works which represent the best expositions of Thomistic approaches from the period between the first translation of Thomas Aquinas's Summa Theologiae into English in 1912 and the start of the Second Vatican Council in 1962.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  160
    Democratic Authority and the Boundary Problem.A. JohnSimmons -2013 -Ratio Juris 26 (3):326-357.
    Theories of political authority divide naturally into those that locate the source of states' authority in the history of states' interactions with their subjects and those that locate it in structural (or functional) features of states (such as the justice of their basic institutions). This paper argues that purely structuralist theories of political authority (such as those defended by Kant, Rawls, and contemporary “democratic Kantians”) must fail because of their inability to solve the boundary problem—namely, the problem of locating the (...) boundaries between different states' domains of authority in the natural or intuitive places. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  26. The Problem of Human Individuality with Emphasis on the Philosophy of Alfred North Whitehead.James RobertSimmons -1955 - Dissertation, Columbia University
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  235
    Cartesian Consciousness Reconsidered.AlisonSimmons -2012 -Philosophers' Imprint 12:1-21.
    Descartes revolutionized our conception of the mind by identifying consciousness as the mark of the mental: all and only thoughts are conscious. Today the idea that all thoughts are conscious seems obviously wrong. Worse, however, Descartes himself seems to posit a whole host of unconscious thoughts. Something is not as it seems. Either Descartes is remarkably inconsistent, or his claim that all thought is conscious is more nuanced than it appears. In this paper I argue that while Descartes was indeed (...) unwavering in his commitment to the conscious mark, he had the resources to distinguish different types and degrees of consciousness that make for a richer cognitive psychology than he is typically credited with. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  28.  56
    The realm of primitive recursion.HaroldSimmons -1988 -Archive for Mathematical Logic 27 (2):177-188.
  29.  45
    Leibnizian Consciousness Reconsidered.AlisonSimmons -2011 -Studia Leibnitiana 43 (2):196-215.
  30. Book Review. [REVIEW]J.Simmons -2005 -Philosophia Christi 7 (2):524-527.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  417
    Changing the cartesian mind: Leibniz on sensation, representation and consciousness.AlisonSimmons -2001 -Philosophical Review 110 (1):31-75.
    What did Leibniz have to contribute to the philosophy of mind? To judge from textbooks in the philosophy of mind, and even Leibniz commentaries, the answer is: not much. That may be because Leibniz’s philosophy of mind looks roughly like a Cartesian philosophy of mind. Like Descartes and his followers, Leibniz claims that the mind is immaterial and immortal; that it is a thinking thing ; that it is a different kind of thing from body and obeys its own laws; (...) and that it comes stocked with innate truth-tracking intellectual ideas and an epistemically troubling habit of forming confused sensory ideas on the occasion of external corporeal events. Nothing is new. Of course, Leibniz adds unconscious perceptions to the mind in the form of his famous petites perceptions, and he offers a unique solution to the problem of mind-body interaction in the form of his infamous pre-established harmony. In the overall scheme of things, however, these look like minor alterations in a philosophy of mind that the Cartesians had been advocating for some fifty years. Or so it appears. (shrink)
    Direct download(12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  32.  253
    Associative political obligations.A. JohnSimmons -1996 -Ethics 106 (2):247-273.
    It is claimed by philosophers as diverse as Burke, Walzer, Dworkin, and MacIntyre that our political obligations are best understood as "associative" or "communal" obligations--that is, as obligations that require neither voluntary undertaking nor justification by "external" moral principles, but rather as "local" moral responsibilities whose normative weight derives entirely from their assignment by social practice. This paper identifies three primary lines of argument that appear to support such assertions: conceptual arguments, the arguments of nonvoluntarist contract theory, and communitarian arguments (...) (which emphasize both an "identity thesis" and a "normative independence thesis"). However, each of these lines of argument fails to show that political obligations are associative obligations. (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  33.  34
    Perceived numerosity as a function of array number, speed of array development, and density of array items.Walter H. Hollingsworth,J. PaulSimmons,Tammy R. Coates &Henry A. Cross -1991 -Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 29 (5):448-450.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34. Teachers' perspectives of teaching science–technology–society in local cultures: A sociocultural analysis.J. Randy McGinnis &PatriciaSimmons -1999 -Science Education 83 (2):179-211.
  35.  639
    Philosophical anarchism.A. JohnSimmons -2001 - InSocial Science Research Network. Cambridge University Press.
    Anarchist political philosophers normally include in their theories (or implicitly rely upon) a vision of a social life very different than the life experienced by most persons today. Theirs is a vision of autonomous, noncoercive, productive interaction among equals, liberated from and without need for distinctively political institutions, such as formal legal systems or governments or the state. This "positive" part of anarchist theories, this vision of the good social life, will be discussed only indirectly in this essay. Rather, I (...) want to focus here on the "negative" side of anarchism, on its general critique of the state or its more limited critique of the specific kinds of political arrangements within which most residents of modern political societies live. Even more specifically, I will center my discussion on one particular version of this anarchist critique - the version that is part of the theory now commonly referred to as "philosophical anarchism". Philosophical anarchism has been much discussed by political philosophers in recent years. But it has not, I think, been very carefully defined or adequately understood. My object here will be to clear the ground for a fair evaluation of philosophical anarchism, by offering a more systematic account of the nature of the theory and of possible variants of the theory, and by responding to the most frequent objections to the theory. I hope by this effort to present philosophical anarchism as a more attractive, or at least a less obviously flawed, political philosophy. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  36.  374
    The principle of fair play.A. JohnSimmons -1979 -Philosophy and Public Affairs 8 (4):307-337.
  37.  54
    The Limits of Obligation. [REVIEW]A. JohnSimmons -1984 -Philosophical Review 93 (2):300-303.
  38.  111
    The Lockean Theory of Rights.A. JohnSimmons -2020 - Princeton University Press.
    John Locke's political theory has been the subject of many detailed treatments by philosophers and political scientists. But The Lockean Theory of Rights is the first systematic, full-length study of Locke's theory of rights and of its potential for making genuine contributions to contemporary debates about rights and their place in political philosophy. Given that the rights of persons are the central moral concept at work in Locke's and Lockean political philosophy, such a study is long overdue.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  39.  317
    (1 other version)On the Territorial Rights of States.A. JohnSimmons -2001 -Noûs 35 (s1):300-326.
    When officials of some political society portray their state as legitimate - and when do they not! - they intend to be laying claim to a large body of rights, the rights in which their state's legitimacy allegedly consists. The rights claimed are minimally those that states must exercise if they are to retain effective control over their territories and populations in a world composed of numerous autonomous states. Often the rights states are trying to claim in asserting their legitimacy (...) go far beyond this minimum. But whether a state's claims are modest or extravagant, the rights claimed invariably fall into three categories. The first category is a set of rights held over or against those persons who fall within the state's claimed legal jurisdiction - what I will call rights over subjects. The second is a set of rights claimed against those persons without the state's jurisdiction - what we can call rights against aliens. And the third category is a set of rights held over a particular geographical territory (whose extent largely determines the scope of the state's jurisdiction) - call these rights over territory. The rights states claim in these three categories jointly define their conception of the sovereignty that they (or their governments or institutions) enjoy, sovereignty that is more extensive (strong, absolute) as the rights asserted in these categories are more numerous and wide-ranging. It is principally on the third of these categories - on the nature and possible moral bases for the claims states make over geographical territories - that I will focus in this essay. The modern state is a territorial entity, and it claims to be legitimately so. Sidgwick was surely correct when he wrote that "it seems essential to the modern conception of a State that its government should exercise supreme dominion over a particular portion of the earth's surface ... Indeed, in modern political thought the connection between a political society and its territory is so close that the two notions almost blend." Common sense seems to view the territoriality of the modern state as natural and unquestionable. That, perhaps, explains why so little has been written, either by contemporary theorists or by the authors of the classics of modern political philosophy, on the moral bases of the modern state's claimed rights over territory. States typically claim not only legal authority over their territories (i.e., that their rights over those territories should be affirmed by international law), but moral authority as well - at the very least insofar as the relevant principles of international law are thought themselves to have moral weight. My concern here, then, will be with the possible moral bases for the kinds of claims made over geographical territories by typical modern states. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  40.  124
    Historical rights and fair shares.A. JohnSimmons -1995 -Law and Philosophy 14 (2):149 - 184.
    My aim of this paper is to clarify, and in a certain very limited way to defend, historical theories of property rights (and their associated theories of social or distributive justice). It is important, I think, to better understand historical rights for several reasons: first, because of the extent to which historical theories capture commonsense, unphilosophical views about property and justice; then, because historical theories have fallen out of philosophical fashion, and are consequently not much scrutinized anymore; and finally, because (...) of (what I see as) the continuing need to better understand the historical components of our society's responsibilities to the descendants of victims of systematic injustice in our own past. The case I will have in mind throughout is that of the property claims of Native American tribes, claims based on their historical standing as the original owners of certain lands and resources. And while I will concentrate here only on the question of rectifying past violations of property rights, this will constitute at least a start to answering more general questions about just rectification, which includes the more serious and less compensable wrongs of violence against persons. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  41.  287
    The anarchist position: A reply to Klosko and Senor.A. JohnSimmons -1987 -Philosophy and Public Affairs 16 (3):269-279.
  42.  259
    (1 other version)Truth.Simon Blackburn &KeithSimmons (eds.) -1999 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This volume is designed to set out some of the central issues in the theory of truth. It draws together, for the first time, the debates between philosophers who favor 'robust' or 'substantive' theories of truth, and those other, 'deflationist' or minimalists, who deny that such theories can be given. The editors provide a substantial introduction, in which they look at how the debates relate to further issues, such as the Liar paradox and formal truth theories.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  43.  1
    Gabriel Biel and Occasionalism: Overcoming an Apparent Tension.Fred Ablondi &J. AaronSimmons -2011 -History of Philosophy Quarterly 28 (2):159.
  44.  32
    Brain evolution: A matter of constraints and permissions?Emmanuel Gilissen &Robert M. T.Simmons -2001 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (2):284-286.
    The article of Finlay et al. is an excellent example of identifying constraints in the development of the brain, and their implications on brain architecture in evolution. Here we further illustrate the importance of constraints by presenting a few examples of how a small number of biophysical mechanisms or even a single life history parameter can have an enormous impact on brain evolution.
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  7
    Kierkegaardian phenomenologies.J. AaronSimmons,Jeffrey Hanson &Wojciech Kaftanski (eds.) -2024 - Lanham: Lexington Books.
    Kierkegaardian Phenomenologies offers a timely consideration of phenomenological engagements within the thought of Søren Kierkegaard. This collection not only reflects the current state of scholarly conversations in Kierkegaardian studies and phenomenological research, but also envisions new directions in which they should go.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Michael Purcell, Levinas and Theology.J. A.Simmons -2007 -Philosophy in Review 27 (3):214.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. On Not Destroying the Health of One's Patients.LanceSimmons -1997 - In David S. Oderberg & Jacqueline A. Laing,Human lives: critical essays on consequentialist bioethics. New York, N.Y.: St. Martin's Press. pp. 144--60.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48. The moves we make.K. MerindaSimmons -2024 - In Jason W. M. Ellsworth & Andie Alexander,Fabricating authenticity. Bristol, CT: Equinox Publishing.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. What Would Freud Say to Voltaire? The Use of Dialogues in Survey Courses.LindaSimmons -2008 -Inquiry (ERIC) 13 (1):56-64.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  61
    Postmodern Kataphaticism: A Constructive Proposal.J. AaronSimmons -2012 -Analecta Hermeneutica 4.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 597
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp