Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  49
    (1 other version)Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics.James Cargile -1959 -Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (2):320-323.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   614 citations  
  2.  53
    Rational Belief Systems.James Cargile -1981 -Philosophical Review 90 (3):454.
  3.  298
    The sorites paradox.James Cargile -1969 -British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 20 (3):193-202.
  4.  80
    A Note on "Iterated Knowings".James Cargile -1970 -Analysis 30 (5):151 - 155.
    No categories
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  5.  110
    (1 other version)Pascal's Wager.James Cargile -1966 -Philosophy 41 (157):250-257.
    A. Pascal's statement of his wager argument is couched in terms of the theory of probability and the theory of games, and the exposition is unclear and unnecessarily complicated. The following is a ‘creative’ reformulation of the argument designed to avoid some of the objections which have been or might be raised against the original.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  6. Paradoxes: A Study in Form and Predication.James Cargile -1979 -Philosophy 55 (213):421-423.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  7.  94
    Paradoxes: A Study in Form and Predication.James Cargile -1979 - Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.
    The ancient semantic paradoxes were thought to undermine the rationalist metaphysics of Plato, and their modern relatives have been used by Russell and others to administer some severe logical and epistemological shocks. These are not just tricks or puzzles, but are intimately connected with some of the liveliest and most basic philosophical disputes about logical form, universals, reference and predication. Dr Cargile offers here an original and sustained treatment of this range of issues, and in fact presents an unfashionable defence (...) of a platonistic ontology. He argues that the paradoxes arise not from mistakes in classical assumptions about truth or from an ontology that includes propositions and properties, but from mistakes in describing what propositions and properties are conveyed by particular linguistic expressions. The book should interest, and may well surprise, philosophers and others concerned with semantics and the foundations of logic. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  8.  80
    On a Problem about Probability and Decision.James Cargile -1992 -Analysis 52 (4):211 - 216.
  9.  98
    Justification and Misleading Defeaters.James Cargile -1995 -Analysis 55 (3):216 - 220.
  10.  128
    Newcomb's paradox.James Cargile -1975 -British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26 (3):234-239.
  11.  138
    In reply to a defense of skepticism.James Cargile -1972 -Philosophical Review 81 (2):229-236.
  12.  171
    On "Alexander's" dictum.James Cargile -2003 -Topoi 22 (2):143-149.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  13.  166
    On Russell's argument against resemblance nominalism.James Cargile -2003 -Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (4):549 – 560.
    Russell famously argued that Resemblance Nominalism leads to a vicious infinite regress in attempting to avoid admitting universals. Saying that a number of things are white only in that they resemble a particular white thing leaves a number of resemblances to that white thing, each of them constituting the holding of the same relation to the paradigm, qualifying that resemblance relation as a universal. Trying to dismiss that new universal by appeal to resemblances between those first resemblances only leads to (...) a new universal of resemblance, and so on. It is argued here that this does not arise for a properly formulated resemblance theory, which only requires one complex relation among the many particulars we deal with, a complex relation which is not multiply instantiated and thus not a universal. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14.  53
    Definitions and Counter-Examples.James Cargile -1987 -Philosophy 62 (240):179 - 193.
    In his paper ‘A Function for Thought Experiments’, T. S. Kuhn asks: Ought we demand of our concepts, as we do of our laws and theories, that they be applicable to any and every situation that might conceivably arise in any possible world? Is it not sufficient to demand of a concept, as we do of a law or theory, that it be unequivocally applicable in every situation which we expect ever to encounter?
    No categories
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  117
    On the Burden of Proof.James Cargile -1997 -Philosophy 72 (279):59 - 83.
    The phrase ‘burden of proof’ or ‘onus probandi’ originally referred to something determined by a judge in a legal proceeding. Some claims would be accepted as true by the court, and other relevant claims would require proving. The burden of doing this proving could be assigned to one or another party by the judge. Success or failure to meet this burden could be determined by the judge or the jury, as could consequences of success or failure.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16.  72
    On Believing You Believe.James Cargile -1967 -Analysis 27 (6):177 - 183.
  17.  76
    The surprise test paradox.James Cargile -1967 -Journal of Philosophy 64 (18):550-563.
  18.  300
    The language of thought revisited.James Cargile -2010 -Analysis 70 (2):359-367.
    (No abstract is available for this citation).
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  73
    On omnipotence.James Cargile -1967 -Noûs 1 (2):201-205.
  20.  36
    The revision theory of truth.James Cargile -1995 -Philosophical Books 36 (3):165-173.
  21.  136
    Utilitarianism and the Desert Island Problem.James Cargile -1964 -Analysis 25 (1):23 - 24.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  117
    IV. Davidson's notion of logical form.James Cargile -1970 -Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 13 (1):129-139.
    (1970). IV. Davidson's notion of logical form 1. Inquiry: Vol. 13, No. 1-4, pp. 129-139.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23.  53
    The Ontological Argument.James Cargile -1975 -Philosophy 50 (191):69 - 80.
    There are several styles of ontological argument. Here are examples of the first style. God has all perfections. Existence is a perfection. ∴God exists. All perfect beings exist. God is a perfect being. ∴God exists. God couldn't be improved. A being that doesn't exist could be improved . ∴God exists.
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24. (2 other versions)The Fallacy of Epistemicism.James Cargile -2005 - In Tamar Szabó Gendler & John Hawthorne,Oxford Studies in Epistemology. Oxford University Press. pp. 33.
  25. Logical form.James Cargile -2009 - In Jonathan Lear & Alex Oliver,The Force of Argument: Essays in Honor of Timothy Smiley. New York: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  351
    Skepticism and possibilities.James Cargile -2000 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (1):157-171.
    One skeptical strategy against A’s claim to know that P is to hold that it is logically possible for someone to have the same “base” for P as A does in spite of its not being true that P. Philosophical replies have focussed on showing that these are not genuine possibilities. Whether they are can be an interesting question of metaphysics, but it is argued in this paper that this metaphysical discussion is not the proper focus for an assessment of (...) skepticism. Even if there are the odd logical possibilities, they do not suffice to warrant skeptical doubts. Rather, there has to be good reason to think that there is a genuine chance of the alleged possibility obtaining. This requirement cannot be satisfied generically, and that is what is wrong with generic skepticism. (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  65
    Rational Decision and Causality by Ellery Eells. [REVIEW]James Cargile -1984 -Journal of Philosophy 81 (3):163-168.
  28.  147
    Some comments on fatalism.James Cargile -1996 -Philosophical Quarterly 46 (182):1-11.
    This paper discusses fatalism, defined as the view that it is never both in one's power to do X and in one's power to not do X. It is argued that this view is made out as more plausible than it really is, because of unclarity as to its meaning. Some philosophers, such as Michael Dummett or David Lewis, who criticise fatalism, actually advocate views closely in line with fatalism as defined here.
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  166
    The problem of induction.James Cargile -1998 -Philosophy 73 (2):247-275.
    No one doubts that philosophers have discussed at length ‘the problem of induction’, but it would also be generally recognized that there would be disagreement as to precisely what that problem is. Rather than tackle the formulation problem, I will borrow from a popular text: Our existence as well as science itself is based on the principle of induction that tells us to reason from past frequencies to future likelihoods, from the limited known of the past and present to the (...) unknown of the past, present, and future ... But though inductive probability is psychologically inescapable, we have trouble providing a rational justification for it. We might say, then, that there is such a practice as induction, and a problem associated with it is that of justifying engaging in it. We engage in reasoning from things we know about the past and present to conclusions about the past, present and future. We can't resist doing this but we have trouble finding a rational justification for doing so. This problem suggests a generalization. We engage in reasoning, reaching new conclusions. It would be hard to resist engaging in this practice. How do we provide a rational justification for it? (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  73
    What Is a Natural Property?James Cargile -1989 -Philosophy 64 (248):137 - 158.
    In Principia Ethica Moore held that the meaning of the word ‘good’ is a simple, unanalysable, non-natural property. Several features of this claim might be questioned. It might be questioned whether there are properties at all, and whether, even if there are, they are ever the meanings of words. Again, it might be questioned whether the word ‘good’ expresses a property, even assuming that some other words do. Moore considers this latter question, but not the former . The two questions (...) may seem connected by the fact that a negative answer to the first trivially leads to a negative answer for the second. But this triviality should be a caution to us. Otherwise we may confuse nominalism with ethical non-cognitivism or ‘anti-realism’. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  18
    [Omnibus Review].James Cargile -1975 -Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (4):584-587.
  32.  66
    Supposing for the Sake of Argument.James Cargile -1995 -Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 15 (1):76-79.
  33.  124
    Haack’s Evidence and Inquiry.James Cargile -1996 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (3):627-632.
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. (1 other version)Recent issues have included.Explaining Action,David S. Shwayder,Charles Taylor,David Rayficld,Colin Radford,Joseph Margolis,Arthur C. Danto,James Cargile,K. Robert &B. May -forthcoming -Foundations of Language.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  33
    Philosophy of language.Andrew Woodfield,James Cargile &Tadeusz Szubka -2005 -Philosophical Books 46 (3):272-278.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  51
    A note on "time, truth, and modalities".James Cargile &George Thomas -1968 -Mind 77 (308):572-574.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  80
    Critical Notice.James Cargile -1986 -Mind 95 (377):116 - 126.
  38.  10
    Logical Paradoxes.James Cargile -2002 - In Dale Jacquette,A Companion to Philosophical Logic. Malden, MA, USA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 103–114.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  68
    On an argument against closure.James Cargile -1999 -Noûs 33 (2):239-246.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  22
    On an interpretation oft, s4, ands.James Cargile -1972 -Philosophia 2 (1-2):137-158.
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  50
    (1 other version)On Consequentialism.James Cargile -1969 -Analysis 29 (3):78 - 88.
    … if someone really thinks, in advance, that it is open to question whether such an action as procuring the judicial execution of the innocent should be quite excluded from consideration—I do not want to argue with him; he shows a corrupt mind. (G. E. M. Anscombe, ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’, Philosophy, 1958, p. 17).
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42. On Goodman's Riddle of Induction.James Cargile -1970 -Ratio (Misc.) 12 (2):144.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  62
    On Having Reasons.James Cargile -1966 -Analysis 26 (6):189 - 192.
    Thesis: Even after the observation of the frequent or constant conjunction of objects, we have no reason to draw any inference concerning any object beyond those of which we have had experience. (Hume) Antithesis: A man who knows of at least one case of an X being a Y, and who does not know of any positive reason for thinking that an X might not be a Y, has some reason for thinking that all X's are Y's (p. 81). When (...) I speak of ‘some reason’ I mean the contradictory of no reason at all (p. 85). (‘A Possible Extension of Logical Theory?’ Geoffrey Hunter, Philosophical Studies 1965, pp. 81–8.). (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  80
    On near Knowledge.James Cargile -1971 -Analysis 31 (5):145 - 152.
  45.  59
    Panteísmo.James Cargile -2001 -Areté. Revista de Filosofía 13 (2):5-28.
    Este artículo empieza con varias interpretaciones de un eslogan panteísta básico. La ambigüedad del eslogan es ilustrada por una critica a la interpretación que Jonathan Bennett hace del panteísmo de Spinoza, según la cualla frase de Spinoza "Todo lo que es, está en Dios" implica que todo lo que está en Dios, es Dios. Seguidamente se arguye que el panteísmo no ofrece solución alguna al problema que tienen los teístas con respecto a si hay cosas distintas de Dios pero no (...) creadas por Dios. Luego se arguye que laexistencia del tipo de totalidad requerida por el panteísmo no es menos problemática que la existencia del Dios teísta en tanto creador. Finalmente, se sostiene que este último es un objeto apropiado de adoración de una manera en que el primero no lo es. (shrink)
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  13
    Possibility Versus Possible Worlds.James Cargile -2019 -Logos and Episteme 10 (2):147-164.
    It is a common idea in philosophy that some false propositions such as (C) that Charlottesville is the largest city in Virginia, have the property of being possibly true. It is not a clear idea but an important one which has inspired considerable effort at clarification. One suggestion is that there exist (really, not just possibly) “possible worlds” in which C or some suitable facsimile is true. One further attempt at clarification on offer is that there exists (again, really) a (...) maximal consistent set of propositions containing C. It is argued here that these attempts at clarification are profoundly erroneous. There exist actual powers of imaginative construction which would yield a scenario sufficiently detailed to be recognized by competent reviewers as one in which C is true. (The depiction might be in film or narrative and would avoid analytic falsehoods.) This is a frail clarification, vulnerable to questions, but is the best possible direction for a clear idea of the possibility of the proposition. The notion of possible worlds is associated with very valuable work in mathematical logic. It can only improve our appreciation of this excellent work to separate it from cloudy metaphysics. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  42
    Two Fallacies.James Cargile -2010 -Logos and Episteme 1 (2):257-268.
    In charging argumentum ad hominem, we accuse someone of attacking the source of a claim. In charging argumentum ad verecundiam, we attack the source of a claim. This is reason for attending to "attacking the source." It is important to distinguish probabilistic reasons for doubting a claim and evidentiary reasons. Evidence that the source of a claim is likely to be wrong is not evidence against the claim. The tendency to overlook this is the essential feature of the ad hominem (...) fallacy. This is relevant in assessing the view that someone who regards his thinking as made possible by Godless arrangements of matter largely determined by chance is, in taking this attitude, advancing a hypothesis which undermines his theorizing about the world or himself. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  39
    (1 other version)The First Person.James Cargile -forthcoming -Symposion. Theoretical and Applied Inquiries in Philosophy and Social Sciences.
    James Cargile ABSTRACT: Many languages have a first person singular subject pronoun. Fewer also have a first person singular object pronoun. The term ‘I’ is commonly used to refer to the person using the term. It has a variety of other uses. A normal person is able to refer...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  56
    The universalisability of lying.James Cargile -1965 -Australasian Journal of Philosophy 43 (2):229 – 231.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  91
    Vagueness. An Investigation into Natural Languages and the Sorites Paradox.James Cargile -1993 -Philosophical Books 34 (1):22-24.
1 — 50 / 68
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp