Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'Ian Caterson'

940 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  34
    Neural Response to Low Energy and High Energy Foods in Bulimia Nervosa and Binge Eating Disorder: A Functional MRI Study.Brooke Donnelly,Nasim Foroughi,Mark Williams,Stephen Touyz,Sloane Madden,Michael Kohn,Simon Clark,Perminder Sachdev,Anthony Peduto,IanCaterson,Janice Russell &Phillipa Hay -2022 -Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    ObjectiveBulimia nervosa and binge eating disorder are eating disorders characterized by recurrent binge eating episodes. Overlap exists between ED diagnostic groups, with BE episodes presenting one clinical feature that occurs transdiagnostically. Neuroimaging of the responses of those with BN and BED to disorder-specific stimuli, such as food, is not extensively investigated. Furthermore, to our knowledge, there have been no previous published studies examining the neural response of individuals currently experiencing binge eating, to low energy foods. Our objective was to examine (...) the neural responses to both low energy and high energy food images in three emotive categories in BN and BED participants.MethodsNineteen females with BN or BED, comprising the binge eating group, and 19 age-matched healthy control ’s completed thorough clinical assessment prior to functional MRI. Neural response to low energy and high energy foods and non-food images was compared between groups using whole-brain exploratory analyses, from which six regions of interest were then selected: frontal, occipital, temporal, and parietal lobes; insula and cingulate.ResultsIn response to low energy food images, the BEG demonstrated differential neural responses to all three low energy foods categories compared to HCs. Correlational analyses found a significant association between frequency of binge episodes and diminished temporal lobe and greater occipital lobe response. In response to high energy food images, compared to HC’s, the BEG demonstrated significantly decreased neural activity in response to all high energy food images. The HC’s had significantly greater neural activity in the limbic system, occipital lobe, temporal lobe, frontal lobe, and limbic system in response to high energy food images.ConclusionResults in the low energy food condition indicate that binge frequency may be related to increased aberrant neural responding. Furthermore, differences were found between groups in all ROI’s except the insula. The neural response seen in the BEG to disgust food images may indicate disengagement with this particular stimuli. In the high energy food condition, results demonstrate that neural activity in BN and BED patients may decrease in response to high energy foods, suggesting disengagement with foods that may be more consistent with those consumed during a binge eating episode. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  216
    Numerical ordering ability mediates the relation between number-sense and arithmetic competence.Ian M. Lyons &Sian L. Beilock -2011 -Cognition 121 (2):256-261.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  3. What is Frege's "Concept horse Problem" ?Ian Proops -2013 - In Sullivan Michael Potter and Peter,Wittgenstein's Tractatus: History and Interpretation. Oxford University Press. pp. 76-96.
    I argue that Frege's so-called "concept 'horse' problem" is not one problem but many. When these different sub-problems are distinguished, some emerge as more tractable than others. I argue that, contrary to a widespread scholarly assumption originating with Peter Geach, there is scant evidence that Frege engaged with the general problem of the inexpressibility of logical category distinctions in writings available to Wittgenstein. In consequence, Geach is mistaken in his claim that in the Tractatus Wittgenstein simply accepts from Frege certain (...) lessons about the inexpressibility of logical category distinctions and the say-show distinction. In truth, Wittgenstein drew his own morals about these matters, quite possibly as the result of reflecting on how the general problem of the inexpressibility of logical category distinctions arises in Frege's writings , but also, quite possibly, by discerning certain glimmerings of these doctrines in the writings of Russell. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  4.  131
    Attention to the passage of time.Ian Phillips -2012 -Philosophical Perspectives 26 (1):277-308.
  5.  281
    Putnam's theory of natural kinds and their names is not the same as kripke's.Ian Hacking -2007 -Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 11 (1):1-24.
    Philosophers have been referring to the “Kripke–Putnam” theory of naturalkind terms for over 30 years. Although there is one common starting point, the two philosophers began with different motivations and presuppositions, and developed in different ways. Putnam’s publications on the topic evolved over the decades, certainly clarifying and probably modifying his analysis, while Kripke published nothing after 1980. The result is two very different theories about natural kinds and their names. Both accept that the meaning of a naturalkind term is (...) not given by a description or defining properties, but is specified byits referents. From then on, Putnam rejected even the label, causal theory of reference, preferring to say historical, or collective. He called his own approach indexical. His account of substance identity stops short a number of objections that were later raised, such as what is called the qua problem. He came to reject the thought that water is necessarily H2O, and to denounce the idea of metaphysical necessity that goes beyond physical necessity. Essences never had a role in his analysis; there is no sense in which he was an essentialist. He thought of hidden structures as the usual determinant of natural kinds, but always insisted that what counts as a natural kind is relative to interests. “Natural kind” itself is itself an importantly theoretical concept, he argued. The paper also notes that Putnam says a great deal about what natural kinds are, while Kripke did not. Moreover, a theory about names of natural kinds is to some extent independent of a theory of natural kinds themselves, to the extent that one can accept the one and reject the other, even when both are advanced by the same philosopher. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  6.  52
    The Mystery of Being. I. Reflection and Mystery.Ian W. Alexander &Gabriel Marcel -1952 -Philosophical Quarterly 2 (6):94.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  7. (1 other version)Kant on the Ontological Argument.Ian Proops -2013 -Noûs 49 (1):1-27.
    The article examines Kant's various criticisms of the broadly Cartesian ontological argument as they are developed in the Critique of Pure Reason. It is argued that each of these criticisms is effective against its intended target, and that these targets include—in addition to Descartes himself—Leibniz, Wolff, and Baumgarten. It is argued that Kant's most famous criticism—the charge that being is not a real predicate—is directed exclusively against Leibniz. Kant's argument for this thesis—the argument proceeding from his example of a hundred (...) thalers—although it may seem to beg the question, in fact succeeds against Leibniz. It does so because the charge of begging the question can be rebutted if one makes certain Leibnizian assumptions. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  8. Epistemic Vices in Public Debate: The Case of New Atheism.Ian James Kidd -2017 - In Christopher Cotter & Philip Quadrio,New Atheism's Legacy: Critical Perspectives from Philosophy and the Social Sciences. Springer. pp. 51-68..
    Although critics often argue that the new atheists are arrogant, dogmatic, closed-minded and so on, there is currently no philosophical analysis of this complaint - which I will call 'the vice charge' - and no assessment of whether it is merely a rhetorical aside or a substantive objection in its own right. This Chapter therefore uses the resources of virtue epistemology to articulate this ' vice charge' and to argue that critics are right to imply that new atheism is intrinsically (...) epistemically vicious, and it ends with some remarks about the rationality of allowing such intrinsically vicious doctrines to feature within public debate about important matters concerning science, religion, and politics. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9.  7
    Faith in Schools?: Autonomy, Citizenship, and Religious Education in the Liberal State.Ian MacMullen -2007 - Princeton University Press.
    This is a work of normative political philosophy that seeks to identify the legitimate goals of public education policy in liberal democratic states and the implications of those goals for arguments about public funding and regulation of religious schools. ;The thesis of the first section is that the inferiority of certain types of religious school as instruments of civic education in a pluralist state would not suffice to justify liberal states in a general refusal to fund such schools. States with (...) no position on the value of autonomy for the good life would have to balance civic concerns against the preferences of religious parents who want to send their children to narrowly religious schools to shield them from exposure to ethical diversity. But, I argue, the principles of liberal democracy actually presuppose the value of autonomy. ;In the second section, I develop a conception of ethical autonomy and argue for its adoption as a public value. Autonomy, understood to entail distinctively rational reflection that must nonetheless inevitably be situated within an unchosen cultural context, can be publicly justified as having instrumental value to all persons in their quest to live a good life. And I defend the legitimacy of adopting autonomy as a goal of public education policy against a series of objections, most notably those grounded in claims about parental rights and fairness to traditional cultures. ;In the third section, I explore the implications of the autonomy goal for religious schools. After defending secular public schools from several prominent criticisms, I consider the argument that religious secondary schools are unsuitable to deliver education for autonomy because they provide children with inadequate exposure to and rational engagement with ethical diversity: I conclude that states cannot justify prohibiting or even presumptively denying public funding to all religious secondary schools, but that there is need for extensive public regulation. Finally, I argue that religious primary schools should be treated differently because of the particular developmental needs and capacities of pre-adolescents. Religious primary schools whose pedagogy is non-authoritarian are specially suitable to lay the foundations for autonomy in young children from religious families. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  10.  785
    ‘“What’s So Great About Science?” Feyerabend on the Ideological Use and Abuse of Science.Ian James Kidd -2016 - In Elena Aronova & Simone Turchetti,The Politics of Science Studies. pp. 55-76.
    It is very well known that from the late-1960s onwards Feyerabend began to radically challenge some deeply-held ideas about the history and methodology of the sciences. It is equally well known that, from around the same period, he also began to radically challenge wider claims about the value and place of the sciences within modern societies, for instance by calling for the separation of science and the state and by questioning the idea that the sciences served to liberate and ameliorate (...) human societies. But what is less known is how, if at all, these two sets of challenges were connected, and why Feyerabend felt it important to raise them at all. In this chapter, my aim is to explore these issues by considering why Feyerabend used radical strategies to challenge the authority of science, and what purpose, if any, they were supposed to serve. Why, for instance, did Feyerabend defend alternative medicine, psychical abilities, astrology, magic and witchcraft and why did he argue that ‘Western science’ is complicit in environmental destruction, intellectual imperialism, social oppression, and spiritual destitution. Located in their historical and political context, such defences and arguments seem peculiar, not least because science was recognised not only as a central site of the intellectual and ideological competition between the West and the Soviet Union, but also because Western victory in that site was considered inevitable. What, then, did Feyerabend think he was trying to achieve by raising radical challenges to a central component of the cultural and intellectual prestige of the Western world grounded in appeals to practices and traditions which most would regard as eccentric at best and absurd at worst? My suggestion is that Feyerabend was making a subtler point than one might suppose. For the purpose of these radical challenges was to determine if the members of Western societies would in fact honour the epistemic standards – of tolerance, critical enquiry – which were identified as being characteristic of science and definitive of the social and political values of Western liberal democracy. I suggest that Feyerabend was trying to demonstrate that scientists were, too often, guilty of the same intolerant and dogmatic attitudes which were, according to prevailing propaganda, the property of illiberal totalitarian societies. Science does not reflect the superior epistemic and political values of Western societies but are, in fact, reflective of the same vices ascribed to the Soviet Union. If that is the case, then the sciences are not symbols of our epistemic and political values, but quite the reverse, hence Feyerabend’s talk of the ‘dogmatic’, ‘totalitarian’, ‘ratiofascist’ nature of modern science. But there is a positive upshot to Feyerabend’s challenge. For even if the sciences do not yet reflect the epistemic and political values of liberal democratic Western societies, they might yet be reformed so that they are. And there is a parallel between Feyerabend’s strategy and that of many of the other radicals of the time – student activists, environmentalists, and pacifists – namely to test the commitment to tolerance and deliberative debate of the establishment by asking it to seriously engage with ideas and convictions opposed to its own. For both science and society can become ‘tyrannical’ through the same means: by exempting themselves from critical scrutiny, by promoting self-serving ‘myths’ about themselves, and by derogating and excluding alternatives, including the ‘outsider’ perspectives they offer. The chapter concludes by suggesting that Feyerabend is distinctive in virtue of his willingness to offer radical criticisms of the authority of science such that it can fulfil its legitimate ideological role – namely, of symbolising and instantiating our core epistemic and political values – such that we can offer a sincere and meaningful answer to Feyerabend’s question ‘what’s so great about science?’. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11.  137
    Is Scientism Epistemically Vicious?Ian James Kidd -2018 - In Jeroen de Ridder, Rik Peels & Rene van Woudenberg,Scientism: Prospects and Problems. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 222-249.
    This chapter offers a virtue epistemological framework for making sense of the common complaint that scientism is arrogant, dogmatic, or otherwise epistemically vicious. After characterising scientism in terms of stances, I argue that their components can include epistemically vicious dispositions, with the consequence that an agent who adopts such stances can be led to manifest epistemic vices. The main focus of the chapter is the vice of closed-mindedness, but I go on to consider the idea that arrogance and dogmatism are (...) ‘cooperative vices’, ones liable to be activated by closed-mindedness. I conclude that determining whether or not any given stance is vicious will require sensitivity to the ontology of that stance and the psychology of the agents who adopt them. This would be contribute to our understanding both of scientism and of epistemic virtuous and vicious characters or psychologies. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  12.  58
    Beyond Simulation–Theory and Theory–Theory: Why social cognitive neuroscience should use its own concepts to study “theory of mind”.Ian A. Apperly -2008 -Cognition 107 (1):266-283.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  13.  26
    D. Caradog Jones—An Appreciation.Ian W. Alexander -1974 -Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 5 (2):192-192.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  27
    De l'Existence a l'Etre. La Philosophie de Gabriel Marcel.Ian W. Alexander -1956 -Philosophical Quarterly 6 (22):82.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  39
    De l'Intimite Spirituelle.La Decouverte de Dieu.Ian W. Alexander,Louis Lavelle &Rene Le Senne -1958 -Philosophical Quarterly 8 (31):175.
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  50
    Jean Paul Sartre. Darstellung und Kritik seiner Philosophie.Ian W. Alexander &Hans Heinz Holz -1953 -Philosophical Quarterly 3 (13):369.
  17.  24
    Maine de Biran, by Antoinette Drevet.Ian W. Alexander -1971 -Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 2 (2):99-100.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  21
    Maine de Biran and Phenomenology.Ian W. Alexander -1970 -Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 1 (1):24-37.
  19.  19
    Reflection, Time and the Novel: Toward a Communicative Theory of Literature.by Angel Medina.Ian W. Alexander -1984 -Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 15 (1):90-92.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  35
    Schopenhauer.Ian W. Alexander -1964 -Philosophical Books 5 (2):14-16.
  21.  16
    Interpretation and Meaning in the Renaissance: The Case of Law.Ian Maclean -1992 - Cambridge University Press.
    This book investigates theories of interpretation and meaning in Renaissance jurisprudence.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  22.  619
    Is Naturalism Bleak? A Reply to Holland and Cottingham.Ian James Kidd -2013 -Environmental Values 22 (6):689-702.
    Although Cottingham and Holland make a persuasive case for the claim that it is difficult to situate a meaningful life within a Darwinian naturalistic cosmology, this paper argues that their case should be modified in response to the apparent fact that certain persons seem genuinely not to experience the ‘bleakness’ that they describe. Although certain of these cases will reflect an incomplete appreciation of the existential implications of Darwinian naturalism, at least some of those cases may be genuine. The resulting (...) possibility that certain persons can embrace Darwinian naturalism and live meaningful lives in apparent immunity to the ‘bleakness charge’ therefore poses new puzzles for Cottingham and Holland, and for wider questions about the meaningfulness of human life. I consider that possibility in light of the work of David E. Cooper and Paul Feyerabend and offer a set of three suggestions for further developing these debates. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23.  27
    Can theory of mind grow up? Mindreading in adults, and its implications for the development and neuroscience of mindreading.Ian Apperly -2013 - In Simon Baron-Cohen, Michael Lombardo & Helen Tager-Flusberg,Understanding Other Minds: Perspectives From Developmental Social Neuroscience. Oxford University Press. pp. 72.
  24. 'Introduction: The New Ideology'.Tom Bentley &Ian Hargreaves -2001 - In Tom Bentley & Daniel Stedman Jones,The Moral Universe. Demos. pp. 5--16.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  18
    Deliberative democracy.Ian O'Flynn -2021 - Medford, MA: Polity Press.
    The central concept in modern democratic theory outlined by a well-respected authority.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  57
    Evidence, Logic, the Rule and the Exception in Renaissance Law and Medicine.Ian Maclean -2000 -Early Science and Medicine 5 (3):227-256.
    This article sets out to investigate aspects of the uptake of Renaissance law and medicine from some of the logical and natural-philosophical components of the university arts course. Medicine is shown to have a much laxer operative logic than law, reflecting its commitment to the theory of idiosyncrasy as opposed to the demands made upon the law by the need for a uniform application of justice. Symptomatic of the different uptake arc the contrasting meanings of "regulariter" and "generaliter" in the (...) two disciplines. Whereas the law treats the rule as inviolable and the exception as only valid if made explicit in due legal form, medicine is able to conceive of a nature as a field of knowledge broader than that encompassed by its rules of art. Both law and medicine approach evidence. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  27.  99
    Technologies of the self: Habitus and capacities.Ian Burkitt -2002 -Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 32 (2):219–237.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  28.  111
    The shifting concept of the self.Ian Burkitt -1994 -History of the Human Sciences 7 (2):7-28.
  29.  74
    Education for autonomy: The role of religious elementary schools.Ian MacMullen -2004 -Journal of Philosophy of Education 38 (4):601–615.
    I argue that religious elementary schools whose pedagogical methods satisfy the principle of rational authority have distinctive advantages over secular elementary schools for the purpose of laying the foundations for ethical autonomy in the children of religious parents. Insights from developmental psychology bolster the argument from conceptual analysis. Before children have the cognitive capacities to engage in authentically autonomous reflection, their long-run interest in developing autonomy is best served by developing their understanding of and provisional identity within their primary culture (...) and by encouraging a limited form of ethical reasoning within the framework provided by that secure cultural identity. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  30.  11
    The Cambridge companion to Pufendorf.Knud Haakonssen &Ian Hunter (eds.) -2023 - New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
    In the same intellectual league as Grotius, Hobbes and Locke, but today less well known, Samuel Pufendorf was an early modern master of political, juridical, historical and theological thought. Trained in an erudite humanism, he brought his copious command of ancient and modern literature to bear on precisely honed arguments designed to engage directly with contemporary political and religious problems. Through his fundamental reconstruction of the discipline of natural law, Pufendorf offered a new rationale for the sovereign territorial state, providing (...) it with non-religious foundations in order to fit it for governance of multi-religious societies and to protect his own Protestant faith. He also drew on his humanist learning to write important political histories, a significant lay theology, and vivid polemics against his many opponents. This volume makes the full scope of his thought and writing accessible to English readers for the first time"--publisher's website. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Aquinas.John Thomas,Ian Dunn & Harris -1997
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  22
    Dismantling the Memory Machine: A Philosophical Investigation of Machine Theories of Memory.Ian G. Wallace -1980 -Philosophical Quarterly 30 (119):176-178.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  33.  5
    Services and the Knowledge-Based Economy.Mark Boden &Ian Miles (eds.) -2000 - Routledge.
    First published in 2000. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  8
    A Wittgensteinian Response to the Scope Problem.John Ian Boongaling -2013 -Philosophia: International Journal of Philosophy (Philippine e-journal) 14 (1):27-42.
    This paper seeks to develop a Wittgensteinian response to the Scope Problem, which ensnares a theory of truth considered as inflationary. The scope problem challenges any inflationary truth theory to provide a single explanation which can account for the concept of truth given the diversity of statements that most of us are willing to accept as true. In line with Wittgenstein's later-views on language and philosophy and their corresponding functions, this paper provides a general diagnosis of the problem: similarities in (...) syntax do not entail similarities in meaning. By employing Wittgenstein's metaphors (i.e., "handles" and "tools") and an analysis via concrete cases and analogies, this paper responds to the challenge presented by the Scope Problem, not by providing a satisfactory definition of truth but rather by providing its "dissolution" á la Wittgenstein. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Categorisation of sexual orientation: A test of essentialism.Nick Braisby &Ian Hodges -2009 - In N. A. Taatgen & H. van Rijn,Proceedings of the 31st Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. pp. 2956--2961.
  36.  41
    Fundraising Ethics: A Rights-Balancing Approach.Ian MacQuillin &Adrian Sargeant -2019 -Journal of Business Ethics 160 (1):239-250.
    The topic of fundraising ethics has received remarkably little scholarly attention. In this paper, we review the circumstances that precipitated a major review of fundraising regulation in the UK in 2015 and describe the ethical codes that now underpin the advice and guidance available to fundraisers to guide them in their work. We focus particularly on the Code of Fundraising Practice. We then explore the purpose and rationale of similar codes and the process through which such codes are typically constructed. (...) We highlight potential weaknesses with the current approach adopted in fundraising and conclude by offering a series of normative perspectives on fundraising ethics that could be used to review and revise the current code and potentially improve the quality of future fundraising decision making. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  55
    A mathematical model of Churchmanian inquiring systems with special reference to Popper's measures for?The Severity of Tests?Ian I. Mitroff,Frederick Betz &Richard O. Mason -1970 -Theory and Decision 1 (2):155-178.
    Through the use of Bayesian probability theory and Communication theory, a formal mathematical model of a Churchmanian Dialectical Inquirer is developed. The Dialectical Inquirer is based on Professor C. West Churchman's novel interpretation and application of Hegelian dialectics to decision theory. The result is not only the empirical application of dialectical inquiry but also its empirical (i.e., scientific) investigation. The Dialectical Inquirer is seen as especially suited to problems in strategic policy formation and in decision theory. Finally, specific application of (...) the inquirer is made to Popper's notions for ‘The Test of Severity’ of a scientific theory. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38. Semantic complexity in natural language.Ian Pratt-Hartmann -1996 - In Shalom Lappin,The handbook of contemporary semantic theory. Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell Reference.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Part 2: A Pilot Ethnomethodological Study.Michael Robertson,Ian Kerridge &Garry Walter -2009 -Journal of Ethics in Mental Health 3 (1):6.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  46
    Neuroteach: Brain Science and the Future of Education.Glenn Whitman &Ian Kelleher -2016 - Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. Edited by Ian Kelleher.
    Teachers are brain changers. Thus it would seem obvious that an understanding of the brain – the organ of learning – would be critical to a teacher’s readiness to work with students. Unfortunately, in traditional public, public-charter, private, parochial, and home schools across the country, most teachers lack an understanding of how the brain receives, filters, consolidates, and applies learning for both the short and long term. Neuroteach was therefore written to help solve the problem teachers and school leaders have (...) in knowing how to bring the growing body of educational neuroscience research into the design of their schools, classrooms, and work with each individual student. It is our hope, that Neuroteach will help ensure that one day, every student –regardless of zip code or school type—will learn and develop with the guidance of a teacher who knows the research behind how his or her brain works and learns. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  121
    Medical knowledge and the rise of technology.Ian R. McWhinney -1978 -Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 3 (4):293-304.
  42.  21
    Ethical and Legal Perspectives in Fetal Alcohol Spectrum Disorders : Foundational Issues.Ian Binnie,Sterling Clarren &Egon Jonsson (eds.) -2018 - Cham: Springer Verlag.
    This book discusses how to deal ethically with people with Fetal Alcohol Spectrum Disorder in the police, courts and correctional services. Ethical and legal issues associated with the deficits of individuals with a brain disorders such as FASD are surfacing more and more frequently in criminal proceedings. People with FASD often have not been diagnosed and rarely exhibit any visible evidence of the disorder. It has been argued that this invisible disability puts them in a disadvantaged position in the justice (...) system, since the awareness of this condition is limited. The need to identify and to address FASD more effectively and the many ethical issues this raises within the context of the law is increasingly acknowledged within judicial and legislative branches, as well as in government departments, agencies and community programs that provide services to those with FASD and their caretakers and families. This is the first book to give to elaborate on ethical and legal issues of FASD. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  33
    Baptists, Fifth Monarchists, and the Reign of King Jesus.Ian Birch -2018 -Perichoresis 16 (4):19-34.
    This article outlines the rise of the Fifth Monarchists, a religiously inspired and politically motivated movement which came to prominence in the 1650s and believed the execution of Charles I cleared the way for King Jesus to return and reign with the saints from the throne of England. The imminent establishment of the Kingdom of Christ on earth was of great interest to Baptists, some of whom were initially drawn to the Fifth Monarchy cause because Fifth Monarchy theology provided a (...) political route to a reformed society in England. While Baptists in the 1650s greatly desired to advance the cause of King Jesus the increasingly revolutionary methods employed by the Fifth Monarchists were at odds with their understanding of the spiritual nature of Christ’s kingdom, thus exposing differences in their respective eschatologies. Finally, observing the ambitious zeal of the Fifth Monarchist programme Baptists disavowed the anarchic revolutionary approach and distanced themselves from the movement. This breach, regarded as apostasy by the Fifth Monarchists, came at a fortunate time for the Baptist cause before the revolution was stamped out and the leaders arrested. The rise and fall of the Fifth Monarchists, however, helped Baptists to clarify the nature and methods of their approach to establishing the kingdom of Christ among the saints on earth, and is therefore worthy of consideration for those wishing to understand the beginning of the Baptists in England and the nature of apocalyptic during the interregnum. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  31
    Can a communist write a novel? The case of Jean kanapa.Ian Birchall -2003 -Sartre Studies International 9 (1):84-101.
  45.  20
    Camarades! La naissance du parti communiste en France, Romain Ducoulombier, Paris: Perrin, 2010.Ian Birchall -2013 -Historical Materialism 21 (3):178-188.
    Romain Ducoulombier, author ofCamarades!, a study of the origins of the French Communist Party, belongs to a different ideological context to earlier authors on the subject, such as Kriegel, Wohl or Robrieux. But though Ducoulombier claims originality for his work, there is little genuinely new here. He fails to grasp the impact of the Russian Revolution on the French working class and has little understanding of the dynamics of the Communist International. He stresses the ‘asceticism’ and ‘messianism’ of the early (...) Communist Party without giving a precise meaning to these terms. Worst of all, Ducoulombier concentrates on archival material while saying remarkably little about the French Communist Party’s actual activities, notably work in the trade unions, anti-militarism and anti-colonialism. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  37
    From Pacifism to Trotskyism.Ian Birchall -2018 -Historical Materialism 26 (4):180-193.
    The French journal Clarté had its origins in a movement launched just after the end of World War I by Henri Barbusse. It was soon taken over by a group of more radical intellectuals, who were close to the French Communist Party but not under its direct control. The journal combined politics and culture. It attempted to analyse the changing world-conjuncture, and in particular the significance of the defeated revolutions in Germany and China. But it also developed a theory of (...) culture under the influence of the Russian proletcult, Victor Serge, Georges Sorel and surrealism. In 1927, under the influence of Pierre Naville, Clarté broke with the Moscow-dominated Communist Party and became the organ of the French Left Opposition. Cuenot has given a well-researched and balanced account of its development. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  47
    Karl Radek by Jean-François Fayet.Ian Birchall -2006 -Historical Materialism 14 (3):259-274.
  48.  38
    On Alain Maillard's La Communauté des égaux; Philippe Riviale's L'impatience du bonheur: apologie de Gracchus Babeuf; and Jean Soublin's Je t'écris au sujet de Gracchus Babeuf.Ian Birchall -2003 -Historical Materialism 11 (1):223-241.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  55
    Paul Levi in Perspective.Ian Birchall -2015 -Historical Materialism 23 (3):143-170.
    Paul Levi was leader of the German Communist Party in the vital years 1919 and 1920; he was subsequently expelled for his opposition to the adventurist March Action in 1921. Three recent books cast new light on this complex figure: David Fernbach’s selection of his writings, Frédéric Cyr’s biography and Paul Frölich’s memoirs. Levi was a man of great talent and courage, but his leadership style was defective; he was neither Leninist nor Luxemburgist, and his greatest weakness was his inability (...) to relate to ultra-leftism. His limitations are revealed by a comparison with his comrade Clara Zetkin. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  60
    Sartre and terror.Ian Birchall -2005 -Sartre Studies International 11 (s 1-2):251-264.
    It is one of Sartre's greatest strengths that his declared aim was 'to write for his own time'. From the 1940s onward, he became ever less interested in 'timeless' questions, and ever more concerned to explore the concrete realities of his own age. This engagement with the contemporary makes it particularly tempting to consider what Sartre's responses to the events of our own age would be. Ever since his death in 1980, those of us who have drawn insight and inspiration (...) from Sartre's works have tended to ask how Sartre might have judged particular political developments. And because of the central place given to violence in his thought, as well as his detailed reflections on the Second World War and the wars in Algeria and Vietnam, it is only natural to ask how Sartre would have responded to the appalling events of 11 September 2001 and the subsequent 'war on terror'. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 940
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp