Contents just are in the head.AmirHorowitz -2001 -Erkenntnis 54 (3):321-344.detailsThe purpose of the paper is to show that semanticexternalism â the thesis that contents are notdetermined by ``individualistic'' features of mentalstates â is mistaken. Externalist thinking, it isargued, rests on two mistaken assumptions: theassumption that if there is an externalist wayof describing a situation the situation exemplifiesexternalism, and the assumption that cases in which adifference in the environment of an intentional stateentails a difference in the state's intentional objectare cases in which environmental factors determine thestate's content. Exposing these mistakes (...) leads to seethat the conditions that are required for thetruth of externalism are inconsistent. (shrink)
Computation, external factors, and cognitive explanations.AmirHorowitz -2007 -Philosophical Psychology 20 (1):65-80.detailsComputational properties, it is standardly assumed, are to be sharply distinguished from semantic properties. Specifically, while it is standardly assumed that the semantic properties of a cognitive system are externally or non-individualistically individuated, computational properties are supposed to be individualistic and internal. Yet some philosophers (e.g., Tyler Burge) argue that content impacts computation, and further, that environmental factors impact computation. Oron Shagrir has recently argued for these theses in a novel way, and gave them novel interpretations. In this paper I (...) present a conception of computation in cognitive science that takes Shagrir's conception as its starting point, but further develops it in various directions and strengthens it. I argue that the explanatory role of computational properties emerges from the idea that syntactical properties and the relevant external factors presented by cognitive systems compose wide computational properties. I also elaborate upon the notion of content that is in play, and argue that it is contents of the kind that are ascribed by transparent interpretations of content ascriptions that impact computation. This fact enables the thesis that external factors impact computation to rebuff the challenge which concerns the claim that psychology must be individualistic. (shrink)
Turning the zombie on its head.AmirHorowitz -2009 -Synthese 170 (1):191 - 210.detailsThis paper suggests a critique of the zombie argument that bypasses the need to decide on the truth of its main premises, and specifically, avoids the need to enter the battlefield of whether conceivability entails metaphysical possibility. It is argued that if we accept, as the zombie argument’s supporters would urge us, the assumption that an ideal reasoner can conceive of a complete physical description of the world without conceiving of qualia, the general principle that conceivability entails metaphysical possibility, and (...) the general principle that for any s and t the metaphysical possibility of s & − t entails that s does not necessitate t, we have to conclude not that materialism is false but rather that either materialism or the “mental paint” (or “phenomenist”) conception of phenomenality is false. And further, given the initial advantages of materialism, the fact that proponents of the zombie argument are not allowed to rely on arguments against materialism in confronting this dilemma, and difficulties with arguments in favor of phenomenism, we find ourselves pushed to reject the mental paint conception rather than materialism. Or at any rate, it is hard to see how the proponent of the zombie argument can carry the burden of proof that lies with her. Thus, whether or not those premises of the zombie argument are true, the argument fails to refute materialism. (shrink)
On the Very Idea of (Real) Content Derivation.AmirHorowitz -2020 -Philosophia 49 (1):271-287.detailsAccording to an idea which is widespread among philosophers, linguistic entities derive their intentionality from the intentionality of mental entities by virtue of some relation between them. Typically, it is some kind of intention on the speaker’s part – e.g., an intention to produce in the hearer a belief with a certain content – that is supposed to endow words with content. This paper argues that the concept of the derivation of content from one entity to another, if understood realistically, (...) is flawed: derived intentionality, I will argue, is merely ascribed intentionality, not a real property of its possessor. Irrealistic-ascriptivist senses are suggested for the ideas of content derivation, of original intentionality, and of the mind as the source of linguistic intentionality. Thus, endorsing the idea that mental intentionality is the source of non-mental intentionality need not tempt one to intentional realism. In an intentional irrealistic framework, what forms of intentionality are original and what are derived is a deeply contingent matter, determined by our practice of content ascription. But while intentional irrealism accommodates all those ideas, this paper defends “content-derivation irrealism” but not thoroughgoing intentional irrealism – the idea that there is real original intentionality is not ruled out. Still, assuming that some entities possess real intentionality, what can make them endow intentionality upon other entities is also our practice of content ascription. (shrink)
No categories
The knowledge argument and higher-order properties.AmirHorowitz &Hilla Jacobson-Horowitz -2005 -Ratio 18 (1):48-64.detailsThe paper argues that Jackson's knowledge argument fails to undermine physicalist ontology. First, it is argued that, as this argument stands, it begs the question. Second, it is suggested that by supplementing the argument , this flaw can be remedied insofar as the argument is taken to be an argument against type-physicalism; however, this flaw cannot be remedied insofar as the argument is taken to be an argument against token-physicalism. The argument cannot be supplemented so as to show that experiences (...) have properties which are illegitimate from a physicalist perspective. (shrink)
(Supervisor: Marcelo Dascal).AmirHorowitz -unknowndetailsThis work discusses a number of issues concerning mental contents. Its main purpose is to account for our thinking about extra-mental reality. I wish, in other words, to answer the question what makes it the case that mental states have the specific contents that they do. I try to present a theory that answers this question without using any semantic/intentional terms. Yet, the theory is neutral regarding the ontological status of the intentional and of the mental generally.
Putnam, Searle, and externalism.AmirHorowitz -1996 -Philosophical Studies 81 (1):27-69.detailsTo sum up, then, both kinds of Putnam's arguments established externalism, though they suffer from several defects. Yet, I think Searle's discussion of these arguments contributes to our understanding of what makes externalism true, and forces us to accept a moderate version of externalism. Searle's own account of the TE story shows us, within a solipsistic outline, how two identical mental states can be directed towards different objects, and further, that the content-determination of indexical thoughts does not necessarily involve external (...) factors. We are thus led to search elsewhere (i.e., not in the nature of indexical thoughts nor in the mere fact of there being identical thoughts with different intentionalities) for what makes the thoughts in question ‘external’. Searle formulates the thesis that intension determines extension as asserting that intension sets certain conditions that anything has to meet in order to fall under its extension. I showed that this is a trivial and implausible understanding of that thesis. Yet, it leads us to distinguish between an intension's setting conditions for falling under its extension and its fully determining such conditions, and thus to see in what sense externalism is true: in the sense that there are intensions that do not fully determine the conditions for falling under their extensions. Rather, they leave indeterminacies. This version of externalism is a moderate one, since though the intensions do not fully determine extensions, they, so to speak, determine their indeterminacies, by specifying the possible external facts that can complete the determination of extension. (The intensions, as I said, function like open sentences, and can be viewed as narrow contents.) So what's in the head plays a much more important role in determining content than Putnam takes it to play. Searle's pointing out that Hilary's concepts ‘elm’ and ‘beech’ are different also contributes to seeing this phenomenon: we realize that in that case the difference between the concepts is what is responsible for the fact that the completions of the extension-determinations are different. I think that this way of viewing the facts shows that ‘the externalist turn’ is not a great revolution, and that with the help of the concept of narrow content we can accept it without abandoning the traditional views about the mind as the source of content, and without being embarrassed by the very idea of (realistic) belief-desire psychology. (shrink)
Is there a problem in physicalist epiphenomenalism?AmirHorowitz -1999 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (2):421-34.detailsPhysicalist epiphenomenalism is the conjunction of the doctrine that tokens of mental events are tokens of physical events and the doctrine that mental events do not exert causal powers by virtue of falling under mental types. The purpose of the paper is to show that physicalist epiphenomenalism, contrary to what many have thought, is not subject to the objections that have been raised against classic epiphenomenalism. This is argued with respect to five such objections: that introspection shows that our mental (...) properties are causally efficacious; that concrete existents and their properties necessarily possess causal powers; that the explanatory and predictive success of psychology implies that psychological properties exist and are causally efficacious; that epiphenomenalism cannot deal with the other minds problem, and that it is unlikely that our mentality does not endow us with evolutionary advantages and therefore it is unlikely that mental properties are not causally efficacious. (shrink)
Externalism, the environment, and thought-tokens.AmirHorowitz -2005 -Erkenntnis 63 (1):133-138.detailsIn "Contents just are in the head" (Erkenntnis 54, pp. 321-4.) I have presented two arguments against the thesis of semantic externalism. In "Contents just aren't in the head" Anthony Brueckner has argued that my arguments are unsuccessful, since they rest upon some misconceptions regarding the nature of this thesis. (Erkenntnis 58, pp. 1-6.) In the present paper I will attempt to clarify and strengthen the case against semantic externalism, and show that Brueckner misses the point of my arguments.
Externalism and the Resolution of Self-knowledge.AmirHorowitz &Hilla Jacobson -2010 -Acta Philosophica 19 (2):339-348.detailsThis paper suggests a new way for defending semantic externalism from what we take to be the most serious attack against it in the context of the discussion of the a priori nature of self-knowledge. We shall argue that the resolution of our a priori knowledge of our beliefs on the assumption that their contents are externally determined is identical to the resolution that it makes sense to attribute to our knowledge of our beliefs independently of any assumption about content-determination. (...) We shall also suggest what might be the source of the conviction that supposedly externally-determined beliefs violate some general epistemological principle. (shrink)
Games, Rules, and Practices.Yuval Eylon &AmirHorowitz -2018 -Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 12 (3):241-254.detailsWe present and defend a view labeled “practiceism” which provides a solution to the incompatibility problems. The classic incompatibility problem is inconsistency of:1. Someone who intentionally violates the rules of a game is not playing the game.2. In many cases, players intentionally violate the rules as part of playing the game.The problem has a normative counterpart:1’. In normal cases, it is wrong for a player to intentionally violate the rules of the game.2’. In many normal cases, it is not wrong (...) for a player to intentionally violate the rules of the game.According to both formalism and informalism, the rules of the game include the formal rules of the game. Both traditional positions avoid the incompatibility problems by rejecting 1 and 1'. Practiceism rejects 2 and 2’: it maintains that the rules are the rules manifested in playing the game, not the formal rules.Practiceism presents two theses: (... (shrink)
Intentionality, Thought and Language: A Correspondence.Eddy M. Zemach &AmirHorowitz -2014 -Philosophia 42 (4):871-888.detailsIntroductionEddy M. Zemach was born in Jerusalem in 1935. His mother, Helena, was a dentist as well as a poet, and his father, Shimon, was a dentist as well as a political figure. Eddy completed B.A. and M.A. degrees in both Hebrew literature and philosophy at the Hebrew university of Jerusalem. He studied for a doctoral degree in philosophy at Yale University. In 1965 he completed his dissertation on the boundaries of the aesthetic, supervised by Paul Weiss. Another of his (...) teachers at Yale was Wilfrid Sellars, who influenced his philosophical views on mind and language. Aesthetics, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of language formed the center of his philosophical interest, though this interest was extended to other philosophical areas, such as metaphysics and epistemology.Eddy published extensively in both philosophy and Hebrew literature, and also wrote many short stories . He wrote some two hundred papers, and twelve scholarly books .. (shrink)
Nothing at Stake in Knowledge.David Rose,Edouard Machery,Stephen Stich,Mario Alai,Adriano Angelucci,Renatas Berniūnas,Emma E. Buchtel,Amita Chatterjee,Hyundeuk Cheon,In-Rae Cho,Daniel Cohnitz,Florian Cova,Vilius Dranseika,Ángeles Eraña Lagos,Laleh Ghadakpour,Maurice Grinberg,Ivar Hannikainen,Takaaki Hashimoto,AmirHorowitz,Evgeniya Hristova,Yasmina Jraissati,Veselina Kadreva,Kaori Karasawa,Hackjin Kim,Yeonjeong Kim,Minwoo Lee,Carlos Mauro,Masaharu Mizumoto,Sebastiano Moruzzi,Christopher Y. Olivola,Jorge Ornelas,Barbara Osimani,Carlos Romero,Alejandro Rosas Lopez,Massimo Sangoi,Andrea Sereni,Sarah Songhorian,Paulo Sousa,Noel Struchiner,Vera Tripodi,Naoki Usui,Alejandro Vázquez del Mercado,Giorgio Volpe,Hrag Abraham Vosgerichian,Xueyi Zhang &Jing Zhu -2019 -Noûs 53 (1):224-247.detailsIn the remainder of this article, we will disarm an important motivation for epistemic contextualism and interest-relative invariantism. We will accomplish this by presenting a stringent test of whether there is a stakes effect on ordinary knowledge ascription. Having shown that, even on a stringent way of testing, stakes fail to impact ordinary knowledge ascription, we will conclude that we should take another look at classical invariantism. Here is how we will proceed. Section 1 lays out some limitations of previous (...) research on stakes. Section 2 presents our study and concludes that there is little evidence for a substantial stakes effect. Section 3 responds to objections. The conclusion clears the way for classical invariantism. (shrink)
De Pulchritudine non est Disputandum? A cross‐cultural investigation of the alleged intersubjective validity of aesthetic judgment.Florian Cova,Christopher Y. Olivola,Edouard Machery,Stephen Stich,David Rose,Mario Alai,Adriano Angelucci,Renatas Berniūnas,Emma E. Buchtel,Amita Chatterjee,Hyundeuk Cheon,In-Rae Cho,Daniel Cohnitz,Vilius Dranseika,Ángeles E. Lagos,Laleh Ghadakpour,Maurice Grinberg,Ivar Hannikainen,Takaaki Hashimoto,AmirHorowitz,Evgeniya Hristova,Yasmina Jraissati,Veselina Kadreva,Kaori Karasawa,Hackjin Kim,Yeonjeong Kim,Minwoo Lee,Carlos Mauro,Masaharu Mizumoto,Sebastiano Moruzzi,Jorge Ornelas,Barbara Osimani,Carlos Romero,Alejandro Rosas,Massimo Sangoi,Andrea Sereni,Sarah Songhorian,Paulo Sousa,Noel Struchiner,Vera Tripodi,Naoki Usui,Alejandro V. del Mercado,Giorgio Volpe,Hrag A. Vosgerichian,Xueyi Zhang &Jing Zhu -2019 -Mind and Language 34 (3):317-338.detailsSince at least Hume and Kant, philosophers working on the nature of aesthetic judgment have generally agreed that common sense does not treat aesthetic judgments in the same way as typical expressions of subjective preferences—rather, it endows them with intersubjective validity, the property of being right or wrong regardless of disagreement. Moreover, this apparent intersubjective validity has been taken to constitute one of the main explananda for philosophical accounts of aesthetic judgment. But is it really the case that most people (...) spontaneously treat aesthetic judgments as having intersubjective validity? In this paper, we report the results of a cross‐cultural study with over 2,000 respondents spanning 19 countries. Despite significant geographical variations, these results suggest that most people do not treat their own aesthetic judgments as having intersubjective validity. We conclude by discussing the implications of our findings for theories of aesthetic judgment and the purpose of aesthetics in general. (shrink)
For Whom Does Determinism Undermine Moral Responsibility? Surveying the Conditions for Free Will Across Cultures.Ivar R. Hannikainen,Edouard Machery,David Rose,Stephen Stich,Christopher Y. Olivola,Paulo Sousa,Florian Cova,Emma E. Buchtel,Mario Alai,Adriano Angelucci,Renatas Berniûnas,Amita Chatterjee,Hyundeuk Cheon,In-Rae Cho,Daniel Cohnitz,Vilius Dranseika,Ángeles Eraña Lagos,Laleh Ghadakpour,Maurice Grinberg,Takaaki Hashimoto,AmirHorowitz,Evgeniya Hristova,Yasmina Jraissati,Veselina Kadreva,Kaori Karasawa,Hackjin Kim,Yeonjeong Kim,Minwoo Lee,Carlos Mauro,Masaharu Mizumoto,Sebastiano Moruzzi,Jorge Ornelas,Barbara Osimani,Carlos Romero,Alejandro Rosas López,Massimo Sangoi,Andrea Sereni,Sarah Songhorian,Noel Struchiner,Vera Tripodi,Naoki Usui,Alejandro Vázquez del Mercado,Hrag A. Vosgerichian,Xueyi Zhang &Jing Zhu -2019 -Frontiers in Psychology 10.detailsPhilosophers have long debated whether, if determinism is true, we should hold people morally responsible for their actions since in a deterministic universe, people are arguably not the ultimate source of their actions nor could they have done otherwise if initial conditions and the laws of nature are held fixed. To reveal how non-philosophers ordinarily reason about the conditions for free will, we conducted a cross-cultural and cross-linguistic survey (N = 5,268) spanning twenty countries and sixteen languages. Overall, participants tended (...) to ascribe moral responsibility whether the perpetrator lacked sourcehood or alternate possibilities. However, for American, European, and Middle Eastern participants, being the ultimate source of one’s actions promoted perceptions of free will and control as well as ascriptions of blame and punishment. By contrast, being the source of one’s actions was not particularly salient to Asian participants. Finally, across cultures, participants exhibiting greater cognitive reflection were more likely to view free will as incompatible with causal determinism. We discuss these findings in light of documented cultural differences in the tendency toward dispositional versus situational attributions. (shrink)
The Ship of Theseus Puzzle.David Rose,Edouard Machery,Stephen Stich,Mario Alai,Adriano Angelucci,Renatas Berniūnas,Emma E. Buchtel,Amita Chatterjee,Hyundeuk Cheon,In-Rae Cho,Daniel Cohnitz,Florian Cova,Vilius Dranseika,Angeles Eraña Lagos,Laleh Ghadakpour,Maurice Grinberg,Ivar Hannikainen,Takaaki Hashimoto,AmirHorowitz,Evgeniya Hristova,Yasmina Jraissati,Veselina Kadreva,Kaori Karasawa,Hackjin Kim,Yeonjeong Kim,Min-Woo Lee,Carlos Mauro,Masaharu Mizumoto,Sebastiano Moruzzi,Christopher Y. Olivola,Jorge Ornelas,Barbara Osimani,Alejandro Rosas,Carlos Romero,Massimo Sangoi,Andrea Sereni,Sarah Songhorian,Paulo Sousa,Noel Struchiner,Vera Tripodi,Naoki Usui,Alejandro Vázquez Del Vázquez Del Mercado,Giorgio Volpe,Hrag A. Vosgerichian,Xueyi Zhang &Jing Zhu -2014 - In Tania Lombrozo, Joshua Knobe & Shaun Nichols,Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy, Volume 1. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK. pp. 158-174.detailsDoes the Ship of Theseus present a genuine puzzle about persistence due to conflicting intuitions based on “continuity of form” and “continuity of matter” pulling in opposite directions? Philosophers are divided. Some claim that it presents a genuine puzzle but disagree over whether there is a solution. Others claim that there is no puzzle at all since the case has an obvious solution. To assess these proposals, we conducted a cross-cultural study involving nearly 3,000 people across twenty-two countries, speaking eighteen (...) different languages. Our results speak against the proposal that there is no puzzle at all and against the proposal that there is a puzzle but one that has no solution. Our results suggest that there are two criteria—“continuity of form” and “continuity of matter”— that constitute our concept of persistence and these two criteria receive different weightings in settling matters concerning persistence. (shrink)
The Gettier Intuition from South America to Asia.Edouard Machery,Stephen Stich,David Rose,Mario Alai,Adriano Angelucci,Renatas Berniūnas,Emma E. Buchtel,Amita Chatterjee,Hyundeuk Cheon,In-Rae Cho,Daniel Cohnitz,Florian Cova,Vilius Dranseika,Ángeles Eraña Lagos,Laleh Ghadakpour,Maurice Grinberg,Ivar Hannikainen,Takaaki Hashimoto,AmirHorowitz,Evgeniya Hristova,Yasmina Jraissati,Veselina Kadreva,Kaori Karasawa,Hackjin Kim,Yeonjeong Kim,Minwoo Lee,Carlos Mauro,Masaharu Mizumoto,Sebastiano Moruzzi,Christopher Y. Olivola,Jorge Ornelas,Barbara Osimani,Carlos Romero,Alejandro Rosas Lopez,Massimo Sangoi,Andrea Sereni,Sarah Songhorian,Paulo Sousa,Noel Struchiner,Vera Tripodi,Naoki Usui,Alejandro Vázquez del Mercado,Giorgio Volpe,Hrag Abraham Vosgerichian,Xueyi Zhang &Jing Zhu -2017 -Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research 34 (3):517-541.detailsThis article examines whether people share the Gettier intuition (viz. that someone who has a true justified belief that p may nonetheless fail to know that p) in 24 sites, located in 23 countries (counting Hong Kong as a distinct country) and across 17 languages. We also consider the possible influence of gender and personality on this intuition with a very large sample size. Finally, we examine whether the Gettier intuition varies across people as a function of their disposition to (...) engage in “reflective” thinking. (shrink)
A psycho-philosophical analysis of fouls and intentions in contact sports.Michael Bar-Eli,Yuval Eylon &AmirHorowitz -2015 -Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 9 (4):375-388.detailsThis paper examines the notion of fouls in sports. In the first part of the paper, we examine some actual distinctions and classifications between different kinds of fouls. In the second part we examine the significance, validity, and justification of these classifications from a normative perspective.The term ‘foul’ evokes negative connotation; some would say—negative normative connotations. Conventional wisdom suggests that typically to commit fouls is, by definition, to go against the rules or principles of the contest. Since sport contests are (...) constitutive activities—this means that to foul is to go against the essence of the contest. In other words, to commit fouls seems not to play the game; it seems unsporting. Consider the following typical example: in a premiership match in 2014 Hull’s forward Nikica Jelavic spun around Company and had a clear path to the goal. Manchester City’s defender Vincent Kompany then held him back. Although immediately ejected from the game, it is noteworthy that Kompany... (shrink)
Behavioral Circumscription and the Folk Psychology of Belief: A Study in Ethno-Mentalizing.Rose David,Machery Edouard,Stich Stephen,Alai Mario,Angelucci Adriano,Berniūnas Renatas,E. Buchtel Emma,Chatterjee Amita,Cheon Hyundeuk,Cho In‐Rae,Cohnitz Daniel,Cova Florian,Dranseika Vilius,Lagos Ángeles Eraña,Ghadakpour Laleh,Grinberg Maurice,Hannikainen Ivar,Hashimoto Takaaki,HorowitzAmir,Hristova Evgeniya,Jraissati Yasmina,Kadreva Veselina,Karasawa Kaori,Kim Hackjin,Kim Yeonjeong,Lee Minwoo,Mauro Carlos,Mizumoto Masaharu,Moruzzi Sebastiano,Y. Olivola Christopher,Ornelas Jorge,Osimani Barbara,Romero Carlos,Rosas Alejandro,Sangoi Massimo,Sereni Andrea,Songhorian Sarah,Sousa Paulo,Struchiner Noel,Tripodi Vera,Usui Naoki,del Mercado Alejandro Vázquez,Volpe Giorgio,A. Vosgerichian Hrag,Zhang Xueyi &Zhu Jing -2017 -Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 6 (3):193-203.detailsIs behavioral integration a necessary feature of belief in folk psychology? Our data from over 5,000 people across 26 samples, spanning 22 countries suggests that it is not. Given the surprising cross-cultural robustness of our findings, we argue that the types of evidence for the ascription of a belief are, at least in some circumstances, lexicographically ordered: assertions are first taken into account, and when an agent sincerely asserts that p, nonlinguistic behavioral evidence is disregarded. In light of this, we (...) take ourselves to have discovered a universal principle governing the ascription of beliefs in folk psychology. (shrink)
No categories
Intentionality and Action.Jesús Padilla Gálvez &Margit Gaffal (eds.) -2017 - Berlin: De Gruyter.detailsThe book links the concept of intention to human action. It provides answers to questions like: Why do we act intentionally? Which impact do reasons and motives have on our decisions? Certain events are identified as intentional actions when they are considered as being rationalized by reasons. The linguistic description of such events enables us to reveal the structure of intention. The mental and the linguistic constitute irreducible ways of understanding events. Among the topics discussed are intentionality, actions, the linguistic (...) form to talk about intentionality and actions, Brentano’s view of intentionality, the phenomenological approach to intention and Wittgenstein's proposals. The contributions by Wolfgang Künne, Peter Simons, Christian Bermes, Kevin Mulligan, Severin Schroeder, António Marques, Margit Gaffal, Michel Le Du, Jesús Padilla Gálvez, Bernhard Obsieger andAmirHorowitz show that actions and decisions are guided by intentional considerations. (shrink)
Are You Now or Have You Ever Been an Impermissivist? --- A conversation among friends and enemies of epistemic freedom.SophieHorowitz,Sinan Dogramaci &Miriam Schoenfield -2024 - In Blake Roeber, Matthias Steup, Ernest Sosa & John Turri,Contemporary Debates in Epistemology. Wiley-Blackwell.detailsWe debate whether permissivism is true. We start off by assuming an accuracy-oriented framework, and then discuss metaepistemological questions about how our epistemic evaluations promote accuracy.
Do credences model guesses?SophieHorowitz -forthcoming -Noûs.detailsWhat are credences? Where do the numbers come from? Some have argued that they are brute and primitive; others, that they model our dispositions to bet, our comparative confidence judgments, or our all‐out beliefs. This paper explores a new answer to this question: credences model our dispositions to guess. I argue that we can think of credences this way, and then consider: should we?
No categories
Epistemic Akrasia.SophieHorowitz -2013 -Noûs 48 (4):718-744.detailsMany views rely on the idea that it can never be rational to have high confidence in something like, “P, but my evidence doesn’t support P.” Call this idea the “Non-Akrasia Constraint”. Just as an akratic agent acts in a way she believes she ought not act, an epistemically akratic agent believes something that she believes is unsupported by her evidence. The Non-Akrasia Constraint says that ideally rational agents will never be epistemically akratic. In a number of recent papers, the (...) Non-Akrasia Constraint has been called into question. The goal of this paper is to defend it... for the most part. (shrink)
Adopting AI: how familiarity breeds both trust and contempt.Michael C.Horowitz,Lauren Kahn,Julia Macdonald &Jacquelyn Schneider -forthcoming -AI and Society:1-15.detailsDespite pronouncements about the inevitable diffusion of artificial intelligence and autonomous technologies, in practice, it is human behavior, not technology in a vacuum, that dictates how technology seeps into—and changes—societies. To better understand how human preferences shape technological adoption and the spread of AI-enabled autonomous technologies, we look at representative adult samples of US public opinion in 2018 and 2020 on the use of four types of autonomous technologies: vehicles, surgery, weapons, and cyber defense. By focusing on these four diverse (...) uses of AI-enabled autonomy that span transportation, medicine, and national security, we exploit the inherent variation between these AI-enabled autonomous use cases. We find that those with familiarity and expertise with AI and similar technologies were more likely to support all of the autonomous applications we tested (except weapons) than those with a limited understanding of the technology. Individuals that had already delegated the act of driving using ride-share apps were also more positive about autonomous vehicles. However, familiarity cut both ways; individuals are also less likely to support AI-enabled technologies when applied directly to their life, especially if technology automates tasks they are already familiar with operating. Finally, we find that familiarity plays little role in support for AI-enabled military applications, for which opposition has slightly increased over time. (shrink)
Accuracy and Educated Guesses.SophieHorowitz -2019 -Oxford Studies in Epistemology 6.detailsCredences, unlike full beliefs, can’t be true or false. So what makes credences more or less accurate? This chapter offers a new answer to this question: credences are accurate insofar as they license true educated guesses, and less accurate insofar as they license false educated guesses. This account is compatible with immodesty; : a rational agent will regard her own credences to be best for the purposes of making true educated guesses. The guessing account can also be used to justify (...) certain coherence constraints on rational credence, such as probabilism. The chapter concludes by discussing some advantages of the guessing account over rival accounts of accuracy. (shrink)