Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'Hahn Carnap'

939 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  14
    Wiener Kreis: Texte zur wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung von RudolfCarnap, Otto Neurath, Moritz Schlick, Philipp Frank, HansHahn, Karl Menger, Edgar Zilsel und Gustav Bergmann.RudolfCarnap,Otto Neurath,Moritz Schlick,Philipp Frank,HansHahn &Karl Menger -2009 - Meiner, F.
    Am Wiener Kreis scheiden sich die Geister, trat er doch mit dem dezidierten Anspruch auf, mit den Mitteln der modernen Logik den metaphysischen Schutt von Jahrtausenden aus dem Weg zu räumen. Statt einer homogenen Bewegung, die sich empiristischen Dogmen verschrieb, erscheint der Wiener Kreis in der philosophischen Forschung jedoch heute als eine heterogene Gruppe von eigenständigen Denkern, die gemeinsam die Grundlagen der modernen Wissenschaftstheorie legten. In jeweils spezifischer Weise setzten sie sich von der philosophischen Tradition ab oder versuchten, einzelne Teile (...) davon in die wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung zu integrieren. Der Band enthält eine repräsentative Auswahl von Aufsätzen der Mitglieder des Wiener Kreises. Sie beschränkt sich mit Ausnahme dreier Frühschriften der Gründer bewußt auf die Jahre des historischen Kreises vom Beginn der Treffen 1924 bis zur Ermordung Schlicks 1936, obwohl einige der Hauptideen erst in den USA ihre volle Wirkung entfalteten und von dort Ende der sechziger Jahre wieder in die deutschsprachige Philosophie zurückwirkten. In ihrer Einleitung skizzieren die Herausgeber die historische Entwicklung des Kreises und erläutern die zentralen thematischen Fragestellungen. Die Anmerkungen identifizieren die internen wie externen Opponenten und erklären den Kontext der zeitgenössischen Wissenschaft. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  16
    RudolfCarnap, HansHahn, Otto Neurath, Moritz Schlick, Friedrich Waissman: Manifeste du Cercle de Vienne et Autres Ecrits.RudolfCarnap,HansHahn,Otto Neurath,Moritz Schlick &Friedrich Waissman -2010 - Librarie Philosophique J. Vrin.
    Autour du Manifeste de Vienne se trouvent reunis des textes fondateurs ecrits autour de 1929. Leurs auteurs:Carnap,Hahn, Neurath, Schlick l'ame du Cercle de Vienne, et Waismann plus proche de Wittgenstein, temoignent d'un courant philosophique constituant aujourd'hui la tradition analytique de source continentale a la fois empiriste et logique. Forme de maniere informelle a Vienne, au coeur de l'Europe, le Cercle reunissait des savants de differentes branches qui voulaient se donner une philosophie susceptible d' unifier leurs vues. (...) Echo aux reves d'unite de la science, cette philosophie en exprime aussi le renversement complet. Veritable Discours de la methode, mais d'esprit anti-cartesien, elle entend reconstruire la science de maniere a evincer la speculation metaphysique, le but etant qu'aucun enonce ne soit laisse a l'exterieur de cette grande architecture de symboles s'il etait pourvu de sens. La declaration de guerre contre la metaphysique est un geste de militance a une epoque riche en differents manifestes. Incomprehensible en dehors du contexte socio-politique viennois de ces annees, elle porte aussi un programme de reconstruction rationnelle qui, au dela du langage de la science, devait toucher tous les secteurs de la vie. Plus complexe qu'il n'y parait, ce programme contient, en reference a Wittgenstein, son prestigieux representant a cote d'Einstein et Russell, une mise en garde contre differentes formes d'irrationalismes, qui est d'actualite. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  58
    Tagung für Erkenntnislehre der exakten Wissenschaften.Carnap Rudolf,Hahn Hans,Frank Philipp &Reichenbach Hans -1929 -Annalen der Philosophie Und Philosophischen Kritik 8 (1):113-114.
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  58
    Einheitswissenschaft. Schriften herausgegeben von Otto Neurath in Verbindung mit RudolfCarnap, Philipp Frank, HansHahn.Otto Neurath,RudolfCarnap,Philipp Frank &HansHahn -1935 -Erkenntnis 5 (1):371-374.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5. The Scientific Conception of the World: The Vienna Circle.HansHahn,Otto Neurath &RudolfCarnap -1929
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  6.  16
    Prikazi knjiga/Book Reviews.HansHahn,Otto Neurath &RudolfCarnap -2006 -Prolegomena 5:1.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  25
    HansHahn, Otto Neurath, RudolfCarnap, Znanstveno shvaćanje svijeta – Bečki krug.Tihomir Vukelja -2006 -Prolegomena 5 (1):111-113.
  8.  95
    Learning Logical Tolerance: HansHahn on the Foundations of Mathematics.Thomas E. Uebel -2005 -History and Philosophy of Logic 26 (3):175-209.
    HansHahn's long-neglected philosophy of mathematics is reconstructed here with an eye to his anticipation of the doctrine of logical pluralism. After establishing thatHahn pioneered a post-Tractarian conception of tautologies and attempted to overcome the traditional foundational dispute in mathematics,Hahn's andCarnap's work is briefly compared with Karl Menger's, and several significant agreements or differences betweenHahn's andCarnap's work are specified and discussed.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  9.  36
    Anne siegetsleitner (ed.), Logischer empirismus, werte und moral, wien–new York: Springer, 2010. As the programmatic declarations of the “scientific worldview” show, not all the members of the circle of vienna devoted themselves to pure epistemological inquiry on the “icy slopes of logic”. Otto Neurath, RudolfCarnap, HansHahn and others. [REVIEW]R. Creath -2012 - In Richard Creath,Rudolf Carnap and the Legacy of Logical Empiricism. Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag. pp. 181.
  10.  30
    Menger Karl. Sin ronrigaku. Japanese translation of 3706 by Tomoharu Hirano. Kagaku ronrigaku, Nissin-Syoin, Tokyo 1944, pp. 29–73.Dubislav Walter. Kigô ronrigaku zyosetu . Japanese translation of Chapters 2 and 3 of 32814 and Der metamathematische Problemkreis from 32812, by Syûitirô Yosioka. Kagaku ronrigaku, Nissin-Syoin, Tokyo 1944, pp. 75–142.Carnap Rudolf. Kigô ronrigaku no taikei. Japanese translation of System der Logistik by Tomoharu Hirano. Kagaku ronrigaku, Nissin-Syoin, Tokyo 1944, pp. 143–248.Łukasiewicz Jan. Tati ronrigaku no tetugakuteki kôsatu. Japanese translation of 1868 by Makoto ltô. Kagaku ronrigaku, Nissin-Syoin, Tokyo 1944, pp. 249–282.Łukasiewicz Jan. Ronrigaku to sono kisoteki mondai. Japanese translation of VII 35 by Makoto Itô. Kagaku ronrigaku, Nissin-Syoin, Tokyo 1944, pp. 283–309.Popper Karl. Tankyû ronrigaku zyosetu. Japanese translation of the Einführung of 537½1 by Syûitirô Yosioka. Kagaku ronrigaku, Nissin-Syoin, Tokyo 1944, pp. 311–349.Hahn Hans. Ronr. [REVIEW]H. Hiż -1954 -Journal of Symbolic Logic 19 (3):236-236.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  48
    Schriften herausgegeben von Otto Neurath in Verbindung mit Rudolf Camap, Philipp Frank, HansHahn. Heft 1: Neurath, O.: Einheitswissenschaft und Psychologie. Heft 2:Hahn, H.: Logik, Mathematik und Naturerkennen. Heft 3:Carnap, R.: Die Aufgabe der Wissenschaftslogik. [REVIEW]Kurt Grelling -1935 -Erkenntnis 5 (1):371-374.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  107
    A. J. Ayer. Editor's introduction. Logical positivism, edited by A. J. Ayer, The Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois, 1959, pp. 3–28; also first paperback edition, The Free Press, New York 1966, pp. 3–28. - Bertrand Russell. Logical atomism. A reprint of XXV 333. Logical positivism, edited by A. J. Ayer, The Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois, 1959, pp. 31–50; also ibid., pp. 31–50. - Moritz Schlick. Positivism and realism. A reprint of XVI 67. Logical positivism, edited by A. J. Ayer, The Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois, 1959, pp. 82–107; also ibid., pp. 82–107. - Carl G. Hempel. The empiricist criterion of meaning. A reprint of XVI 293. Logical positivism, edited by A. J. Ayer, The Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois, 1959, pp. 108–129; also ibid., pp. 108–129. - RudolfCarnap. The old and the new logic. English translation of 3525 by Isaac Levi. Logical positivism, edited by A. J. Ayer, The Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois, 1959, pp. 133–146; also ibid., pp. 133–146. - HansHahn. Logic, mathematics and k. [REVIEW]Alonzo Church -1970 -Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (2):312-312.
  13. Was man aus Einflüssen machen kann - Hans Hahns Adaptierung von Russells Logizimus und Wittgensteins Nominalismus.Alexander Linsbichler -2018 -Contributions of the Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society 26:138-140.
    Im Rahmen dieses Beitrags beleuchten wir, wie HansHahn die Einflüsse Russells und Wittgensteins adaptiert, um seine individuelle Variante von Logizismus zu entwickeln. Von Bedeutung ist in diesem Zusammenhang Hahns unterschätzte Vorreiterrolle in der Entwicklung des logischen Toleranzprinzips und des logischen Pluralismus, also der Loslösung von der Vorstellung einer einzigen „korrekten“ Logik. Die detaillierten Arbeiten Uebels (2007, 2009) zur Entwicklung des logischen Pluralismus im Wiener Kreis verdienen zumindest zwei punktuelle Ergänzungen: Erstens untermauern die in diesem Kontext bisher unberücksichtigten Protokolle (...) des Wiener Kreises sowie Vorlesungsmitschriften Hermann Brochs die von Uebel im Gegensatz zu Goldfarb (1996) beschriebene Distanzierung Hahns von Wittgenstein. Zweitens relativieren Hahns und Mengers Arbeiten zu Occams Rasiermesser Uebels Einschätzung, Mengers Beitrag zum Toleranzprinzip sei „wenig philosophisch“. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  327
    (1 other version)On gödel's way in: The influence of RudolfCarnap.Warren Goldfarb -2005 -Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (2):185-193.
    The philosopher RudolfCarnap, although not himself an originator of mathematical advances in logic, was much involved in the development of the subject. He was the most important and deepest philosopher of the Vienna Circle of logical positivists, or, to use the labelCarnap later preferred, logical empiricists. It wasCarnap who gave the most fully developed and sophisticated form to the linguistic doctrine of logical and mathematical truth: the view that the truths of mathematics and logic (...) do not describe some Platonistic realm, but rather are artifacts of the way we establish a language in which to speak of the factual, empirical world, fallouts of the representational capacity of language.Carnap was also the thinker who, after Russell, most emphasized the importance of modern logic, and the distinctive advances it enables in the foundations of mathematics, to contemporary philosophy. It was throughCarnap's urgings, abetted by HansHahn, onceCarnap arrived in Vienna as Privatdozent in philosophy in 1926, that the Vienna Circle began to take logic seriously and that positivist philosophy began to grapple with the question of how an account of mathematics compatible with empiricism can be given.A particular facet ofCarnap's influence is not widely appreciated: it wasCarnap who introduced Kurt Gödel to logic, in the serious sense. Although Gödel seems to have attended a course of Schlick's on philosophy of mathematics in 1925–26, his second year at the University, he did not at that time pursue logic further, nor did the seminar leave much of a trace on him. In the early summer of 1928, however,Carnap gave two lectures to the Circle which Gödel attended, or so I surmise. At these occasions,Carnap presented material from his manuscript treatise, Untersuchungen zur allgemeinen Axiomatik, that is, “Investigations into general axiomatics”, which dealt with questions of consistency, completeness and categoricity.Carnap later circulated this material to various people including Gödel. (shrink)
    Direct download(10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  15. (1 other version)The Place of Quine in Analytic Philosophy.Scott Soames -2013 - In Gilbert Harman & Ernest LePore,A Companion to W. V. O. Quine. Hoboken, New Jersey: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Quine was born on June 25, 1908 in Akron Ohio. From 1926 to 1930 he attended Oberlin College, from which he graduated with a B.A. in mathematics that included reading in mathematical philosophy. He received his PhD from Harvard in 1932 with a dissertation on Principia Mathematica advised by Whitehead. The next year traveling on fellowship in Europe, where he interacted withCarnap, Tarski, Lesniewski, Lukasiewicz, Schlick,Hahn, Reichenbach, Gödel, and Ayer. He was back in Cambridge between 1933 (...) and 1936 as a Junior Fellow at the Harvard Society. In 1936, he joined the Harvard faculty, where he remained for 42 years, except for 3 years in the Navy in World War II. Returning after the war, he was promoted to Professor in 1948. Although he retired in 1978, he retained his office and remained active through much of the 1990s. Quine died on Christmas Day 2000. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  46
    The Vienna Circle: Studies in the Origins, Development, and Influence of Logical Empiricism.Friedrich Stadler -2015 - Cham: Springer.
    This abridged and revised edition of the original book (Springer-Wien-New York: 2001) offers the only comprehensive history and documentation of the Vienna Circle based on new sources with an innovative historiographical approach to the study of science. With reference to previously unpublished archival material and more recent literature, it refutes a number of widespread clichés about "neo-positivism" or "logical positivism". Following some insights on the relation between the history of science and the philosophy of science, the book offers an accessible (...) introduction to the complex subject of "the rise of scientific philosophy” in its socio-cultural background and European philosophical networks till the forced migration in the Anglo-Saxon world. The first part of the book focuses on the origins of Logical Empiricism before World War I and the development of the Vienna Circle in "Red Vienna" (with the "Verein Ernst Mach"), its fate during Austro-Fascism (Schlick's murder 1936) and its final expulsion by National-Socialism beginning with the "Anschluß" in 1938. It analyses the dynamics of the Schlick-Circle in the intellectual context of "late enlightenment" including the minutes of the meetings from 1930 on for the first time published and presents an extensive description of the meetings and international Unity of Science conferences between 1929 and 1941. The chapters introduce the leading philosophers of the Schlick Circle (e.g., HansHahn, Otto Neurath, RudolfCarnap, Philipp Frank, Felix Kaufmann, Edgar Zilsel) and describe the conflicting interaction between Moritz Schlick and Otto Neurath, the long term communication between Moritz Schlick, Friedrich Waismann and Ludwig Wittgenstein, as well as between the Vienna Circle with Heinrich Gomperz and Karl Popper. In addition, Karl Menger's "Mathematical Colloquium" with Kurt Gödel is presented as a parallel movement. The final chapter of this section describes the demise of the Vienna Circle and the forced exodus of scientists and intellectuals from Austria. The second part of the book includes a bio-bibliographical documentation of the Vienna Circle members and for the first time of the assassination of Moritz Schlick in 1936, followed by an appendix comprising an extensive list of sources and literature. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  17.  23
    Logical Positivism.Christopher Ray -2000 - In W. Newton-Smith,A companion to the philosophy of science. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell. pp. 243–251.
    Logical positivism and the Vienna Circle are almost synonymous. The Vienna Circle grew in strength throughout the 1920s, attracting philosophers such as RudolfCarnap, Friedrich Waismann, and Otto Neurath and mathematicians and scientists such as Kurt Gödel and HansHahn. It started as an intellectual club (initially known as the Ernst Mach Society), with Moritz Schlick, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Vienna, as its leading light. As the club debated and discussed problems in science, logic, and (...) philosophy, a definite consensus emerged. The members of the Vienna Circle were bound, initially at least, by commitments, to. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  275
    “Logical Positivism”—“Logical Empiricism”: What's in a Name?Thomas Uebel -2013 -Perspectives on Science 21 (1):58-99.
    Do the terms “logical positivism” and “logical empiricism” mark a philosophically real and significant distinction? There is, of course, no doubt that the first term designates the group of philosophers known as the Vienna Circle, headed by Moritz Schlick and including RudolfCarnap, Herbert Feigl, Philipp Frank, HansHahn, Otto Neurath, Friedrich Waismann and others. What is debatable, however, is whether the name “logical positivism” correctly distinguishes their doctrines from related ones called “logical empiricism” that emerged from the (...) Berlin Society for Scientific Philosophy around Hans Reichenbach which included Walter Dubislav, Kurt Grelling, Kurt Lewin and a young Carl Gustav Hempel.1 The .. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  19.  31
    Logischer Positivismus und radikale Gesellschaftsreform.Ansgar Beckermann -1979 -Analyse & Kritik 1 (1):30-46.
    For many years some critically engaged German sociologists have challenged Logical Positivism with the criticism that Positivism’s allegedly neutral conception of science in fact supports conservative or even reactionary political movements. This line of criticism is due, at last in part, to the fact that German scientists became acquainted with the positivistic branch of analytical philosophy after World War II almost exclusively through the works of the liberal-conservative K. R. Popper. Popper, however, is by no means representative of all Positivists. (...) There were influential members of the Vienna Circle who saw a direct connection between the aims of the „scientific world view“ and the endeavour to renew the society on the basis of rational, i.e. socialistic, principles. This connection becomes especially clear in the manifesto Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung − Der Wiener Kreis which was published in 1929 byCarnap,Hahn and Neurath. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20.  17
    Redefining the Status of Philosophical Statements.Dewi Trebaul -2024 -Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 61 (1):94-105.
    In his foreword to the Philosophical papers by HansHahn, Karl Menger mentions a controversy about the possibility or impossibility to speak about language within the Vienna Circle in the early 1930’s. He then adds: “Waismann proclaimed that one could not speak about language.Hahn took strong exception to this view. Why should one not – if perhaps in a higher-level language – speak about language? To which Waismann replied essentially that this would not fit into the texture (...) of Wittgenstein’s latest ideas.”1 Thanks to the publication of the protocols of the Vienna Circle by Friedrich Stadler in his book The Vienna Circle – Studies in the origins, development and influence of logical empiricism, we have access to some discussions within the circle in the years 1930 and 1931, that allow us a partial reconstruction of the controversy. In these minutes we attend a very lively discussion on the topic of ‘talking about language’. We would like to make more explicit the tenets of this controversy, starting from the discussions within the circle. We will then focus on the evolution of the positions of different members of the Circle, that reflect different attitudes towards this problem, that are expounded in articles published until 1936. Although its members strived to stay the closest, they could to the landmarks laid down by the Tractatus logico-philosophicus, some of its members broke with them in many respects. The need to admit the possibility of talking theoretically about language became more pressing as the works of Tarski and Godel began to exert an influence on the researches of its members. Two options emerged: talking about a language in another language (Hahn) or in the same language (Carnap).Hahn’s positions, despite their originality, stand close to those ofCarnap, who presents in 1931 his meta-logical project. Disagreements with Waismann occured frequently. Neurath remained skeptical about such a development that could, according to him, lead back to metaphysical considerations. The protocols by Rosa Rand give us precious insights on the premises of this debate, symptomatic of the diversity of the positions and of the fruitfulness of the exchanges within the Vienna Circle at that time. However, this debate takes place in a broader setting, namely the discussion of the status of philosophical statements once the rejection of metaphysics is accomplished. The answers provided reflect strong dissenting currents within the circle. For Neurath, to conceive of philosophy as providing elucidations is mistaken. Science shall take the form of an encyclopedia, that contains heterogeneous discourses – exact formulated sentences, as well as piece of ordinary language – and is taken in a dynamic process. No discourse outside science can be accepted. For Schlick and Waismann, there is still room for philosophy as providing elucidations about language. ForCarnap, the aim is to attain a logically suitable language for science; discussions in a natural language have only a provisional role, in order to attain an adequate language, in which the logic of science can be formulated. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  18
    Wittgenstein and the Variety of Vienna Circles.Thomas Uebel -2023 - In Friedrich Stadler,Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle: 100 Years After the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Springer Verlag. pp. 109-126.
    The Vienna Circle was, as the research of recent decades made abundantly clear, far from a homogeneous group of philosophers (nor an always harmonious one). This can be shown with regard to the way different general philosophical and cultural influences affected the views of different members, but also with regard to the way in which the doctrines of specific philosophers closely associated with the origin of logical empiricism were received. Wittgenstein is a case in point. This paper sets out, with (...) the help of a few indicative examples, how the critical reception of the Tractatus by HansHahn, Philipp Frank and Otto Neurath—former members of an informal pre-World War 1 discussion group, the so-called first Vienna Circle—and by RudolfCarnap reflected their pre-existent theoretical interests. Wittgenstein’s Tractatus contributed to their developing philosophy but was far from its foundation, contrary to what has often been presumed about the relation of Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  41
    The Murder of Professor Schlick: The Rise and Fall of the Vienna Circle.Allan Janik -2023 -Common Knowledge 29 (1):103-104.
    It is not unusual to speculate on the contrary-to-fact implications of political assassinations. Lincoln's is the classic case in point, but we need only think of Julius Caesar, Gandhi, or John Kennedy, if we require further examples. One totally neglected case in this context is that of Moritz Schlick. One of the remote consequences of his murder, on June 22, 1936, which was most definitely a political assassination, is that today's academic world may well have been an entirely different one (...) if he had gone on to lead the Vienna Circle into exile. That group of young philosophers of science had formed as he assumed the University of Vienna's chair of natural philosophy in 1922. A quarter of a century later, the entire English-speaking world (and Scandinavia) was in thrall to “logical positivism,” a caricature of scientific philosophy as the circle conceived it but an incredibly powerful intellectual standpoint, for all that. The view that all genuine knowledge can be quantified not only dominated philosophy but transformed the nature of universities to the point of threatening the very existence of the humanities, which could scarcely meet this demand. The polemical and oversimplified view of RudolfCarnap's strong program for scientific philosophy simply found no place for disciplines based on mere description (ethnology) or on understanding complex interlinked constellations of events as they develop over time (history and its myriad allied disciplines).The die was cast, and the humanities became saddled with an inferiority complex that, even today, they have only partially shaken off. Only disciplines that employed mathematical methods in aid of rigorous explanation, working collectively in networks like those of physics or chemistry, were worthy of being institutionalized at universities. Since the humanities were, for the most part, embodied in individual researchers burning the Midnight Oil as they pondered the Eternal Verities, they were disqualified as sciences. They would have to reform themselves radically or disappear. The battle commenced, and sensitive observers can attest that, administrative rhetoric to the contrary, it still goes on. Had Schlick lived on, the pluralism and tolerance that was part of his view of the world might well have carried more influence than the more radical elements in the group ultimately did, and so the humanities might well have fared better in a more secure environment than they have done.Edmonds's The Murder of Professor Schlick does not venture into such speculations. Instead, it offers us a vibrant, suspense-filled narrative replete with as much information as the reader can digest (and more). Briefly, Edmonds presents a fully detailed, complex version of the high drama of the rise and decline of logical positivism in both its philosophical and its political dimensions, complete with vivid portraits of the characters whose thought and personalities supplied that movement with its dazzling dynamism. They include such characters as Schlick himself; the irrepressible Otto Neurath, who had been a minister in the short-lived Bavarian Soviet Republic; RudolfCarnap, the circle's standard-bearer; Ludwig Wittgenstein, its unwilling ideal; Bertrand Russell, its Promethean inspiration; the eccentric Kurt Gödel; the rabbi Josef Schächter; the clever Englishman A. J. Ayer; America's rising star, W. V. Quine; the perennial contrarian, Karl Popper; the unfortunate Friedrich Waismann, doomed to failure in all his efforts; the tragic Edgar Zilsel, who committed suicide in American exile; and several frequently neglected women, such as Rose Rand, OlgaHahn, Marie Reidemeister, and Olga Taussky. In addition, the strong Jewish presence in the circle and the surrounding anti-Semitism that was a continuing stumbling block to it are clearly and powerfully described.These are but highlights of Edmond's narrative, but they are proof positive that his study is where to begin an encounter with the Vienna Circle and thus with the philosophical view that, more than any other, has conferred its character on modern thought and deeply molded people who have never heard of it. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  85
    Otto Neurath and Ludwig von Mises. Philosophy, Politics, and Economics in Viennese Late Enlightenment.Alexander Linsbichler -2021 -Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 14 (2).
    Logical empiricism and the Austrian School of economics are two of the internationally most influential intellectual movements with Viennese roots. By and large independently of each other, both have been subject to detailed historical and philosophical investigations for the last two dec-ades. However, in spite of numerous connections and interactions be-tween the two groups, their relationship has captured surprisingly sparse attention. My dissertation focuses on the many-faceted juxtaposition of two supposedly antagonistic championsof Viennese Late Enlightenment: logical empiricist Otto Neurath and (...) Austrian economist Ludwig Mises. I rationally reconstruct and critically compare their epistemological, meth-odological, and economic positions and demonstrate that a closer look reveals more compatibilities and similarities than acknowledged by the received view and by the protagonists themselves. Over and above the historiographic task of challenging and amending this received view, the analytic components of my thesis inform contemporary debates in phi-losophy, politics, economics, and other sciences. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24.  62
    Informe de RudolfCarnap sobre filósofos mexicanos presos.RudolfCarnap -2011 -Signos Filosóficos 13 (26):155-160.
  25.  63
    Jan WolenskiCarnap's metaphilosophy.Carnap'S. Metaphilosophy -2003 - In Thomas Bonk,Language, Truth and Knowledge: Contributions to the Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 2--27.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  8
    KurtHahn, Erinnerungen, Gedanken, Aufforderungen: Beiträge zum 100. Geburtstag des Reformpädagogen.KurtHahn &Werner Esser (eds.) -1987 - Lüneburg: K. Neubauer.
  27.  54
    Hannah Arendt—Complete Works, Critical Edition in Digital and Print: An Interview with BarbaraHahn, James McFarland, and Thomas Wild.BarbaraHahn,James McFarland &Thomas Wild -2019 -Arendt Studies 3:9-14.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  15
    A Contextualistic Worldview: Essays by Lewis E.Hahn.Lewis EdwinHahn -2001 - Southern Illinois University Press.
    This selection of articles by Lewis E.Hahn addresses the philosophical school of contextualism and four contemporary American philosophers: John Dewey, Henry Nelson Wieman, Stephen C. Pepper, and Brand Blanshard. Stressing the relatively recent contextualistic worldview, which he considers one of the best world hypotheses,Hahn seeks to achieve a broad perspective within which all things may be given their due place. After providing a brief outline,Hahn explains contextualism in relation to other philosophies. In his opening (...) chapter, as in later chapters, he expresses contextualism as a form of pragmatic naturalism. In spite ofHahn’s high regard for contextualism, however, he does not think it would be good if we were limited to a single worldview. “The more different views we have and the more different sources of possible light we have, the better our chances that some of these cosmic maps will shed light on our world and our place in it.”. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  140
    RudolfCarnap's analysis of `truth': Reply.RudolfCarnap -1948 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 9 (2):300-304.
  30.  29
    Carnap's internal and external questions: Part I: Quine's criticisms.I.Carnap'S. Distinctions -2003 - In Thomas Bonk,Language, Truth and Knowledge: Contributions to the Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 2--97.
  31.  12
    (2 other versions)John Dewey on Teaching Philosophy in High School.Lewis E.Hahn -1967 -Educational Theory 17 (3):219-221.
  32.  66
    Neutral, Indubitable Sense-Data as the Starting Point for Theories of Perception.Lewis EdwinHahn -1939 -Journal of Philosophy 36 (22):589-600.
  33. Transfiguration--glauben, staunen, denken, hoffen.Claudia Schmidt-Hahn (ed.) -2018 - Innsbruck: StudienVerlag.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  182
    Value concepts.RudolfCarnap -2017 -Synthese 194 (1):185-194.
    Carnap wrote a continuation of his reply to Kaplan, which would, however, have made that reply, already by far the longest in the book, too long. So he set aside his projected notes for a continuation to serve as the basis for a separate paper, which he never got around to writing. It is transcribed here from his shorthand and translated into English, with some introductory notes to provide a little context.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  35.  182
    Reflections and Replies: Essays on the Philosophy of Tyler Burge.MartinHahn &Björn T. Ramberg (eds.) -2003 - MIT Press.
    Essays by various philosphers on the work of Tyler Burge and Burge's extensive responses.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  36.  23
    Ilkka NiiniluotoCarnap on truth.I.Carnap'S. Early Work -2003 - In Thomas Bonk,Language, Truth and Knowledge: Contributions to the Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 2--1.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Contradiction in motion: Hegel's organic concept of life and value.Susan SongsukHahn -2007 - Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press.
    In this analysis of one of the most difficult and neglected topics in Hegelian studies, Songsuk SusanHahn tackles the status of contradiction in Hegel's ...
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  38.  45
    Die bedeutung der wissenschaftlichen weltauffassung, insbesondere für mathematik und physik.HansHahn -1930 -Erkenntnis 1 (1):96-105.
  39.  37
    Philosophy in Process.Lewis E.Hahn -1964 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 28 (3):458-459.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  49
    Frege's Lectures on Logic:Carnap's Student Notes, 1910-1914.Gottlob Frege &RudolfCarnap -2003 - Chicago, IL, USA: Open Court.
    "By looking at Frege's lectures on logic through the eyes of the youngCarnap, this book casts new light on the history of logic and analytic philosophy. As two introductory essays by Gottfried Gabriel and by Erich H. Reck and Steve Awodey explain,Carnap's notes allow us to better understand Frege's deep influence onCarnap and analytic philosophy, as well as the broader philosophical matrix from which both continental and analytic styles of thought emerged in the 20th (...) century."--BOOK JACKET. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  48
    How Communication Can Make Voters Choose Less Well.UlrikeHahn,Momme von Sydow &Christoph Merdes -2019 -Topics in Cognitive Science 11 (1):194-206.
    In recent years, the receipt and the perception of information has changed in ways which have fueled fears about the fates of our democracies. However, real information on these possibilities or the direction of these changes does not exist. Into this gap,Hahn and colleagues bring the power of Condorcet's (1785) Jury Theorem to show that changes in our information networks have affected voter inter‐dependence so that it is likely that voters are now collectively more ignorant even if individual (...) voter competence remains unchanged. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  42.  53
    Logic and Language Studies Dedicated to Professor RudolfCarnap on the Occasion of His Seventieth Birthday.RudolfCarnap -1963 - Reidel.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  73
    Collectives and Epistemic Rationality.UlrikeHahn -2022 -Topics in Cognitive Science 14 (3):602-620.
    Topics in Cognitive Science, Volume 14, Issue 3, Page 602-620, July 2022.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  35
    (1 other version)The Philosophy of W.V. Quine.Lewis EdwinHahn &Paul Arthur Schilpp (eds.) -1986 - Chicago: Open Court.
    For 30 years, Quine, a dominant figure in logical theory and philosophy of logic, has combined insights in methodology, language, epistemology, and ontology, to blur the boundaries of speculative metaphysics and natural sciences. This revised text contains two new essays with replies from Quine.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  45. Psa 1970 in Memory of RudolfCarnap : Proceedings of the 1970 Biennial Meeting, Philosophy of Science Association.Roger C. Buck,RudolfCarnap &R. S. Cohen -1971
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  56
    A Paradox Perspective on Corporate Sustainability: Descriptive, Instrumental, and Normative Aspects.TobiasHahn,Frank Figge,Jonatan Pinkse &Lutz Preuss -2018 -Journal of Business Ethics 148 (2):235-248.
    The last decade has witnessed the emergence of a paradox perspective on corporate sustainability. By explicitly acknowledging tensions between different desirable, yet interdependent and conflicting sustainability objectives, a paradox perspective enables decision makers to achieve competing sustainability objectives simultaneously and creates leeway for superior business contributions to sustainable development. In stark contrast to the business case logic, a paradox perspective does not establish emphasize business considerations over concerns for environmental protection and social well-being at the societal level. In order to (...) contribute to the consolidation of this emergent field of research, we offer a definition of the paradox perspective on corporate sustainability and a framework to delineate its descriptive, instrumental, and normative aspects. This framework clarifies the paradox perspective’s contents and its implications for research and practice. We use the framework to map the contributions to this thematic symposium on paradoxes in sustainability and to propose questions for future research. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  47.  23
    The Philosophy of RudolfCarnap.RudolfCarnap -1963 - Open Court. Edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp.
    The first volume of the Library of Living Philosophers (LLP) appeared in 1939, the brainchild of the late Professor Paul A. Schilpp. Schilpp saw that it would help to eliminate confusion and endless sterile disputes over interpretation if great philosophers could be confronted by their capable philosophical peers and asked to reply. As well as a number of critical essays with the chosen philosopher's replies to each essay, each volume would include an intellectual autobiography and an up-to-date bibliography The LLP (...) series has exceeded even Schilpp's expectations, enabling great philosophers to do more than clarify by extending and elaborating their thoughts. A volume in the Library of Living Philosophers is not merely a commentary on a philosopher's work; it is a critical part of that work. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  48. When swampmen get arthritis: "Externalism" in Burge and Davidson.MartinHahn -2003 - In Martin Hahn & Björn T. Ramberg,Reflections and Replies: Essays on the Philosophy of Tyler Burge. MIT Press.
  49.  71
    The rationality of informal argumentation: A Bayesian approach to reasoning fallacies.UlrikeHahn &Mike Oaksford -2007 -Psychological Review 114 (3):704-732.
  50.  43
    "Perceptions of randomness: Why three heads are better than four": Correction toHahn and Warren (2009).UlrikeHahn &Paul A. Warren -2009 -Psychological Review 116 (4):874-874.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 939
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp