Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'Greater good'

972 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  19
    EvaluatingGreaterGood Defenses.David O'Connor -2008 - InGod, Evil and Design: An Introduction to the Philosophical Issues. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 190–206.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Justified and Compensated Suffering and Death Afterlife A Theistic Variation on the Hypothesis of Indifference Verdict on theGreaterGood Defense Suggested Reading.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  11
    Thegreater-good defence: an essay on the rationality of faith.Melville Y. Stewart -1993 - New York: St. Martin's Press.
    Several defences, viewed in this study as specifications or 'offspring' of the 'parent'greater-good defence, have been formulated in response to the charge that Christianity is untenable because God's existence is incompatible with evil's existence. In this first book-length study of the parent defence, Stewart begins with careful definitions of the omni-attributes central to the dispute: omnipotence, omniscience, omnibenevolence. The parent defence is traced to tenets of theism and variant accounts of the defence considered. Plantinga's modal free-will defence (...) and Hick's and Yandell's soul-growth specifications are carefully analyzed and several difficulties resolved. An original formulation of a redemption specification and an original account of the origin of moral evil are offered. Stewart argues that the defences are rightly viewed as a family of defences falling under thegreater-good heading, and that they comprise a complementary apologetic complex that refutes the claim of inconsistency. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  3.  20
    GreaterGood Defenses.David O'Connor -2008 - InGod, Evil and Design: An Introduction to the Philosophical Issues. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 171–189.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Hick and Swinburne Moral Evil and the Free‐Will Defense Natural Disasters and other Terrible Things, and the Free‐Will Defense Suggested Reading.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  41
    TheGreaterGood Defense. [REVIEW]Jane Mary Trau -1996 -Faith and Philosophy 13 (2):293-296.
  5.  10
    GreaterGood: The Case for Proportionalism.Garth Hallett -1995 - Georgetown University Press.
    "Hallett's fine book defends his earlier accounts of the right-making characteristics of moral acts."-Religious Studies Review.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  40
    TheGreater-Good Defense.Brian Leftow &Melville Stewart -1996 -Philosophical Quarterly 46 (184):405.
  7.  27
    What the ‘greatergood’ excludes: Patients left behind by pre‐operative COVID‐19 screening in an Ethiopian town.Georgina D. Campelia,Hilkiah K. Suga,John H. Kempen,James N. Kirkpatrick &Nancy S. Jecker -2023 -Developing World Bioethics 23 (3):269-276.
    During the coronavirus disease 2019 (COVID‐19) pandemic, bioethical analyses often emphasized population health and societal benefit. Hospital policies frequently focused on reducing risk of transmitting SARS‐CoV‐2 by restricting visitors; requiring protective equipment; and screening staff, patients and visitors. While restrictions can be burdensome, they are often justified as essential measures to protect the whole population against a virus with high rates of transmission, morbidity and mortality. Yet communities are not monolithic, and the impacts of these restrictions affect different groups differently. (...) An ophthalmological unit outreach program in Ethiopia serves to illustrate. Pre‐operative screening policies were designed to protect as many patients as possible but had adverse impacts on underserved communities. As this case study demonstrates, creating hospital policies that truly serve thegood of the society may require a more holistic review of impacts on inequitably positioned communities. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  47
    Ideal Isolation for theGreaterGood: The Hazards of Postcolonial Freedom.Mary Theis -2015 -Cultura 12 (1):129-143.
    Given the increasing complexity of living in a global village, countries and regions that are parts of larger political entities frequently have considered the option of separating or seceding an ideal solution to their problems with a larger center of power. Isolation, a form of “freedom from,” has the potential of offering them free rein or “freedom to” manage their affairs for their own sake. Francophone playwrights and filmmakers have found the dialectical interplay between “freedom from” and “freedom to” fertile (...) dramatic soil for plays and films. Some of them work in both of these and other genres. These works seem to ask the same question: Is it desirable or possible to achieve both, even in ideal isolation, without suffering cultural stagnation or repeating the abuse of power on the part of the political center that led to the separation? This article explores the answers to this question given in the plays of Aimée Césaire, Anne Hébert, and Wajdi Mouawad within thegreater context for this issue found in J. M. Coetzee’s Waiting for the Barbarians and Azouz Begag’s Un Mouton dans la baignoire and in francophone films by Raoul Peck, Bertrand Tavernier, Claire Denis, Rachid Bouchareb, Ousmane Sembène, Michael Haneke, and Mathieu Kasovitz. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  40
    GreaterGood: The Case for Proportionalism. [REVIEW]Christopher Kaczor -1997 -Review of Metaphysics 50 (4):898-898.
    In this book, Garth L. Hallett offers the best book of its kind available today. Unlike many other apologiae for proportionalism, Hallet fully engages numerous contemporary moral philosophers, among them Robert Merrihew Adams, Alan Donagan, Judith Thomson, and Alan Gewirth, in addition to engaging Catholic theorists including Aquinas, Germain Grisez, and John Finnis. Hallet also merits commendation for breaking ranks with other proportionalists, particularly Peter Knauer, about not a few matters, most significantly the extent to which proportionalism governs the moral (...) life and the importance of the distinction between the "moral" and the "premoral.". (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  643
    Structures ofgreatergood theodicies: The objection from alternative goods.Bruce Langtry -1998 -Sophia 37 (2):1-17.
    The paper investigates howgreatergood theodicies are supposed to work, and argues that, in principle, appeal togreater goods can explain why God, if he exists, is justified in refraining from ensuring that there is little or no evil. (Readers interested in objections from alternative goods might also want to look at the rather different discussion of them in Section 7.11 of my book God, The Best, and Evil (OUP 2008).
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11.  33
    Pandering for theGreaterGood? Senate, People, and Politics in Cicero’s de lege agraria 1 and 2.Brian Krostenko -2021 -Polis 38 (1):108-126.
    Cicero’s first speeches as consul, de lege agraria I and II, delivered to the senate and the people respectively, are virtually identical in outline and broad argument. That allows the rhetorical technique of individual sections to be compared closely. This article uses such comparisons to probe the tactics and ideology of the speeches. In both Cicero’s choice of word and phrase might suggest that he is simply addressing his audiences as suits their stations. But a consideration of the circumstances of (...) the speeches reveals instead that Cicero is directing his audiences to alternate ways of imagining their social and political positions; in effect, Cicero propounds distinct, principled, and communalist definitions of dignitas and libertas, core values of each audience – though sometimes at the price of distorting the intent of the bill. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  74
    For theGreaterGood? The Devastating Ripple Effects of the Covid-19 Crisis.Michaéla C. Schippers -2020 -Frontiers in Psychology 11:577740.
    As the crisis around Covid-19 evolves, it becomes clear that there are numerous negative side-effects of the lockdown strategies implemented by many countries. Currently, more evidence becomes available that the lockdowns may have more negative effects than positive effects. For instance, many measures taken in a lockdown aimed at protecting human life may compromise the immune system, and purpose in life, especially of vulnerable groups. This leads to the paradoxical situation of compromising the immune system and physical and mental health (...) of many people, including the ones we aim to protect. Also, it is expected that hundreds of millions of people will die from hunger and postponed medical treatments. Other side effects include financial insecurity of billions of people, physical and mental health problems, and increased inequalities. The economic and health repercussions of the crisis will be falling disproportionately on young workers, low-income families and women, and thus exacerbate existing inequalities. As the virus outbreak and media coverage spread fear and anxiety, superstition, cognitive dissonance reduction and conspiracy theories are ways to find meaning and reduce anxiety. These behavioral aspects may play a role in the continuance of lockdown decisions. Based on theories regarding agnotology (i.e. the ways ignorance or doubt about certain topics is created by means of withholding or presenting information in a certain way), social influence, superstition and stress and coping, I seek to explain the social and behavioral aspects of human behavior in times of crises. Both the Covid-19 crisis itself as well as the resulting economic and (mental) health crisis are global problems that may require global solutions. I present a model of drivers and outcomes of lockdown behaviors and offer suggestions and a tool to counteract the negative psychological effects by means of online life crafting therapeutic writing interventions. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  13.  77
    Thegreatergood defense.Keith E. Yandell -1974 -Sophia 13 (3):1-16.
  14.  9
    Business and thegreatergood: rethinking business ethics in an age of crisis.Knut Johannessen Ims &Lars Jacob Tynes Pedersen (eds.) -2015 - Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.
    With cutting-edge insights from leading European and North American scholars, this authoritative book addresses the fundamental problems of business in an age of crisis whilst presenting radical, but practical, solutions. The contributors explore three main value shifts: from inequality to equality, from the technical-materialistic to the ecological-spiritual, and from compliance and enforcement to autonomy and responsibility. A number of striking issues are addressed including the doctrine of self-interest, the purpose of business, codes of conduct, personal responsibility, existential perspectives on business (...) ethics and the development of ethical competence. This book will be an essential point of reference for academic researchers and postgraduate students in business ethics and corporate social responsibility, as well as practitioners interested in the relevance of business ethics to leadership, management, strategy and finance. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  83
    Divine Hiddenness,Greater Goods, and Accommodation.Luke Teeninga -2017 -Sophia 56 (4):589-603.
    J.L. Schellenberg argues that one reason to think that God does not exist is that there are people who fail to believe in Him through no fault of their own. If God were all loving, then He would ensure that these people had evidence to believe in Him so that they could enter into a personal relationship with Him. God would not remain ‘hidden’. But in the world, we actually do find people who fail to believe that God exists, and (...) their nonbelief does not seem to be due to their resisting God. I argue that if there are valuable goods brought about by God’s hiddenness, then even if each of those goods might obtain without hiddenness, God would have a sufficient reason for remaining hidden so long as enough of those goods would be made sufficiently more valuable because of God’s hiddenness. If this is the case, then the existence of ‘nonresistant nonbelievers’ in the actual world does not entail that God does not exist. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  27
    Higher Learning,GreaterGood: The Private and Social Benefits of Higher Education.David Palfreyman -2011 -Perspectives: Policy and Practice in Higher Education 15 (3):99-102.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  17
    Thegood life and thegreatergood in a global context.Laura Savu Walker -2015 - Lanham: Lexington Books.
    TheGood Life and theGreaterGood in a Global Context brings together scholars working in the fields of the humanities and social sciences who critically examine the notion of the "good life," understood in all of its dimensions--material, psychological, moral, emotional, and spiritual--and in relation to thegreatergood. In so doing, the authors provide interdisciplinary insights into what thegood life means today and how a viable vision of it can be (...) achieved to benefit not just individuals but our interdependent world as well. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  52
    Higher learning,greatergood: The private and social benefits of higher education – by W. W. McMahon.Michael A. Peters -2010 -Educational Philosophy and Theory 42 (4):504-506.
  19.  59
    For thegreater goods? Ownership rights and utilitarian moral judgment.J. Charles Millar,John Turri &Ori Friedman -2014 -Cognition 133 (1):79-84.
    People often judge it unacceptable to directly harm a person, even when this is necessary to produce an overall positive outcome, such as saving five other lives. We demonstrate that similar judgments arise when people consider damage to owned objects. In two experiments, participants considered dilemmas where saving five inanimate objects required destroying one. Participants judged this unacceptable when it required violating another’s ownership rights, but not otherwise. They also judged that sacrificing another’s object was less acceptable as a means (...) than as a side-effect; judgments did not depend on whether property damage involved personal force. These findings inform theories of moral decision-making. They show that utilitarian judgment can be decreased without physical harm to persons, and without personal force. The findings also show that the distinction between means and side-effects influences the acceptability of damaging objects, and that ownership impacts utilitarian moral judgment. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  20.  24
    Pain, pleasure, and thegreatergood: from the Panopticon to the Skinner box and beyond.Cathy Gere -2017 - London: University of Chicago Press.
    "Contents "--"Introduction: Diving into the Wreck" -- "1. Trial of the Archangels" -- "2. Epicurus at the Scaffold" -- "3. Nasty, British, and Short" -- "4. The Monkey in the Panopticon" -- "5. In Which We Wonder Who Is Crazy" -- "6. Epicurus Unchained" -- "Afterword: The Restoration of the Monarchy" -- "Notes" -- "Bibliography.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  136
    Blockchain, TheGreaterGood, and Human and Civil Rights.Kobina Hughes -2017 -Metaphilosophy 48 (5):654-665.
    The central theme of this paper is that the development of a technology that is predicted to have a major impact on the way we transact with each other should be a matter where the needs of society at large are taken into account. Where the technology is one that emerges from the domain of the Internet, inclusivity becomes even more acute in order to avoid widening the already existing gap in reaping the “digital dividend.” With blockchain, the obligation could (...) even be seen as a moral one, as blockchain is said to have the potential to negate the scope for the abuse of trust by states and institutions. This could be a game changer in areas such as public procurement and the conduct of elections where abuse can lead to the denial of essential resources and a concomitant loss of life, or to conflict and mass killings. Blockchain presents an opportunity for the Internet development community to claim a degree of recognition in the human rights realm by aiding civil intervention in areas where military intervention has been deemed inappropriate. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  96
    Divine hiddenness and the problem of nogreater goods.Luke Teeninga -2021 -International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 89 (2):107-123.
    John Schellenberg argues that God would never withhold the possibility of conscious personal relationship with Him from anyone for the sake ofgreater goods, since there simply would not begreater goods than a conscious personal relationship with God. Given that nonresistant nonbelief withholds the possibility of such relationship, this entails that God would not allow nonresistant nonbelief for the sake ofgreater goods. Thus, if Schellenberg is right, allgreater goods responses to the hiddenness argument (...) must fail in principle. I argue that there aregood reasons for thinking thatgreater goods responses do not, for the above reason, fail in principle. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  26
    Paths of Glory and the Tyranny of theGreaterGood.Donald R. Riccomini -2016 -Film-Philosophy 20 (2-3):324-338.
    In Paths of Glory (Stanley Kubrick, 1957) the individual's moral intent is distorted, compromised, and eventually co-opted by the overriding utilitarian ethic of ensuring the survival of the system – the ultimate ‘greatergood’ – at all costs. The individual may challenge the system in a noble quest for justice, like Dax. He may hypocritically seek professional advancement from striving to serve it, like Mireau. Or he may cynically manipulate it for political purposes, like Broulard. In each case, (...) the consequences are ultimately the same – the individual is forced to align his particular moral vision, however noble or ignoble, with the imperative of thegreatergood. The individual may resist or affirm the system and achieve some level of moral consistency and purity, but only momentarily and with limited success. In the end, whatever the value or relevance of the individual conscience to a particular situation, it is overridden by the demands of thegreatergood. -/- . (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  48
    Universalism and theGreaterGood.Gordon Knight -1997 -Faith and Philosophy 14 (1):98-103.
    Thomas Talbott has recently argued in this journal that the three propositions 1) God wills universal salvation 2) God has the power to produce universal salvation and 3) some persons are not saved are inconsistent. I contend that this claim is only true if God has no overriding purposes that would place restrictions on the means God uses to achieve God’s ends. One possible example of such an overriding purpose would be God’s aim to produce the mostgood. I (...) end by suggesting that while God’s purpose of universal salvation does render the achievement of this end probable, it is by no means necessary. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  181
    ‘Utilitarian’ judgments in sacrificial moral dilemmas do not reflect impartial concern for thegreatergood.Guy Kahane,Jim Everett,Brian Earp,Miguel Farias &Julian Savulescu -2015 -Cognition 134 (C):193-209.
    No categories
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  26.  48
    Sacrificial utilitarian judgments do reflect concern for thegreatergood: Clarification via process dissociation and the judgments of philosophers.Paul Conway,Jacob Goldstein-Greenwood,David Polacek &Joshua D. Greene -2018 -Cognition 179 (C):241-265.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  27.  179
    Universalism and theGreaterGood: Reply to Gordon Knight.Thomas Talbott -1999 -Faith and Philosophy 16 (1):102-105.
    Gordon Knight recently challenged my assumption, which I made for the purpose of organizing and classifying certain theological disputes, that a specific set of three propositions is logically inconsistent . In this brief rejoinder, I explain Knight’s objection and show why it rests upon a misunderstanding.
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. ch. 4. Business and thegreatergood as a combination of private and public wealth.Georges Enderle -2015 - In Knut Johannessen Ims & Lars Jacob Tynes Pedersen,Business and the greater good: rethinking business ethics in an age of crisis. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  50
    O felix culpa, redemption, and theGreater-Good Defense.Melville Stewart -1986 -Sophia 25 (3):18-31.
  30. ch. 10. Personal responsibility for thegreatergood.Knut J. Ims &Lars Jacob Tynes Pedersen -2015 - In Knut Johannessen Ims & Lars Jacob Tynes Pedersen,Business and the greater good: rethinking business ethics in an age of crisis. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  20
    If there is aGreater EcologicalGood: On the Way to an Ethico-Politics with Zizek and Sluga.Mark Manolopoulos -2017 -International Journal of Žižek Studies 11 (2).
    Is there such a thing as “a/thegreatergood”? Could it be conceived in radically ecological terms? By critically drawing on skeptical insights presented by Slavoj Žižek and Hans Sluga, the article articulates what I am calling “a/thegreater ecologicalgood” as an end and as the ethico-political means to this end. I begin by describing thisgood as an aim: the survival-flourishing of earthly entities and environs. Its contours and limits are outlined, and various (...) Žižekian objections are addressed. Next, the ethical and political means for thisgood’s realization are delineated. We are summoned to allow things to survive-thrive. But the existing order excessively disallows things from surviving-flourishing, so we are compelled to struggle against it and foster a society of letting-be. The article concludes by proffering an outline of a possible strategy for this political struggle. It would involve the collaborative conception of a blueprint of this envisioned society; popularizing and building mass solidarity around the blueprint; and leveraging this solidarity to, ideally, peacefully implement the blueprint; otherwise, ethico-political violence may be required in order to realize thisgreater ecologicalgood. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  26
    Beyond Warm Glow: The Risk-Mitigating Effect of Corporate Social Responsibility.Abhi Bhattacharya,ValerieGood,Hanieh Sardashti &John Peloza -2020 -Journal of Business Ethics 171 (2):317-336.
    Corporate social responsibility positively impacts relationships between firms and customers. Previous research construes this as an outcome of customers’ warm glow that results from supporting firms’ benevolence. The current research demonstrates that beyond warm glow, CSR positively impacts firms’ sales through mitigating their customers’ perceptions of purchase risk. We demonstrate this effect across three conditions in which customers’ perceived risk of purchase is heightened, using both secondary data and two lab experiments. Under conditions ofgreater purchase risk, CSR positively (...) impacts both sales and customer purchase intentions to agreater extent than in conditions of lower purchase risk. In addition to measuring purchase risk as the mediating process behind these effects, we demonstrate that the effect of CSR on sales is stronger for those CSR activities that signal a stakeholder orientation. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  33.  33
    Pain, Pleasure, and theGreaterGood: From Panopticon to the Skinner Box and Beyond[REVIEW]Fenneke Sysling -2018 -Isis 109 (4):818-819.
  34.  106
    When Will Your Consequentialist Friend Abandon You for theGreaterGood?Scott Woodcock -2010 -Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 4 (2):1-24.
    According to a well-known objection to consequentialism, the answer to the preceding question is alarmingly straightforward: your consequentialist friend will abandon you the minute that she can more efficiently promote goodness via options that do not include her maintaining a relationship with you. The most prominent response to this objection is to emphasize the profound value of friendship for human agents and to remind critics of the distinction between the theory’s criterion of rightness and an effective decision-making procedure. Whether or (...) not this response is viable remains a contentious issue within the now considerable literature generated on the topic, yet it is a curious fact that the debate has unfolded in such a way that the question of when a consequentialist agent ought to break from her indirect methods of promoting thegood and revert back to a direct form of consequentialist decision-making has not been decisively settled. In this paper, I claim that the empirical considerations at stake for resolving this question are more complicated than is normally acknowledged; however, I argue that this should not deter sophisticated consequentialists from endorsing flexible psychological dispositions in order to monitor these empirical considerations as best as can be expected for agents with our distinctly human faculties and limitations. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  41
    Susan Lanzoni, Empathy: A History. New Haven, CT and London: Yale University Press, 2018. Pp. ix + 392. ISBN 978-0-3002-2268-5. $30.00 . - Cathy Gere, Pain, Pleasure, and theGreaterGood: From the Panopticon to the Skinner Box and Beyond. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 2017. Pp. 282. ISBN 978-0-2265-0185-7. $30.00. [REVIEW]Rob Boddice -2019 -British Journal for the History of Science 52 (3):534-535.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  8
    Children's cost-benefit analysis about agents who act for thegreatergood.Zoe Finiasz,Montana Shore,Fei Xu &Tamar Kushnir -2025 -Cognition 256 (C):106051.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  36
    AGreater Means to theGreaterGood: Ethical Guidelines to Meet Social Movement Organization Advocacy Challenges.Carrie Packwood Freeman -2009 -Journal of Mass Media Ethics 24 (4):269-288.
    Existing public relations ethics literature often proves inadequate when applied to social movement campaigns, considering the special communication challenges activists face as marginalized moral visionaries in a commercial public sphere. The communications of counter-hegemonic movements is distinct enough from corporate, nonprofit, and governmental organizations to warrant its own ethical guidelines. The unique communication guidelines most relevant to social movement organizations include promoting asymmetrical advocacy to agreater extent than is required for more powerful organizations and building flexibility into the (...) TARES principles to privilege social responsibility over respect for audience values in activist campaigns serving as ideological critique. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  72
    Perceptual differences of sales practitioners and students concerning ethical behavior.J. B. DeConinck &D. J.Good -1989 -Journal of Business Ethics 8 (9):667 - 676.
    This study investigates specific behavioral perceptual differences of ethics between practitioners and students enrolled in sales classes. Respondents were asked to indicate their beliefs to issues related to ethics in sales. A highly significant difference was found between mean responses of students and sales personnel. Managers indicated agreater concern for ethical behavior and less attention to sales than did the students. Students indicated a strong desire for success regardless of ethical constraints violated.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  39.  24
    Prosperity: Better Business Makes theGreaterGood, by Colin Mayer. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018. 288 pp. [REVIEW]Ryan Burg -2019 -Business Ethics Quarterly 29 (4):545-549.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  31
    A LoveGreater Than Which Cannot Be Imagined: Divine Goodness and Mercy in Anselm's Cur Deus homo.Daniel Waldow -2021 -Heythrop Journal 62 (4):703-718.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  129
    For theGreater Individual and SocialGood: Justifying Age-Differentiated Paternalism.Viki Møller Lyngby Pedersen -2024 -Utilitas 36 (1):1-15.
    What justifies differences in the acceptance of paternalism towards competent minors and older people? I propose two arguments. The first argument draws on the widely accepted view that paternalism is easier to justify the moregood it promotes for the paternalizee. It argues that paternalism targeting young people generally promotes moregood for the people interfered with than similar paternalism targeting older people. While promoting people's interests or well-being is essential to the justification of paternalism, the first argument (...) has certain unfair implications in that it disfavours paternalism towards the worse off. The second argument caters to such fairness concerns. It argues that priority or inequality aversion supports age-differentiated paternalism because young people, who act imprudently and thereby risk their interests or well-being, are worse off than older people who act in similar ways. I suggest that both arguments are pertinent in evaluating specific paternalistic acts and policies. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  30
    When Higher Risk Does Not EqualGreater Harm: Doing the MostGood in a Limited Pediatric Study Population.Jeff Matsler &Jamila M. Young -2020 -American Journal of Bioethics 20 (4):118-120.
    Volume 20, Issue 4, May 2020, Page 118-120.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  178
    Good reasons to vaccinate: mandatory or payment for risk?Julian Savulescu -2021 -Journal of Medical Ethics 47 (2):78-85.
    Mandatory vaccination, including for COVID-19, can be ethically justified if the threat to public health is grave, the confidence in safety and effectiveness is high, the expected utility of mandatory vaccination isgreater than the alternatives, and the penalties or costs for non-compliance are proportionate. I describe an algorithm for justified mandatory vaccination. Penalties or costs could include withholding of benefits, imposition of fines, provision of community service or loss of freedoms. I argue that under conditions of risk or (...) perceived risk of a novel vaccination, a system of payment for risk in vaccination may be superior. I defend a payment model against various objections, including that it constitutes coercion and undermines solidarity. I argue that payment can be in cash or in kind, and opportunity for altruistic vaccinations can be preserved by offering people who have been vaccinated the opportunity to donate any cash payment back to the health service. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  44.  14
    Science and the “Good Citizen”: Community-Based Scientific Literacy.Wolff-Michael Roth &Stuart Lee -2003 -Science, Technology and Human Values 28 (3):403-424.
    Science literacy is frequently touted as a key togood citizenship. Based on a two-year ethnographic study examining science in the community, the authors suggest that when considering the contribution of scientific activity to thegreatergood, science must be seen as forming a unique hybrid practice, mixed in with other mediating practices, which together constitute “scientifically literate,good citizenship.” This case study, an analysis of an open house event organized by a grassroots environmentalist group, presents (...) some examples of activities that embed science in “good citizenship.” Through a series of vignettes, the authors focus on four central aspects: the activists' use of landscape and spatial arrangements, the importance of multiple representations of the same entity, the relational aspect of knowing and becoming part of a community, and the insertion of scientific into moral discourse, resulting in what they call a “stewardship triad.”. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45.  9
    Good and Evil: Interpreting a Human Condition by Edward Farley, and: The Evils of Theodicy by Terrence W. Tilley, and: The Co-Existence of God and Evil by Jane Mary Trau.Phillip Quinn -1992 -The Thomist 56 (3):525-530.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:BOOK REVIEWSGood and Evil: Interpreting a Human Condition. By EDWARD FARLEY. Minneapolis, Minn.: Fortress Press, 1990. Pp. xxi + 295. The Evils of Theodicy. By TERRENCE W. TILLEY. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 1990. Pp. xii + 277. The Co-Existence of God and Evil. By JANE MARY TRAU. New York, N.Y.: Peter Lang, 1991. Pp. 109. Evil is deeply and endlessly fascinating to the religious mind. On (...) the one hand, it challenges religion. The existence of the evils within our ken poses a threat to the rationality of central tenets of theism; the presence of overwhelming evils within our lives can threaten the viabil· ity of our religious attitudes and practices. On the other hand, religions typically offer strategies for coping with evil. They propose explanations of its origins that may aid us in understanding it, and they con· tain salvific practices that are meant to lead to redemption from sin or the cessation of suffering. So religious responses to evil are bound to be complex, and this complexity will inevitably be reflected in the treatment of evil in academic discourses. In addition, the present academic division of labor results in religion being studied in many disciplines. Each of them has its own traditions and agendas, and this often leads to a diversity of approaches that gives interdisciplinary dis· cussion of religious responses to evil something of the air of conversa· tion after Babel. The three books under review here, which represent the disciplines of philosophy, religious studies, and theology, illustrate nicely both the complexity and the diversity. Jane Mary Trau, who is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Barry University, has written a short essay in analytic philosophy of religion proposing a solution to the logical problem of evil. The problem arises from the fact that there are arguments purporting to show that the proposition that God is omniscient, omnipotent, and omnibenevolent is inconsistent with the proposition that evil exists. One way to solve the problem would be to find a possibly true proposition such that it is consistent with the proposition ·that God is omniscient, omnipotent, and omnibenevolent and together with that proposition entails that evil exists. Alvin Plantinga's celebrated free-will defense offers a solution of this sort. Trau's alternative solution is a version of the familiargreater-goods defense. Trau's main claim is that it is possible that evil has positive value. An evil has positive value if it is logically necessary for somegreater 525 526 BOOK REVIEWSgood, and it certainly seems to he possible that some evils have positive value. Thus, for example, suppose God creates nothing other than two angels, A and B. Nothing interrupts the felicity of either hut a mild pang of sorrow felt by A, to which B responds with compassion. A's sorrow is logically necessary for thegreatergood of B's compassionate response to A's sorrow. Hence A's sorrow is an evil that has positive value. Moreover, the proposition that evils with positive value exist is consistent with the proposition that God is omniscient, omnipotent, and omnihenevolent. So the existence of evil is consistent with the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent, and omnihenevolent deity. In other words, Trau's version of thegreater-goods defense does seem to provide a solution to the logical problem of evil. But that is not to say that all the evils there actually are or even all those we know about do or could have positive value. Thus it does not follow, without further assumptions, that the existence of all the evils there actually are is consistent with the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent, and omnihenevolent deity. In a discussion of natural evil near the end of her hook, Trau acknowledges the need for such additional assumptions. She says: "Four assumptions underlie the claim that natural evils have positive value: (1) The material universe has positive value. (2) The material universe must function in a way that requires the occurrence of natural evils as secondary effects. (3) The material universe is either the best or the only possible universe. (4) If the universe as we know it did not function the way it does... (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  97
    Scratched Fingers, Ruined Lives, and Acknowledged Lesser Goods.Cass Weller -2004 -Hume Studies 30 (1):51-85.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Studies Volume 30, Number 1, April 2004, pp. 51-85 Scratched Fingers, Ruined Lives, and Acknowledged Lesser Goods CASS WELLER It is not contrary to reason to prefer the destruction of the whole world to the scratching of my finger. It is not contrary to reason for me to choose my total ruin, to prevent the least uneasiness of an Indian, or person wholly unknown to me. It is (...) as little contrary to reason to prefer even my own acknowledged lessergood to mygreater, and have a more ardent affection for the former than the latter. (T 2.3.3.6; SBN 416)1 Everyone is familiar with the cases Hume parades in this passage when he dramatically displays just how far one's preferences and other passions can go without being contrary to reason. His general point is tediously clear. Whatever failing there is in one who prefers the destruction of the world to the scratching of his finger or chooses his total ruin to prevent the least uneasiness of a person wholly unknown to him, it is not a failing of reason, unless this preference and choice involve false suppositions of fact, existence, or mathematics. But they do not according to Hume. So they are not contrary to reason. At the same time, anyone who is given to worrying and fretting over the text will be initially somewhat at a loss to explain in any further detail the nature of the phenomena Hume flaunts as not flouting reason and how they relate to one another. For example, is the notion of preference at work that of a settled judgment of value or that of a blind impulse to be understood only in terms of strength of desire? Is the character Hume inhabits in the first person one who simply finds himself with a blind urge to keep his finger scratch-free or one who Cass Weiler is Associate Professor of Philosophy, University of Washington, Seattle, WA 98195, USA. e-mail:[email protected] 52 Cass Weller has a settled policy of keeping his finger scratch-free viewed as more valuable than anything else. Is preferring my lessergood to my acknowledgedgreatergood the practical counterpart of self-consciously believing that Ï• and not p? Or is it, rather, a common form of weakness? And if so, how is it related to the two previous cases? Although most discussions of Hume's views on practical reason refer to this passage, I know of no extended discussion of the three notorious cases.2 This is no doubt due in part to the fact that the details do not really matter for understanding the main point. A mental state not involving a false belief of experience or a priori reason cannot be contrary to reason.3 Nevertheless, I think it is agood idea to try and figure out just what Hume is saying and that by digging right here we may hope to uncover important aspects of Hume's theory of evaluation, motive, and reason. The task is to get a more detailed view of Hume's own theoretical understanding of the preferences and choices he exhibits as not contrary to reason, in particular whether a preference is an evaluative attitude, and how it may conflict with an acknowledged interest. To this end we will have to go beyond what is adequate for a reader's understanding of the preferences in their narrow rhetorical context. Hume himself invites the reader, inadvertently or not, to look for the wider Humean explanation of preferring one's acknowledged lessergood to thegreater by deploying the analogy of a one pound weight's raising a hundred through the advantage of its situation. This idea connects with other passages in the Treatise, as we shall see, in particular with Hume's discussion of the preference for the contiguous over the remote at T 3.2.7 (SBN 534-9). With a clearer view of Hume's understanding of the preferences we will be in a better position to ask about the sort of criticism persons with such preferences are subject to. And, to tip my hand, we will see that Hume... (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  26
    InGood Times but Not in Bad: The Role of Managerial Discretion in Moderating the Stakeholder Management and Financial Performance Relationship.Ali M. Shahzad,Matthew A. Rutherford &Mark P. Sharfman -2016 -Business and Society Review 121 (4):497-528.
    We examine the role of managers in controlling the positive impact of stakeholder management (SM) on firm financial performance (FP) in the long term. We develop and test competing hypotheses on whether managers act as “good citizens” or engage in “self‐dealing” when allowedgreater discretion. We test our assertions using dynamic panel data analysis of a sample of 806 U.S. public firms operating in 34 industries over 5 years (2005–2009). Our results indicate a nuanced influence of managerial discretion (...) contexts on the SM‐FP relationship. We infer that given more latitude in decision making, as long as the “going isgood” managers act asgood citizens, but otherwise they revert to managerial self‐dealing. In light of our results, firms designing governance mechanisms to encourage managers to balance the needs of both shareholders and stakeholders must remain cognizant of contextual contingencies. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  99
    Cangood news lead to a more pessimistic choice of action?Giacomo Bonanno -1988 -Theory and Decision 25 (2):123-136.
    Adapting a definition introduced by Milgrom (1981) we say that a signal about the environment isgood news relative to some initial beliefs if the posterior beliefs dominate the initial beliefs in the sense of first-order stochastic dominance (the assumption being that higher values of the parameter representing the environment mean better environments). We give an example wheregood news leads to the adoption of a more pessimistic course of action (we say that action a, revealsgreater (...) pessimism than action a„ if it gives higher payoff in bad environments and lower payoff ingood environments). We then give sufficient conditions for a signal not to induce a more pessimistic choice of action. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  30
    Good Enough to be God.Thomas M. Ward -2022 -Journal of Analytic Theology 10:65-75.
    This paper develops a view of worship according to which worship is a certain sort of _life orientation_, and argues that according to the Bible, the worship of God normatively is _non-instrumental, comprehensive, unconditional orientation of one’s life toward God_. It then develops a biblical view about how this sort of worship of God is _possible_. Finally, it argues that it is _good_ to worship God in this way only if God is an Anselmian being—_that than which nothinggreater (...) can be conceived_—and suggests that the God of the Bible, the Psalms in particular, is in fact an Anselmian being. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  42
    Attributes of agood nurse.Rahime Aydin Er,Mine Sehiralti &Aslihan Akpinar -2017 -Nursing Ethics 24 (2):238-250.
    Background: The opinions of students regarding the attributes of agood nurse can make a major contribution to the planning and the conducting of professional education. There are few studies which aim at identifying the qualifications of agood nurse from the perspectives of nursing students. Objectives: To determine the opinions of first- and fourth-year nursing students concerning the ‘attributes of agood nurse’, and whether and how their views change depending on their year of study. Research (...) design: Descriptive research. Participants and research context: This study was conducted in the nursing department of a vocational school of health in the 2010/2011 academic year. The study participants consisted of first-year and intern students. A survey form was used to identify characteristics of participants, and students were asked the following open-ended question about their opinions related to the attributes of agood nurse. Ethical considerations: The permission was taken from the school administration. Informed consent was obtained, and anonymity was ensured for participating students. Findings: A total of 120 students participated in this study. Most frequently expressed attributes were ‘professional competence’ in first-year and ‘responsibility’ in fourth-year students. While first-year students placed agreater emphasis on the attributes of ‘geniality’, ‘patience’, ‘calmness’, ‘love of nursing’, ‘loyalty to nursing’ and ‘not attaching importance to material values’, fourth-year students emphasized the attributes of ‘empathy’, ‘honesty’, ‘responsibility’ and ‘scientific curiosity’ significantly more. Discussion and conclusion: Fourth-year students placed agreater emphasis on the attributes which the students are expected to acquire through a nursing program and clinical experience. However, they mentioned the attributes related to agood nurse–patient relationship and communication significantly less. Appropriate ethical training methods andgood role models can help students acquire attributes that are important for the nursing profession and combine them with the attributes they already have. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
1 — 50 / 972
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp