Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'Douglas C. Pitt'

961 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  48
    Value Congruence Awareness: Part 2. DNA Testing Sheds Light on Functionalism.Robert G. Isaac,L. Kim Wilson &Douglas C.Pitt -2004 -Journal of Business Ethics 54 (3):297-309.
    Part 1 of this exploratory study demonstrated that for terminal, instrumental, and work values, supervisors could only accurately assess the extent to which their terminal values are congruent with their employees, whereas, employees could only accurately describe degrees of alignment with their supervisors' work values. Thus, supervisors appear to possess conscious awareness of the terminal values held by their employees and employees similarly possess conscious awareness of their supervisors' work values. Part 2 of the study examined what each of these (...) two parties might do with their conscious knowledge concerning value congruence with the other member. Supervisor ratings and employee self-ratings concerning employee job performance, citizenship, climate fit, working relationship (LMX), and other issues, were correlated with supervisor terminal value congruence estimates and employee work value congruence estimates respectively. For supervisors, only one significant finding was noted, indicating a positive relationship between the supervisors' awareness of terminal value congruence with the employee and the supervisors' estimate of the employee's potential for future promotion. For employees, seven hypotheses received support demonstrating relationships between the employees' awareness of supervisor/employee work value congruence and self-ratings of work behaviours, citizenship behaviours, volunteerism behaviours, work climate behaviours, work climate attitudes, work climate organizational-wide attitudes, and the supervisor/employee working relationship. Implications for management and future research are discussed. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  248
    The Contributions of the Bodily Senses to Body Representations in the Brain.Douglas C. Wadle -forthcoming -Review of Philosophy and Psychology:1-32.
    Felix reaches up to catch a high line drive to left field and fires the ball off to Benji at home plate, who then tags the runner trying to score. For Felix to catch the ball and transfer it from his glove to his throwing hand, he needs to have a sense of where his hands are relative to one another and the rest of his body. This sort of information is subconsciously tracked in the body schema (or postural schema), (...) a representation of the current bodily posture that is updated on the basis of proprioceptive inputs. While the existence of the body schema in not in dispute, its origin is. After reviewing the competing proposals, I introduce the conceptual tools needed to move the debate forward and apply them to the question of the extent to which the body schema could be learned from perceptual input in utero. I argue that it could give rise to something recognizable as the body schema, though not quite rising to the level of the mature body schema. After considering the implications for further research on the origins of the body schema, I show how these results apply to other body representations, helping clarify the vexing question of the number, nature, and interactions among body representations in the brain. This theoretical work also promises to advance our understanding and treatment protocols for disorders affecting such body representations (e.g., anorexia nervosa). (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  22
    The Mechanism of Paradox in the Structures of Logic, Mathematics, and Physics.Douglas C. Gill -2023 -Open Journal of Philosophy 13 (2):155-170.
    This paper presents a model for the structure of universal frameworks in logic, mathematics, and physics that are closed to logical conclusion by the mechanism of paradox across a dualism of elements. The prohibition takes different forms defined by the framework of observation inherent to the structure. Forms include either prohibition to conclusion on the logical relationship of internal elements or prohibition to conclusion based on the existence of an element not included in the framework of a first element. The (...) model is applied to logical arguments in philosophy, mathematics, and physics and is initially a geometrical analysis of quantum theory and its application in experiment. Conclusion from the analysis is extended to give insight into the complexity of infinities above the two-dimensional boundary of the model. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4.  751
    Sensory modalities and novel features of perceptual experiences.Douglas C. Wadle -2020 -Synthese 198 (10):9841-9872.
    Is the flavor of mint reducible to the minty smell, the taste, and the menthol-like coolness on the roof of one’s mouth, or does it include something over and above these—something not properly associated with any one of the contributing senses? More generally, are there features of perceptual experiences—so-called novel features—that are not associated with any of our senses taken singly? This question has received a lot of attention of late. Yet surprisingly little attention has been paid to the question (...) of what it means to say that a feature is associated with a sensory modality in the first place. Indeed, there is only one fully developed proposal in the literature, due to Casey O’Callaghan. I argue that this proposal is too permissive to inform the debate over novel features. I go on to argue that all attempts to formulate a better proposal along these lines fail. The corollary of my arguments is that the question of the existence of novel features is poorly formed. Furthermore, the problem generalizes, with the result that we should not rely on our pre-theoretical notions of the senses as the basis of theorizing about the features of perceptual experiences. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  23
    (1 other version)Conscience and Other Virtues: From Bonaventure to Macintyre.Douglas C. Langston -2000 - Pennsylvania State University Press.
    In this bookDouglas Langston traces its intellectual history to account for its neglect while arguing for its still vital importance, if correctly understood.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  6. Body, Mind, and Method.Douglas C. Long (ed.) -1979 - Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidl.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  905
    (1 other version)Particulars and their qualities.Douglas C. Long -1968 -Philosophical Quarterly 18 (72):193-206.
    Berkeley, Hume, and Russell rejected the traditional analysis of substances in terms of qualities which are supported by an "unknowable substratum." To them the proper alternative seemed obvious. Eliminate the substratum in which qualities are alleged to inhere, leaving a bundle of coexisting qualities--a view that we may call the Bundle Theory or BT. But by rejecting only part of the traditional substratum theory instead of replacing it entirely, Bundle Theories perpetuate certain confusions which are found in the Substratum Doctrine. (...) I examine two major types of BT developed by Russell and by G. F. Stout with the intention of showing that (1) the seemingly innocuous concept of "a quality" employed by these versions cannot be used to state their theories coherently, and (2) the fatal problems that the BT encounters point to a more satisfactory and interesting alternative to both the Substratum Doctrine and the BT. This is a view that I call the Qualified Particulars Theory. In a final section I draw morals from this discussion that apply to the analogous Humean view that a mind is a "bundle of perceptions and sensations.". (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  8.  28
    Eye fixation and spatial organization in imagery.Douglas C. Hall -1974 -Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 3 (5):335-337.
  9.  35
    Scotus and Ockham on the Univocal Concept of Being.Douglas C. Langston -1979 -Franciscan Studies 39 (1):105-129.
  10.  27
    Emerson and the Agrarian Tradition.Douglas C. Stenerson -1953 -Journal of the History of Ideas 14 (1):95.
  11. John vickrey Van Cleve.Douglas C. Baynton -1999 -Semiotica 126 (1/4):143-150.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  489
    Restricted Auditory Aspatialism.Douglas C. Wadle -2025 -British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 76 (1):173-207.
    Some philosophers have argued that we do not hear sounds as located in the environment. Others have objected that this straightforwardly contradicts the phenomenology of auditory experience. And from this they draw metaphysical conclusions about the nature of sounds—that they are events or properties of vibrating surfaces rather than waves or sensations. I argue that there is a minimal, but recognizable, notion of audition to which this phenomenal objection does not apply. While this notion doesn’t correspond to our ordinary notion (...) of auditory experience, it does—in conjunction with our lack of an uncontroversial individuation of the senses and recent interest in distinctively multisensory features of perceptual experiences—raise the possibility of more expansive notions of audition, including some that do plausibly count as corresponding to our everyday notion of audition, that lack the spatial phenomenology cited in the objection. Until this possibility is ruled out, the phenomenal objection and metaphysical conclusions drawn from it remain inconclusive. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. The philosophical concept of a human body.Douglas C. Long -1964 -Philosophical Review 73 (July):321-337.
    I argue in this paper that philosophers have not clearly introduced the concept of a body in terms of which the problem of other minds and its solutions have been traditionally stated; that one can raise fatal objections to attempts to introduce this concept; and that the particular form of the problem of other minds which is stated in terms of the concept is confused and requires no solution. The concept of a "body" which may or may not be the (...) body of a person, which is required to state the traditional problem, is, on close examination, incoherent and cannot be introduced into a reasonable philosophical discussion. Also published in The Philosophy of the Body, Rejections of Cartesian Dualism, ed. Stuart F. Spicker. (shrink)
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14. Descartes' argument for mind-body dualism.Douglas C. Long -1969 -Philosophical Forum 1 (3):259-273.
    In his Meditations Descartes concludes that he is a res cogitans, an unextended entity whose essence is to be conscious. His reasoning in support of the conclusion that he exists entirely distinct from his body has seemed unconvincing to his critics. I attempt to show that the reasoning which he offers in support of his conclusion. although mistaken, is more plausible and his mistakes more interesting than his critics have acknowledged.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  57
    Moral Scepticism and Moral Knowledge.Douglas C. Long -1984 -Noûs 18 (1):132-136.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  69
    Scotus's doctrine of intuitive cognition.Douglas C. Langston -1993 -Synthese 96 (1):3 - 24.
  17.  532
    The self-defeating character of skepticism.Douglas C. Long -1992 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1):67-84.
    An important source of doubt about our knowledge of the "external world" is the thought that all of our sensory experience could be delusive without our realizing it. Such wholesale questioning of the deliverances of all forms of perception seems to leave no resources for successfully justifying our belief in the existence of an objective world beyond our subjective experiences. I argue that there is there is a fatal flaw in the very expression of philosophical doubt about the "external world." (...) Therefore, no such justification is necessary. The feature of skepticism which I believe renders it vulnerable is the assumption that each of us has a right to be certain of his own existence as a subject of conscious experience even in the face of comprehensive doubt about our empirical beliefs. (shrink)
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  18. How Dualists Should (Not) Respond to the Objection from Energy Conservation.Alin C. Cucu &J. Brian Pitts -2019 -Mind and Matter 17 (1):95-121.
    The principle of energy conservation is widely taken to be a se- rious difficulty for interactionist dualism (whether property or sub- stance). Interactionists often have therefore tried to make it satisfy energy conservation. This paper examines several such attempts, especially including E. J. Lowe’s varying constants proposal, show- ing how they all miss their goal due to lack of engagement with the physico-mathematical roots of energy conservation physics: the first Noether theorem (that symmetries imply conservation laws), its converse (that conservation (...) laws imply symmetries), and the locality of continuum/field physics. Thus the “conditionality re- sponse”, which sees conservation as (bi)conditional upon symme- tries and simply accepts energy non-conservation as an aspect of interactionist dualism, is seen to be, perhaps surprisingly, the one most in accord with contemporary physics (apart from quantum mechanics) by not conflicting with mathematical theorems basic to physics. A decent objection to interactionism should be a posteri- ori, based on empirically studying the brain. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  19.  62
    Grandparental investment and the epiphenomenon of menopause in recent human history.Douglas C. Broadfield -2010 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33 (1):19-20.
    The effects of grandparental investment in relatives are apparent in human groups, suggesting that a postreproductive period in humans is selective. Although investment of relatives in kin produces obvious benefits for kin groups, selection for a postreproductive period in humans is not supported by evidence from chimpanzees. Instead, grandparental investment is likely a recent phenomenon of longevity, rather than an evolved feature.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  15
    Aquinas on Conscience, the Virtues, and Weakness of Will.Douglas C. Langston -1998 -The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 9:35-41.
    The intellectualistic analysis of conscience Aquinas provides appears to regard conscience as mechanistic and undynamic. Such understanding fails to place Aquinas’s remarks on conscience in the context of the virtue ethics he offers in the Summa and his Commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics. In fact, there is an intricate connection between the virtues and conscience in Aquinas’s thought, and this connection relates directly to his remarks on weakness of will. His connecting conscience to issues in Aristotelian virtue ethics affects subsequent (...) discussions of conscience in significant ways. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  933
    The Problem of the Unity of the Representative Assembly in Hobbes’s Leviathan.Douglas C. Wadle -2017 -Hobbes Studies 30 (2):178-201.
    In _Leviathan_, Hobbes embraces three seemingly inconsistent claims: (i) the unity of a multitude is secured only by the unity of its representer, (ii) assemblies can represent other multitudes, and (iii) assemblies are, or are constituted by, multitudes. Together these claims require that a representative assembly, itself, be represented. If that representer is another assembly, it too will need a unifying representer, and so on. To stop a regress, we will need an already unified representer. But a multitude can only (...) speak or act through its representer, and an assembly is a multitude, so any representing done by the assembly is actually done by this already unified, regress-stopping representer. That is, if (i) and (iii) are true, (ii) cannot be. I will argue that this inconsistency is only apparent and that we can resolve it without rejecting any of these three claims. We do this by appealing to a representer-as-decision-procedure meeting certain criteria. Such a procedural representer breaks the transitivity of representation such that the assembly it represents can properly represent some further multitude. I proceed in my defense of the procedural representer view by addressing a series of problems it faces, the solutions to which give us a progressively clearer picture of the criteria this representer must meet. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  31
    The Aristotelian Background to Scotus's Rejection of the Necessary Connection of Prudence and the Moral Virtues.Douglas C. Langston -2008 -Franciscan Studies 66:317-336.
  23.  39
    How We Should Conceive of Creation: Natural Birth as an Ethical Guidepost for Neonatal Rescue.Douglas C. McAdams,W. Kevin Conley,Kevin T. FitzGerald &G. Kevin Donovan -2017 -American Journal of Bioethics 17 (8):42-44.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  45
    (2 other versions)Is "realistic epistemological monism inadmissible"?Douglas C. Macintosh -1913 -Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 10 (26):701-710.
  25.  56
    Descartes: Critical and Interpretive Essays.Douglas C. Long -1983 -Noûs 17 (1):99-104.
  26.  21
    A note reconsidering the message of Heraclius’ silver hexagram, circa AD 615.Douglas C. Whalin -2019 -Byzantinische Zeitschrift 112 (1):221-232.
    The hexagram was first minted during the darkest days of the final Roman-Persian War when Roman fortunes were at their lowest. As a result, commentators have read the coin’s novel inscription, Deus Adiuta Romanis as evidence for the ’stressful and desperate’ state of the empire. This paper presents the case that reading the coin alongside evidence for popular military practices instead paints a picture of the Roman state apparatus deftly manipulating mass propaganda. For the Romans in the 610s, these new (...) coins signalled not defeatism but defiance and the promise of victory. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  75
    (1 other version)Representational pragmatism.Douglas C. Macintosh -1912 -Mind 21 (82):167-181.
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  30
    The next step in the epistemological dialectic.Douglas C. Macintosh -1929 -Journal of Philosophy 26 (9):225-233.
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  50
    Expressions and the Stress Factor.Douglas C. Kurjian -1983 -Thought: Fordham University Quarterly 58 (3):345-357.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  1
    Scotus's Doctrine of Intuitive Cognition.Douglas C. Langston -1993 -Synthèse: An International Journal for Epistemology, Methodology and Philosophy of Science 96 (1):3-24.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. T. Ribot, La Psychologie des Sentiments.C.Douglas -1897 -Mind 6:107.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  747
    Disembodied existence, physicalism and the mind-body problem.Douglas C. Long -1977 -Philosophical Studies 31 (May):307-316.
    The idea that we may continue to exist in a bodiless condition after our death has long played an important role in beliefs about immortality, ultimate rewards and punishments, the transmigration of souls, and the like. There has also been long and heated disagreement about whether the idea of disembodied existence even makes sense, let alone whether anybody can or does survive dissolution of his material form. It may seem doubtful that anything new could be added to the debate at (...) this late date, but I hope to show that this is not so. I will explore the problem of disembodiment from a somewhat different direction than has been tried before, one that leads to what seem to me more interesting and more definite conclusions about its unintelligibility. Furthermore, the approach I will be taking puts both the traditional mind-body problem and the competing claims of dualism and physicalism in a fresh light that can help us to understand better the nature of our embodied existence. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  437
    Why Machines Can Neither Think nor Feel.Douglas C. Long -1994 - In Paul Ziff & Dale Jamieson,Language, mind, and art: essays in appreciation and analysis in honor of Paul Ziff. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    Over three decades ago, in a brief but provocative essay, Paul Ziff argued for the thesis that robots cannot have feelings because they are "mechanisms, not organisms, not living creatures. There could be a broken-down robot but not a dead one. Only living creatures can literally have feelings."[i] Since machines are not living things they cannot have feelings. In the first half of my paper I review Ziff's arguments against the idea that robots could be conscious, especially his appeal to (...) our linguistic usage. In the second half of the essay I try to provide a deeper ontological understanding of why we ought not attribute minds to nonliving artifacts. I argue that inanimate mechanisms are incapable of genuinely active and purposive behavior. They are importantly different in kind from living human beings and animals. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  398
    (1 other version)Agents, mechanisms, and other minds.Douglas C. Long -1979 - InAgents, Mechanisms, and Other Minds. Dordrecht, Holland: Reidel. pp. 129--148.
    One of the goals of physiologists who study the detailed physical, chemical,and neurological mechanisms operating within the human body is to understand the intricate causal processes which underlie human abilities and activities. It is doubtless premature to predict that they will eventually be able to explain the behaviour of a particular human being as we might now explain the behaviour of a pendulum clock or even the invisible changes occurring within the hardware of a modern electronic computer. Nonetheless, it seems (...) fair to say that hovering in the background of investigations into human physiology is the promise or threat, depending upon how one looks at the matter that human beings are complete physical-chemical systems and that all events taking place within their bodies and all movements of their bodies could be accounted for by physical causes if we but knew enough. I am not concerned at the moment with whether or not this ’mechanistic’ hypothesis is true, assuming that it is clear enough to be intelligible, nor with whether or not we could ever know that it is true. I wish to consider the somewhat more accessible yet equally important question whether our coming to believe that the hypothesis is true would warrant our relinquishing our conception of ourselves as beings who are capable of acting for reasons to achieve ends of our own choosing. I use the word ’warrant’ to indicate that I will not be discussing the possibility that believing the mechanistic hypothesis might lead us, as a matter of psychological fact, to think of human beings as mere automata, as objects whose movements are to be explained only by causes rather than by reasons, as are the actions of a personal subject. I intend to consider only whether the acceptance of mechanism would in fact justify such a change in conception. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  80
    The Metaphysics of Mind, by Michael Tye. [REVIEW]Douglas C. Long -1991 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (4):959-961.
  36. A. Seth, Man's Place in the Cosmos and other Essays. [REVIEW]C.Douglas -1898 -Mind 7:92.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  23
    E. Maynard Adams, 1919-2003.Douglas C. Long -2004 -Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 77 (5):159 - 160.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  599
    The bodies of persons.Douglas C. Long -1974 -Journal of Philosophy 71 (10):291-301.
    Much mischief concerning the concept of a human body is generated by the failure of philosophers to distinguish various important senses of the term 'body.' I discuss three of those senses and illustrate the issues they can generate by discussing the concept of a Lockean exchange of bodies as well as the brain-body switch.
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  643
    Second thoughts: A reply to mr. Ginnane.Douglas C. Long -1961 -Mind 70 (279):405-411.
    In his article "Thoughts" (MIND, July 1960) William Ginnane argues that "thought is pure intentionality," and that our thoughts are not embodied essentially in the mental imagery and other elements of phenomenology that cross our minds along with the thoughts. Such images merely illustrate out thoughts. In my discussion I resist this claim pointing out that our thoughts are often embodied in events that can be described in pheno¬menological terms, especially when our reports of our thinking are introduced by the (...) colorful phrases that Ginnane himself suggests, such as "It crossed my mind that.." or "It occurred to me that…" It is true that we also have a mode of speech in which we report what we have thought in well-formed sentences. Sometimes the very utterance of such sentences is what we call thinking out loud. More often than not, however, our thoughts are fragmentary enough so that if someone asks us what we were thinking, we must stop and rather carefully formulate the expression of those thoughts. In this case there has been nothing running through our minds which can be phenomenologically described as complete sentences, yet in formu¬lating the significance of what has been passing through our minds we do use complete sentences. It is true that one of the confusions we have been bothered by in the past is the idea that in describing the contents of our minds we must somehow find there a proto-type of the report we give in propositional form. The philosopher's phrase "entertaining a proposition" only encour¬ages this confusion, as it looks like an attempt to describe one's mental history phenomenologically. Nevertheless, the successive phenomenological events that occur in our minds often seem to be not merely illustrations accompanying our thoughts, but to embody what we say occurred to us. -/- . (shrink)
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  23
    Hume. [REVIEW]Douglas C. Long -1982 -Noûs 16 (3):474-477.
  41.  440
    One more foiled defense of skepticism.Douglas C. Long -1994 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (2):373-375.
    This paper is a response to Anthony Brueckner's critique of my essay "The Self-Defeating Character of Skepticism," which appeared in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research in 1992. In this reply I contend that the three main avenues by which one might plausibly account for one's self-awareness are unavailable to an individual who is restricted to the skeptic's epistemic ground rules. First, all-encompassing doubt about the world cancels our "external" epistemic access via perception to ourselves as material individuals in the world. Second, (...) one does not have direct cpistemic access to one's substantial self through introspection, since the self as such is not a proper object of inner awareness. Third, we cannot claim, as Descartes did, that we have indirect epistemic access to the substantial self by inference from the occurrence of experiences.The summary conclusion for which I argue is that, if we are to account for our self-knowledge, we cannot adopt the purely subjective epistemological stance that is at the heart of global skepticism. (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  43
    Through Deaf Eyes: A Photographic History of an American Community.Douglas C. Baynton,Jack R. Gannon &Jean Lindquist Bergey -2007 - Gallaudet University Press.
    Photographs and interviews document the history of deaf culture in the United States.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  718
    Why Life is Necessary for Mind: The Significance of Animate Behavior.Douglas C. Long -2010 - In James O'Shea Eric Rubenstein,Self, Language, and World:Problems from Kant, Sellars, and Rosenberg. Ridgeview Publishing Co. pp. 61-88.
    I defend the thesis that psychological states can be literally ascribed only to living creatures and not to nonliving machines, such as sophisticated robots. Defenders of machine consciousness do not sufficiently appreciate the importance of the biological nature of a subject for the psychological significance of its behavior. Simulations of a computer-controlled, nonliving autonomous robot cannot carry the same psychological meaning as animate behavior. Being a living creature is an essential link between genuinely expressive behavior and justified psychological ascriptions.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  16
    Immediacy and Mediation in Aquinas: “In I Sent.,” Q. 1, A. 5.Douglas C. Hall -1989 -The Thomist 53 (1):31-55.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:IMMEDIACY AND MEDIATION IN AQUINAS: Introduction "IN I SENT.," Q. 1, A. 5DOUGLAS c. HALI, Louvain Universtiy Belgium ] ] HE PURPOSE of the present essay is to provide an nalysis of the dialectically related notions of " immediacy " and "med:ia1tion" in Question I, Art~cle 5 of Aquinas' Commentary on the Sentences. "Immediacy" here refers to the non-mediated " light of inspiration " which Aquinas proposes (...) as a principle for theology; while " mediation " refers to the problem of interpretation via,sensible signs in an historical community. It is proposed that there are dialectical tensions unresolved by Aquinas, and usually overlooked by commentators and interpreters.1 1 The most extensive analysis published to date of the theological methodology of Aquinas in this Commentary is by M. Corbin, Le chemin de la theologie chez Thomas d'Aquin (Paris: Beauchesne, 1974). For his analysis of the text in question see pp. 273-290. The present essay seeks precisely to be even more "hegelian" and more "barthian" than Corbin, and to provide some documentation for the validity of,such an interpretation of Aquinas. For a further methodological discussion, see my "Participated Trinitarian Relations : Dialectics of Method, Understanding, and Mystery in the Theology of Thomas Aquinas" (Leuven: S.T.D. dissertation, the Faculty of Theology, 1987). For basic points in the literature see P. Mandonnet, "Chronologie sommaire de la vie et des ecrits de saint Thomas," Revue des sciences philosophiques et theologiques 9 (1920), 142·152; G. Rossi, "L'autografo di S. Tommaso del Commento al III libro delle Sentenze," Divus Thomas Oommentarium de philosophia et theologia 35 (1932), 532-585; A. Hayen, "S. Thomas a-t-il edite deux fois son Commentaire sure le livre des Sentences," Recherches de theologie ancienne et medievale 9 (1937), 219-236. See also the review of this by A. Donclaine, in Bulletin thomiste 6 (1940), 100-108. P. Vanier, "Theologie trinitaire chez S. Thomas d'Aquin. Evolution du concept d'action notionelle," Publications de l'Institut d'etudes medievales 13 (1953), p. 124. 31DOUGLAS C. BALL The "Prologue" to the Commentary The " Prologue " of Aquinas' Commentary consists of two parts, as did that of Albert the Great, and as was the custom of the time. The first part takes its point of departure from a biblical text, which is then interpreted in accord with the na- >bure of theology and the project of commentary on the four hooks of the Sentences. The theme of Aquinas' biblical meditation is not scientia hut sapientia. The second part of Aquinas' "Pmlogue " consists, as did Albert's, of a question on the status and method of theology. This Question 1 is of particular importance in that it clearly states that sacred doctrine is not principally to he considered soientia. After the biblical reflection-mediation, Aquinas presents an introductory question on the status and method of sacra doctrina in a more "scholastic" manner, specifying five articles that will be addressed: 1) its necessity; 9l) supposing that it exists, whether it is one or many; 3) if it is one, whether it is practical or speculative, and if it is speculative, whether it is wisdom, science, or understanding; 4) its subject; 5) its mode.2 For a critique of this position see the review of Vanier by J. Hamer in Bulletin thomiste 9 (1954-1956), 596-601. See also E. Gilson, The Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas.Aquinas (New York, 1956); M. D. Chenu, Toward Understanding St. Thomas (Chicago: Henry Regnery Company, 1964); J. Weisheipl, "The Meaning of 'Sacra Doctrina'," The Thomist 38 (1974), 64-67; B. Mondin, St. Thomas.Aquinas' Philosophy in the Oommentary to the Sentences (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1975). Good arguments on the dating and circumstances of the work are to be found in J. Weishepil, Friar Thomas d'.A.quino: His Life, Thought, and Work (Garden City: Doubleday, 1974). 2Aquinas, Soriptum Super Libros Sententiarum, vol. 1, ed. Mandonnet (Paris: Lethielleux, 1929), q. 1 (p. 6). [It should be noted that there is as yet no critical edition of this work. All references here will be to this edition, which at least provides a basic text, which is fundamentally a reprint of the Vives edition, and thus differs at times... (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  95
    Is modern information technology enabling the evolution of a more direct democracy?Douglas C. Walton -2007 -World Futures 63 (5 & 6):365 – 385.
    Many futurists, technologists, and democratic theorists have asserted the Internet and modern information technology are enabling the realization of an authentic direct democracy, or at least a more participatory democracy. Conversely, critics contend advances in technology are only automating the existing democracy. This article explores the potential of modern information technology to enable the emergence of a more participatory democratic system. In particular, the key foundations of modern direct democracy are analyzed with respect to promising technological developments.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  369
    Avowals and first-person privilege.Dorit Bar-on &Douglas C. Long -2001 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (2):311-35.
    When people avow their present feelings, sensations, thoughts, etc., they enjoy what may be called “first-person privilege.” If I now said: “I have a headache,” or “I’m thinking about Venice,” I would be taken at my word: I would normally not be challenged. According to one prominent approach, this privilege is due to a special epistemic access we have to our own present states of mind. On an alternative, deflationary approach the privilege merely reflects a socio-linguistic convention governing avowals. We (...) reject both approaches. On our proposed account, a full explanation of the privilege must recognize avowals as expressive performances, which can be taken to reveal directly the subject’s present mental condition. We are able to improve on special access accounts and deflationary accounts, as well as familiar expressive accounts, by explaining both the asymmetries and the continuities between avowals and other pronouncements, and by locating a genuine though non-epistemic source for first-person privilege. (shrink)
    Direct download(9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  47.  69
    Moral Philosophy on the Threshold of Modernity (review).Douglas C. Langston -2006 -Journal of the History of Philosophy 44 (3):475-476.
    Douglas C. Langston - Moral Philosophy on the Threshold of Modernity - Journal of the History of Philosophy 44:3 Journal of the History of Philosophy 44.3 475-476 Jill Kraye and Risto Saarinen, editors. Moral Philosophy on the Threshold of Modernity. New Synthese Historical Library, 57. Dordrecht: Springer, 2005. Pp. vi + 340. Cloth, e139.10. This is a collection of fifteen essays from a 2001 workshop, "Late Medieval and Early Modern Ethics and Politics," funded by the European Science Foundation as (...) part of a network of meetings on Early Modern Thought. The editors intend the volume to reflect current historical and philosophical scholarship about the moral thought of the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries. It is arranged into three sections, reflecting three different themes: 1... (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  26
    Ethics in Pharmacy Practice: A Practical Guide.Dennis M. Sullivan,Douglas C. Anderson &Justin W. Cole -2021 - Springer Verlag.
    This textbook offers a unique and accessible approach to ethical decision-making for practicing pharmacists and student pharmacists. Unlike other texts, it gives clear guidance based on the fundamental principles of moral philosophy, explaining them in simple language and illustrating them with abundant clinical examples and case studies. The strength of this text is in its emphasis on normative ethics and critical thinking, and that there is truly a best answer in the vast majority of cases, no matter how complex. The (...) authors place high trust in a pharmacist’s moral judgment. This teaches the reader how to think, based on ethical principles, not necessarily what to think. This means navigating between the two extremes of overly theoretical and excessively prescriptive. The cogent framework given in this text uses the language of competing duties, identifying the moral principles at stake that create duties for the pharmacist. This is the balancing act of normative ethics, and of deciding which duties should prevail in a given clinical situation. This work presents a clear-cut pathway for resolving ethical dilemmas encountered by pharmacists, based on foundational principles and critical thinking. Presents a clear-cut pathway for resolving the ethical dilemmas encountered by pharmacists, based on foundational principles and critical thinking. Jon E. Sprague, RPh, PhD, Director of Science and Research for the Ohio Attorney General. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  33
    Reducing Enterprise Product Line Architecture Deployment and Testing Costs via Model-Driven Deployment, Configuration, and Testing.Jules White &Douglas C. Schmidt -unknown
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  78
    Special Supplement: Empirical Research on Informed Consent: An Annotated Bibliography.Jeremy Sugarman,Douglas C. McCrory,Donald Powell,Alex Krasny,Betsy Adams,Eric Ball &Cynthia Cassell -1999 -Hastings Center Report 29 (1):S1.
1 — 50 / 961
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp