Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs
Order:

1 filter applied
Disambiguations
Douglas B. Rasmussen [52]Douglas Bruce Rasmussen [1]
  1.  23
    Norms of Liberty: A Perfectionist Basis for Non-Perfectionist Politics.Douglas B. Rasmussen &Douglas J. Den Uyl -2005 - Pennsylvania State University Press.
    How can we establish a political/legal order that in principle does not require the human flourishing of any person or group to be given structured preference over that of any other? Addressing this question as the central problem of political philosophy,_ Norms of Liberty_ offers a new conceptual foundation for political liberalism that takes protecting liberty, understood in terms of individual negative rights, as the primary aim of the political/legal order. Rasmussen and Den Uyl argue for construing individual rights as (...) metanormative principles, directly tied to politics, that are used to establish the political/ legal conditions under which full moral conduct can take place. These they distinguish from normative principles, used to provide guidance for moral conduct within the ambit of normative ethics. This crucial distinction allows them to develop liberalism as a metanormative theory, not a guide for moral conduct. The moral universe need not be minimized or morality grounded in sentiment or contracts to support liberalism, they show. Rather, liberalism can be supported, and many of its internal tensions avoided, with an ethical framework of Aristotelian inspiration—one that understands human flourishing to be an objective, inclusive, individualized, agent-relative, social, and self-directed activity. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  2.  23
    Liberty and Nature: An Aristotelian Defense of Liberal Order.Douglas B. Rasmussen &Douglas J. Den Uyl -1991 - Open Court Publishing Company.
    Aristotle's way of thinking has normally been understood as hostile to any liberal, pluralistic, or commercial society. In Liberal Nature, Rasmussen and Den Uyl set out to show that the Aristotelian approach to ethics supports the natural rights which form the most secure basis for liberal principles. The authors lay the foundations for their thesis by rebutting the most prominent arguments against the Aristotelian approach; they then offer a new interpretation for Aristotelian ethics as a natural-end ethics in which human (...) flourishing is the ultimate moral standard. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  3.  203
    Human Flourishing and the Appeal to Human Nature*: DOUGLAS B. RASMUSSEN.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1999 -Social Philosophy and Policy 16 (1):1-43.
    If “perfectionism” in ethics refers to those normative theories that treat the fulfillment or realization of human nature as central to an account of both goodness and moral obligation, in what sense is “human flourishing” a perfectionist notion? How much of what we take “human flourishing” to signify is the result of our understanding of human nature? Is the content of this concept simply read off an examination of our nature? Is there no place for diversity and individuality? Is the (...) belief that the content of such a normative concept can be determined by an appeal to human nature merely the result of epistemological naiveté? What is the exact character of the connection between human flourishing and human nature? These questions are the ultimate concern of this essay, but to appreciate the answers that will be offered it is necessary to understand what is meant by “human flourishing.” “Human flourishing” is a relatively recent term in ethics. It seems to have developed in the last two decades because the traditional translation of the Greek term eudaimonia as “happiness” failed to communicate clearly that eudaimonia was an objective good, not merely a subjective good. (shrink)
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  4.  18
    The Perfectionist Turn: From Metanorms to Metaethics.Douglas J. Den Uyl &Douglas B. Rasmussen -2016 - Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Edited by Douglas B. Rasmussen.
    Contemporary political philosophy - especially in the works of Martha Nussbaum, John Rawls and Amartya Sen - has assumed that it can separate itself off from other philosophical positions and frameworks. In this book, Den Uyl and Rasmussen challenge this trend by moving from the liberalism they advocate in their earlier work to what they call 'individualistic perfectionism' in ethics. They continue to challenge the assumption that a neo-Aristotelian ethical framework cannot support a liberal, non-perfectionist political theory by filling in (...) the nature of the perfectionist ethical approach utilised in their previous political theorising. By developing the central features and principles of individualistic perfectionism they show that it is a major and powerful alternative to much contemporary ethical thinking - particularly to constructivism - and that it is capable of overcoming standard objections to perfectionism. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5.  58
    The Significance for Cognitive Realism of the Thought of John Poinsot.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1994 -American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 68 (3):409-424.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  6. A groundwork for rights: Man's natural end.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1980 -Journal of Libertarian Studies 4 (1):65-76.
  7.  120
    Quine and Aristotelian Essentialism.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1984 -New Scholasticism 58 (3):316-335.
  8.  40
    Rand on Obligation and Value.Douglas B. Rasmussen -2002 -Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 4 (1):69 - 86.
    Douglas B. Rasmussen examines, in this revised and extended version of his 1990 address to the Ayn Rand Society, whether Rand's ethics are best interpreted as dependent on a "pre-moral" choice. He argues that such an interpretation undercuts Rand's claim to provide a rational foundation for ethics. He suggests an alternative, neo-Aristotelian interpretation of Rand's ethics, which treats "man's survival qua man" as the telos of human choice and takes the obligation to achieve this ultimate end as the result of (...) its being the good for human beings. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  33
    Rejoinder to Tibor R. Machan, "Rand and Choice" (Spring 2006): Regarding Choice and the Foundation of Morality: Reflections on Rand's Ethics.Douglas B. Rasmussen -2006 -Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 7 (2):309 - 328.
    This essay examines the relationship between human choice and Rand's ethical standard for moral goodness and obligation. It shows that the neo-Aristotclian interpretation of Rand's ethics—an interpretation that does not accept the doctrine of "premoral choice" but instead claims that flourishing as a rational animal is the telos of human life and choice—is crucial to the viability of her ethical theory. The defenders of premoral choice confuse the conceptual order with the real and, despite their intentions, make Rand's ethics into (...) a voluntarist ethics, that is, an ethics in which reason is subordinate to will. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  26
    Liberty for the 21st Century: Contemporary Libertarian Thought.Tibor R. Machan &Douglas B. Rasmussen -1995 - Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    Fifteen distinguished contributors free present up-to-date arguments for the libertarian alternative. Part One introduces libertarianism and outlines some approaches by which it might be justified. Part Two addresses how a society that embraces libertarian principles might deal with various social problems, especially those that seem to require government intervention. Part Three responds to criticisms of libertarianism from other political perspectives and presents a libertarian critique of those viewpoints. Contributors: N. Scott Arnold; James E. Chesher; Mike Gemmell; John Hospers; Gregory R. (...) Johnson; Loren E. Lomasky; Tibor R. Machan; Eric Mack; Jan Narveson; Douglas B. Rasmussen; Daniel Shapiro; Aeon Skoble; Mark Thornton; Douglas J. Den Uyl; Steven Yates. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11.  112
    The Myth of Atomism.Douglas J. Den Uyl &Douglas B. Rasmussen -2006 -Review of Metaphysics 59 (4):841-868.
    CHARLES TAYLOR, IN TWO IMPORTANT ESSAYS, offers both a refutation of what appears to be the foundations of liberalism as well as an alternative “third way” to the liberal-communitarian debate. In this paper we are broadly interested in the role of community within a liberal framework, and for that reason the Taylor essays are a useful way to begin such an exploration. There is, we believe, much in Taylor with which to agree. If liberalism somehow fails to accommodate any meaningful (...) conception of community or somehow manages to undermine the possibility of community, that would be a serious strike against it. “Atomism” is one of those concepts inherently linked by thinkers such as Taylor to liberalism. It is the sort of concept meant to evoke, if not describe, a perspective on human association that is at least problematic to community-building, if not directly undermining it. Taylor’s first essay with the title of “Atomism” explores this idea and levels the charge of anticommunity against liberalism. The second essay, “Cross Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate,” builds upon that charge but seeks to moderate the apparent antiliberal stance of the first. Our position is that liberalism is not opposed to community and that “atomism” when applied to liberalism is something of a myth — a caricature rather than an integral part of liberalism. Our specific theses will be the following: “atomism” as used by Taylor is a confused tool and one whose uses for understanding liberalism are extremely limited, if applicable at all; the applicability of “atomism” is ironically more consistent with certain forms of collectivism than with liberalism; and Taylor’s own proposed way of navigating the difference between liberalism and communitarianism is in the end a form of communitarianism and not an alternative at all. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  23
    On Grounding Ethical Values in the Human Life Form.Douglas B. Rasmussen &Douglas J. Den Uyl -2023 -Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 23 (1-2):328-340.
    Benjamin Lipscomb (The Women Are Up to Something) and Clare Mac Cumhaill and Rachel Wiseman (Metaphysical Animals) have written books discussing the same four women philosophers—Elizabeth Anscombe, Philippa Foot, Mary Midgley, and Iris Murdoch—and their rise to prominence in the almost exclusively male-dominated academies of Oxford and Cambridge universities. This review focuses on these philosophers’ intellectual contributions, with special attention given to the Aristotelian character of their views in the face of an opposing philosophical regimen. We conclude with a brief (...) reflection on Ayn Rand’s moral philosophy in light of the contributions made by these four women philosophers. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  68
    The Open-Question Argument and the Issue of Conceivability.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1982 -Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 56:162.
  14.  95
    (1 other version)The Importance of Metaphysical Realism for Ethical Knowledge.Douglas B. Rasmussen -2008 -Social Philosophy and Policy 25 (1):56-99.
    In this essay, I consider whether the alleged demise of metaphysical realism does actually provide a better way for defending the cognitive status of ethical judgments. I argue that the rejection of a realist ontology and epistemology does not help to establish the claim that ethical knowledge is possible. More specifically, I argue that Hilary Putnam's argument does not succeed in making a case for ethical knowledge. In fact, his account of the procedures by which our valuations are warranted—the criteria (...) of idealized inquiry—ultimately begs the question in a number of crucial ways. Moreover, it prejudices the moral and political discussion in certain ideological respects. Finally, though Putnam has apparently modified to some extent his approach to the issue of realism in recent years, I will point out that these modifications are not fundamental and do not help to advance the case for ethical knowledge. I note also that Martha C. Nussbaum's appeal to Putnam’s argument actually works against her attempt to make a case for an Aristotelian conception of human flourishing. Ultimately, I conclude that metaphysical realism is vital for ethical knowledge. (shrink)
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  43
    The Right to Liberty in a Good Society.Randy E. Barnett &Douglas B. Rasmussen -unknown
    We have been asked to consider how a "Constitution of Civic Virtue" might contribute to a "good society." To answer this question, we need to have some idea of what a good society might be, and we need to be able to articulate that idea. Certainly, we think we know a good movie when we see it, a good book when we read it, a good argument when we hear it, and a good idea when we have one, but we (...) are not sure we have a handle on what a good society is. Even what we think we know about good books, movies, arguments, and ideas gives us pause. For we are not sure we can always explain why we think a particular movie is good or a book is bad. And even when we can explain it, we find that many people disagree with us about such matters. Indeed, we, at times, even disagree with each other. By this we do not mean to suggest any skepticism about there being such a thing as a good book, a good film, a good wine, a good car, or even a good person. If there is one thing we think we know in this world, it is that there are good persons-quite amazingly good actually. Nor do we mean to deny that there may be such a thing as a good society, though we are not so confident about this. A lot depends on what is meant by those words. Having said this, we will set our skepticism aside and now offer a conception of a good society; but we no more expect everyone to agree with this conception then we expect them to agree with one of us that "The Tao of Steve" was a really good movie. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  93
    Ethical individualism, natural law, and the primacy of natural rights.Douglas J. Den Uyl &Douglas B. Rasmussen -2001 -Social Philosophy and Policy 18 (1):34-69.
    Whether or not Strauss's observation is historically accurate, it does suggest two sets of questions for philosophical examination. (1) Is Strauss correct to view natural duties and natural rights as the same type of ethical concept? Do they serve the same function? Do they work on the same level, and are they necessarily in competition with each other? (2) Does saying that the individual human being is the center of the moral world require that one reject the idea of a (...) human end, or telos? Does accepting the ethical centrality of a human telos require that one reject ethical individualism? Are they mutually exclusive?Footnotes* For criticism, we are grateful to the other contributors to this volume and to its editors, as well as Paul Gaffney. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  23
    Retreat from Liberalism: Human Capabilities and Public Reasoning.Douglas J. Den Uyl &Douglas B. Rasmussen -2009 -Journal des Economistes Et des Etudes Humaines 15 (1).
    Central to Amartya Sen's understanding and defense of political orders that promote equality is his appeal to human capabilities. However, he fails to provide a basis for their selection, weighting, and value. Moreover, the account of ethical reasoning by which he does attempt to respond to basic challenges is highly problematic. It not only conflicts with a view of human flourishing that is individualized, agent-relative, and self-directed but also offers neither justification for nor principled limitation of state imposed solutions.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  97
    The Perfectionist Turn.Douglas J. Den Uyl &Douglas B. Rasmussen -2013 -Social Philosophy and Policy 30 (1-2):69-94.
    This essay asks whether what is good for someone is distinct from her self-perfection, and whether it makes sense to understand either her good or her self-perfection in terms of the other. The essay adopts a traditional naturalistic understanding of perfection. It argues, however, that the conception of human nature that underlies the perfectionist view must be more individualistic than it is often taken to be. It goes on to distinguish individuative from generic features of human nature; because the account (...) includes both types of characteristics, the concluding vision of human nature, and hence human perfection, is deeply individualized. What is good for an individual is linked to the exercise of her nature rather than to desires individuals simply happen to have. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. A Critique of Rawls' "Theory of Justice".Douglas B. Rasmussen -1974 -Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 55 (3):303.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  48
    Commentary on Sterba.Douglas B. Rasmussen &Douglas J. Den Uyl -2011 -Journal of Social Philosophy 42 (4):416-427.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  48
    Deely, Wittgenstein, and Mental Events.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1980 -New Scholasticism 54 (1):60-67.
  22.  23
    Grounding Necessary Truth in the Nature of Things: A Redux.Douglas B. Rasmussen -2014 - In Paolo C. Biondi & Louis F. Groarke,Shifting the Paradigm: Alternative Perspectives on Induction. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 323-358.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  40
    In Memoriam: Henry Babcock Veatch (1911-1999).Douglas B. Rasmussen -1999 -Review of Metaphysics 53 (1):271 - 272.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  32
    Individual rights and human flourishing.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1989 -Public Affairs Quarterly 3 (1):89-103.
  25.  52
    Liberalism and Natural End Ethics.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1990 -American Philosophical Quarterly 27 (2):153 - 161.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  44
    Liberalism and the Choice of Liberties.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1985 -Bowling Green Studies in Applied Philosophy 7:1-25.
  27.  1
    Liberalism, Human Good, and The Threat of Postliberalism.Douglas B. Rasmussen &Douglas J. Den Uyl -forthcoming -Journal des Economistes Et des Etudes Humaines.
    jonathan Rauch claims that the aim of liberalism is not to provide for the moral needs of persons but instead provide the space for their pursuit of meaning. His claim could, however, be construed as rejecting the possibility of an objective standard for human good and indeed moral knowledge. Such a construal would make liberalism vulnerable to the postliberal charge that it is, as Alasdair MacIntyre has warned, the harbinger of nihilism. This essay counters this postliberal charge by providing an (...) account of human good that is objective and yet compatible with liberty being the paramount political value. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  48
    Liberalism in Retreat.Douglas B. Rasmussen -2009 -Review of Metaphysics 62 (4):875-908.
    This essay presents a brief summary of the Sen/Nussbaum conception of liberalism, offers some main points of criticism, and contrasts their conception of human flourishing and politics with an alternative one. The ultimate aim will be to show that they do not advance the cause of liberalism properly understood but actually retreat from it. The “human capabilities argument,” “public reasoning,” “internalist essentialism,” and other key concepts are discussed. The paper concludes that Sen and Nussbaum fail to adequately defend the premises (...) of the human capabilities argument and that their argument invites a retreat from liberalism. Moreover, on their theory individuals have no basis upon which to erect borders for their resources or themselves and to say to any and all that some areas are off limits no matter who may benefit. Rather, there is only the relentless and enforced pursuit of capabilities. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29. Logical Possibility: An Aristotelian Essentialist Critique.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1983 -The Thomist 47 (4):515.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  43
    Logical Possibility, Iron Bars, and Necessary Truth.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1977 -New Scholasticism 51 (1):117-122.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. Mangerial ethics.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1988 - In Tibor R. Machan,Commerce and morality. Totowa, N.J.: Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 23.
  32.  40
    Natural Law and Natural Rights: Bastiat Vindicated.Douglas B. Rasmussen -2001 -Journal des Economistes Et des Etudes Humaines 11 (2).
    Bastiat claims that the individual rights to life, liberty, and property are natural rights. Further, he claims that these natural rights are a matter of natural law and are not mere conventions. However, he never offers a detailed account of the connection between natural law and natural rights. By outlining a neo-Aristotelian theory of natural law that consists of two poles—an individualized vision of human flourishing and a conception of individual rights as metanormative principles—it is argued that Bastiat’s core insight (...) is correct. Individual rights are the proper political expression of a natural law approach to ethics. They determine the ultimate purpose of human law.Bastiat affirme que les droits individuels à la vie, à la liberté et à la propriété sont des droits naturels. De plus, il envisage ces droits naturels comme relevant du Droit Naturel plutôt qu’étant de simples conventions. Cependant, il n’offre nulle part une explication détaillée des liens entre le Droit Naturel et les droits naturels. En mettant en avant une théorie néo-aristotélicienne du Droit Naturel composée de deux pôles — une version individualisée de l’épanouissement humain et une conception des droits individuels en tant que principes métanormatifs — cet article soutient que l’idée centrale de Bastiat est juste. Les droits individuels sont l’expression politique adéquate d’une approche de l’éthique en termes de Droit Naturel. Ils déterminent la finalité ultime de la loi humaine. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Norms of liberty : Challenges and prospects.Douglas B. Rasmussen &Douglas J. Den Uyl -2008 - In Aeon J. Skoble,Reading Rasmussen and Den Uyl: Critical Essays on Norms of Liberty. Lexington Books.
  34. Necessary Truth, the Game Analogy, and the Meaning-is-Truth Thesis.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1982 -The Thomist 46 (3):423.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  26
    Perfectionism, immanence, and transcendence.Douglas B. Rasmussen &Douglas J. Den Uyl -2012 - In Jonathan A. Jacobs,Reason, Religion, and Natural Law: From Plato to Spinoza. , US: Oxford University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  53
    Political Legitimacy and Discourse Ethics.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1992 -International Philosophical Quarterly 32 (1):17-34.
  37. Rorty and the Nature of Intentionality.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1983 -Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 57:152.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  50
    Realism, Intentionality, and the Nature of Logical Relations.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1992 -Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 66:267-277.
  39.  9
    Reclaiming Liberalism.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1994 -The Thomist 58 (1):109-119.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:RECLAIMING LIBERALISM * DOUGLAS B. RASMUSSEN St. John's University Jamaica, New York Through the shift of emphasis from natural duties or obligations to natural rights, the individual, the ego, had become the center and origin of the moral world, since man-as distinguished from man's end-had become that center or origin. -Leo Strauss T:HE CONCEPTION of individuality that lies at the oundation of natural rights classical liberalism has been a (...) arget of criticism for some time. This is not news. What is news and what is becoming more apparent to those who examine the issue is that the alternatives Strauss presents in the above quotation are not mutually exclusive. Indeed, as I and my colleague, Douglas J. Den Uyl, have recently observed: Making the individual the moral center of the universe does not require that one accept nominalism, mechanism, or hedonism, nor does accepting essentialism, teleology, and eudaimonism... require rejecting individualism. It is possible for the fulfillment of the individual to be interpreted in terms of the requirements for human wellbeing. There can be a view of the ego or self that is neither otherwordly nor Hobbesian, but Aristotelian. Further, the achievement of man's natural end need not be interpreted along Platonic lines. There is no such thing as the flourishing of "man." There is only the flourishing of individual men. The human good neither exists apart from the chokes and actions of individual human beings nor independent of the particular " mix " of goods that the individual human being must determine as appropriate for his circumstances. *This essay is based on a paper presented at a meeting of the American Association for the Philosophic Study of Society, American Philosophical Association (Eastern Division) convention, December 29, 1991 in New York City. This meeting was devoted to David L. Norton's book Democracy and Moral Development (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1991). 109 110 DOUGLAS B. RASMUSSEN Strauss's dichotomy betrays a disturbing tendency, often found among proponents of natural right and natural law, to reify the concept " natural end " and make it some good that competes with the good of individual human beings.1 David L. Norton in his recent work, Democracy and Moral Development, has also noted the nonexclusivity of Strauss's alternatives. Conditioned as we are by modernity's conception of the individual, the question of replacing avarice as the thematic motivation in lives of persons is likely to leave us at a loss. What else could possibly serve? The purpose of this book is to propose the eudaimonistic answer, and that answer is love in the meaning of Eros. Thus understood, love is not exclusively or primarily interpersonal; it is first of all the right relationship of each person with himself or herself. The self to which love is in the first instance directed is the ideal self that is aspired to and by which random change is transformed into the directed development we term growth. When the ideal of the individual is rightly chosen, it realizes objective values that subsisted within the individual as innate potentialities, thereby achieving in the individual the self-identity that is termed "integrity" and that constitutes the foundation of other virtues.2 Norton desires to reconceptualize the individualism historically associated with classical liberalism so as both to retain the gains of classical liberalism and to overcome its moral minimalism. According to Norton, the crucial problem with the conception of individuality historically associated with classical liberalism is that it is "non-developmental," or rather, there is only development within a single stage, namely, for self-preservation. There is nothing more. There is no standard of self-perfection by which to distinguish satisfaction of desire from satisfaction of right desire -no way to distinguish Socrates's satisfaction from that of a fool's. Norton thus seeks to replace classical liberalism's non-developmental conception of individuality with a eudaimonistic conception of the individual. 1 Douglas B. Rasmussen and Douglas J. Den Uy!, Liberty and Nature: An Aristotelian Defense of Liberal Order (La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1991), pp. 2 Democracy and Moral Development, p. 40. 92-93. RECLAIMING LIBERALISM 111 By replacing classical liberalism's conception of individuality with a... (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  29
    Reality, Reason, and Rights: Essays in Honor of Tibor R. Machan.Douglas B. Rasmussen,Aeon J. Skoble &Douglas J. Den Uyl (eds.) -2011 - Lexington Books.
    This collection of essays seeks to explore Tibor R. Machan’s philosophical ideas by considering some of the basic issues with which he has been concerned throughout his long and highly productive career.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  68
    Rejoinder to Robert Hartford, "Objectivity and the Proof of Egoism" (Spring 2007): Rand's Metaethics.Douglas B. Rasmussen -2007 -Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 8 (2):307 - 316.
    In response to Robert Hartford's criticisms of his Spring 2006 Journal of Ayn Rand Studies essay, "Regarding Choice and the Foundations of Morality," Rasmussen argues against "the official" interpretation of Rand's ethics as resting on a basic "choice to live." Drawing from his work with Douglas Den Uyl, Rasmussen argues that Rand's metaethics is best understood in "biocentric," neo-Aristotelian terms: that human choice does not set the context in which it operates and that "man's life qua man" is the natural (...) end of human life. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  13
    Rorty, Wittgenstein, and the Nature of Intentionality.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1988 -Philosophie Et Culture: Actes du XVIIe Congrès Mondial de Philosophie 3:47-51.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  57
    Rorty, Wittgenstein, and the Nature of Intentionality.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1983 -Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 57:152-162.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  47
    Two Dogmas of Egalitarianism.Douglas B. Rasmussen &Douglas J. Den Uyl -2020 -Journal des Economistes Et des Etudes Humaines 26 (1).
    It is more than clear that in our previous works—Norms of Liberty and The Perfectionist Turn—we are opposing what is generally understood as egalitarianism in political philosophy. Our purpose here is to clarify our opposition by showing that our rejection of egalitarianism cannot be successfully accused of being inconsistent with morality itself. We believe that discussing what we call “two dogmas of egalitarianism” will go some distance in accomplishing that end. These “dogmas” can be stated as follows: (1) The burden (...) of proof for any deviation from equality in ethics rests upon the advocate of inequality; and (2) One's position on the natural equality (or inequality) of human beings requires a similar position in one’s ethical conclusions. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  35
    The Role and Responsibility of the Moral Philosopher.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1982 -Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 56:162-172.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  37
    Wittgenstein and the Search for Meanings.Douglas B. Rasmussen -1982 -Semiotics:577-590.
  47.  91
    Reply to Peter E. Vedder, "Self-Directedness and the Human Good" (Fall 2007): Defending Norms of Liberty.Douglas J. Den Uyl &Douglas B. Rasmussen -2008 -Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 10 (1):235 - 238.
    This essay is a response to Peter E. Vedder's Fall 2007 review of the authors' book, Norms of Liberty: A Perfectionist Basis for Non-Perfectionist Politics. Vedder argues that the authors 1) have a Kantian notion of self-directedness, and 2) are inconsistent in the application of their philosophical anthropology to their view of political liberty. In denying both claims, the authors assert that Vedder both fails to define certain terms and holds them to positions they do not accept.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  7
    (1 other version)The Philosophic Thought of Ayn Rand.Douglas J. Uyl &Douglas B. Rasmussen (eds.) -1984 - University of Illinois Press.
    "An Illini book." Includes bibliographical references and index.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. Jack W. Meiland and Michael Krausz, eds.: "Relativism". [REVIEW]Douglas B. Rasmussen -1986 -The Thomist 50 (2):309.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  57
    The Catholic Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. [REVIEW]Douglas B. Rasmussen -1994 -American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 68 (4):557-561.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp