Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'Donald C. Baker'

959 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  6
    Geoffrey Chaucer, The Squire's Tale, ed.Donald C.Baker.(A Variorum Edition of the Works of Geoffrey Chaucer, 2/12.) Norman, Okla., and London: University of Oklahoma Press, 1990. Pp. xxvii, 273; color frontispiece, black-and-white plate. $45. [REVIEW]Kenneth Bleeth -1993 -Speculum 68 (3):731-733.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  51
    J. D. A. Ogilvy andDonald C.Baker, Reading Beowulf: An Introduction to the Poem, Its Background, and Its Style. Drawings by KeithBaker. Norman, Okla.: University of Oklahoma Press, 1983. Pp. xvii, 221; black-and-white facsimile frontispiece. $17.95. [REVIEW]Edward B. Irving -1985 -Speculum 60 (2):487.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  71
    Hume’s True Scepticism.Donald C. Ainslie -2015 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    David Hume is famous as a sceptical philosopher but the nature of his scepticism is difficult to pin down. Hume's True Scepticism provides the first sustained interpretation of Part 4 of Book 1 of Hume's Treatise: his deepest engagement with sceptical arguments, in which he notes that, while reason shows that we ought not to believe the verdicts of reason or the senses, we do so nonetheless.Donald C. Ainslie addresses Hume's theory of representation; his criticisms of Locke, Descartes, (...) and other predecessors; his account of the imagination; his understanding of perceptions and sensory belief; and his bundle theory of the mind and his later rejection of it. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  4.  216
    Scepticism About Persons in Book II of Hume's Treatise.Donald C. Ainslie -1999 -Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (3):469-492.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Scepticism About Persons in Book II of Hume’s TreatiseDonald C. AinslieBook ii of Hume’s Treatise—especially its first two Parts on the “indirect passions” of pride, humility, love, and hatred—has mystified many of its interpreters.1 Hume clearly thinks these passions are important: Not only does he devote more space to them than to his treatment of causation, but in the “Abstract” to the Treatise, he tells us that Book II (...) “contains opinions that are altogether as new and extraordinary” (T 659) as those found in Book I. And, he says, these opinions constitute “the foundation” (T 646) for his treatment of morals and politics in Book III.2 The mystery arises, however, because in the actual text of [End Page 469] Book II Hume never spells out what makes his opinions on the passions “new and extraordinary,” nor why they are foundational for his moral theory.Thus some of his interpreters, notably Norman Kemp Smith, conclude that Hume was simply mistaken in his assessment of his treatment of the passions. While his accounts of the will and of motivation (in the early Sections of Part iii of Book II) are significant, Kemp Smith takes the extended analysis of the indirect passions to spring merely from his misplaced enthusiasm for associationist psychology. As such, the philosophical lessons to be learned from the first two Parts of Book II are slim.3 Páll Árdal, in contrast, tries to construct for Hume what he seems to have omitted—a philosophical rationale for his obvious interest in the indirect passions. Árdal starts by drawing attention to the role these passions play in Hume’s moral philosophy, in particular, his repeatedly connecting the indirect passions to the moral sentiments of approval and disapproval. Árdal concludes that Hume means to equate the moral sentiments with particular kinds of indirect passions. The first two Parts of Book II are of interest, on Ardal’s reading, because it is there that he shows us how moral sentimentalism can be founded on something more fully naturalistic than Hutcheson’s somewhat mysterious “moral sense.”4I argue against Árdal’s interpretation in §2. But this reopens the problem of accounting for Hume’s interest in the indirect passions. I offer my view in §§3–5 where, like Árdal, I provide a reconstruction of Hume’s discussion of these passions in order to show how it has an underlying philosophical motivation. My claim is that Hume relies on the indirect passions to explain how we form beliefs about persons as bearers of features that make them into who [End Page 470] they are. It is by feeling an indirect passion towards someone that we think of her as more than accidentally related to some quality, such as her country, her riches, her family, or even her character traits. In support of my interpretation I point to the many parallels Hume draws between the indirect passions and the associative mechanism he offers to explain our forming causal beliefs (I.iii). And I suggest that, just as Hume’s associative explanation of causal beliefs is necessitated by his scepticism about intrinsic “necessary connexions,” so also his associative mechanism for our beliefs about persons—the indirect passions—is necessitated by a certain kind of scepticism about persons. This is not the scepticism about persons that we find in “Of personal identity” (I.iv.6), where Hume argues against the view that our perceptions inhere in a simple soul; it is rather a scepticism about there being intrinsic features of persons that define them as who they are.But, before I explain in more detail what my claim amounts to, it will help to have available a brief description of the mechanism that Hume’s takes to explain the indirect passions.1. THE MECHANISM FOR THE INDIRECT PASSIONSA passion, for Hume, is a simple impression felt in response to various circumstances. Because of their simplicity, we cannot define passions by putting their characteristic feeling into words; instead, Hume thinks, we can only delineate “such circumstances, as attend them” (T 277). Passions are indirect if those circumstances include as an outcome the focusing of attention onto a person... (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  5.  38
    Fifty readings plus: an introduction to philosophy.Donald C. Abel (ed.) -2004 - Boston, Mass.: McGraw-Hill.
    This textbook is a flexible and affordable collection of classic and contemporary primary sources in philosophy. The readings cover seven basic topics of Western Philosophy. The selections are long enough to present a self-contained argument but not so lengthy that students lose track of the main point. Each reading has an outline with study questions, questions for reflection and discussion, and an annotated bibliography. The book includes a glossary and an appendix on logic and argumentation.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Ancient Greek and Roman Rhetoricians: A Biographical Dictionary.Donald C. Bryant,Robert W. Smith,Peter D. Arnott,Erling Holtsmark &Galen O. Rowe -1970 -Philosophy and Rhetoric 3 (1):63-64.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  13
    Sextus, Montaigne, Hume: Pyrrhonizers by Brian C. Ribeiro (review).Donald C. Ainslie -2024 -Journal of the History of Philosophy 62 (3):517-518.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content: Reviewed by Sextus, Montaigne, Hume: Pyrrhonizers by Brian C. RibeiroDonald C. Ainslie Brian C. Ribeiro. Sextus, Montaigne, Hume: Pyrrhonizers. Brill: Leiden, 2021. Pp. 165. Hardback, $154.00. Brian C. Ribeiro’s Sextus, Montaigne, Hume: Pyrrhonizers is a charming and quirky investigation of his three titular skeptics. It is perhaps best understood as a skeptical investigation of skepticism. By that I mean that, like a good Pyrrhonist, Ribeiro explains (...) how things appear to him without claiming to lay down a doctrine or dogma. His topic is how and why skepticism still matters (7). And he suggests that those who are moved by skeptical arguments can learn intellectual modesty from them and thereby achieve a degree of philosophical “calmness of soul” (141).Ribeiro approaches his three figures by taking the cogency of their skeptical arguments for granted. There is little investigation of why these philosophers call various beliefs into question, and his concern is rather what remains once the skeptical doubts are taken on board. Because what he calls “Pyrrhonizing” philosophers reveal that large swaths of our beliefs lack epistemic merit, they also show us how we are not fully rational creatures in our everyday lives. In the case of Sextus, Ribeiro’s focus is on the famous question of whether skeptics can live their skepticism once they have actually suspended all belief. With Sextus, as with Montaigne and Hume, Ribeiro opts for the more radical of the interpretive options; he is not persuaded by Michael Frede’s suggestion that Pyrrhonists restrict their suspension only to abstruse matters, not the everyday (51). But even if we follow the “four-fold way” (20–23) that Sextus offers us as guides for life—the directives of nature, feelings, custom, and expertise—Ribeiro still thinks we will inevitably fall back into belief. He concludes that the original Pyrrhonists should be read aspirationally: insofar as we develop our capacities [End Page 517] to argue on both sides of every question and thus are able to suspend judgment, to that extent we will achieve tranquility. In the case of Montaigne, Ribeiro focuses on his Christian fideism. Once he recognizes the incapacity of reason to resolve intellectual problems, he falls back on faith. And Ribeiro argues that the Catholic flavor of this faith is simply a reflection of Montaigne’s surroundings. In a different community, he could just as easily have embraced a different faith. The heart of the book concerns Hume, whom Ribeiro discusses in three chapters, as opposed to the one each devoted to Sextus and Montaigne. In keeping with his interpretive preferences, Ribeiro’s Hume is a radical skeptic, though he acknowledges the significant yet “utterly perplexing” (95n22) naturalist strains that are also present. Ribeiro takes the resulting tension to be insoluble (98), though I was not convinced. Consider that, in both the Treatise and the Enquiry, Hume uses causal reasoning to investigate causal reasoning. He learns that our ideas are caused by prior impressions; that repeated experience of conjoint events causes us to associate our ideas of similar events; and so on. In the Treatise, he concludes the argument that association is at the root of such causal reasoning by presenting a set of rules, a “logic,” for it. The argument is not as such skeptical, though when Hume “recasts” it in the first Enquiry, he does so in terms of “sceptical doubts” and a “sceptical solution.” In the Treatise, “total” and “extravagant” skepticism come into play only as “systems of philosophy” that Hume uses to shed light on his own core commitments. The problem, I think, is that Ribeiro tends to read Hume a little too literally, as if he is himself falling prey to the skeptical upheaval of the conclusion to the first book of the Treatise, or the final section of the first Enquiry. But I would suggest that Hume is rather deploying the rhetoric of skepticism in these discussions, using it for his ultimate philosophical ends (a point that is especially clear in Ribeiro’s favorite of Hume’s works, the Dialogues). He is showing his reader how his naturalistic philosophical project is itself rooted in human nature, and thus does not yield insight into the intrinsic structure of... (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  41
    Books for review and for Iisting here should be addressed to the Review Editor: Eric Snider, Philosophy, Uni versity of Toledo, Toledo, Ohio 43606, USA.Donald C. Abel,Brenda Almond &Donald Hill -1992 -Teaching Philosophy 15 (2).
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. The Doctrine of Synergism in Gregory of Nyssa's "De Instituto Christiano".Donald C. Abel -1981 -The Thomist 45 (3):430.
  10. John P. Burke, Lawrence Crocker and Lyman Letgers, eds., Marxism and the Good Society Reviewed by.Donald C. Lee -1983 -Philosophy in Review 3 (4):164-166.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  88
    The Limits of Consequentialism.Donald C. Hubin -2008 -Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 10:167-176.
    Modern consequentialism is a very broad theory. Consequentialists can invoke a distribution sensitive theory of value to address the issues of distributive justice that bedeviled utilitarianism. They can attach intrinsic moral value to such acts truth-telling and promise-keeping and, so, acknowledge the essential moral significance of such acts in a way that classical utilitarianism could not. It can appear that there are no limits to consequentialism’s ability to respond to the criticisms against utilitarian theories by embracing a sophisticated theory of (...) value. But there are limits. They are imposed by consequentialism’s commitment to ground considerations of rightness solely on considerations of goodness. Some consequentialists have attempted to incorporate elements of guilt and desert into the theory of value. This can be done, consistent with consequentialist scruples, only if these notions can be analyzed without appeal to deontic concepts such as right and wrong. I analyze the problem consequentialists face and suggest a way incorporate notions of guilt and desert in a theory of value without relying in any fundamental way on concepts of right and wrong action. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Fatherhood.Donald C. Hubin -2013 - In Hugh LaFollette,The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell.
    Surveys theories of paternity/fatherhood.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  27
    Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgement.Donald C. Hubin -1991 -Philosophical Quarterly 41 (163):252-256.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  14.  252
    Hume’s Reflections on the Identity and Simplicity of Mind.Donald C. Ainslie -2001 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (3):557-578.
    The article presents a new interpretation of Hume’s treatment of personal identity, and his later rejection of it in the “Appendix” to the Treatise. Hume’s project, on this interpretation, is to explain beliefs about persons that arise primarily within philosophical projects, not in everyday life. The belief in the identity and simplicity of the mind as a bundle of perceptions is an abstruse belief, not one held by the “vulgar” who rarely turn their minds on themselves so as to think (...) of their perceptions. The author suggests that it is this philosophical observation of the mind that creates the problems that Hume finally acknowledges in the “Appendix.” He is unable to explain why we believe that the perceptions by means of which we observe our minds while philosophizing are themselves part of our minds. This suggestion is then tested against seven criteria that any interpretation of the “Appendix” must meet. (shrink)
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  15.  23
    Clifford Leslie Barrett 1894-1971.Donald C. Williams -1971 -Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 45:209 - 210.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. On the credibility of personalism.Donald C. Williams -1951 -Philosophical Forum 9:23.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Dewey's progressive pedagogy for rhetorical instruction: teaching argument in a nonfoundational framework.Donald C. Jones -2014 - In Brian Jackson & Gregory Clark,Trained capacities: John Dewey, rhetoric, and democratic practice. Columbia, South Carolina: The University of South Carolina Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  71
    On the Elements of Being: II.Donald C. Williams -1953 -Review of Metaphysics 7 (2):171-192.
    If a bit of perceptual behavior is a trope, so is any response to a stimulus, and so is the stimulus, and so therefore, more generally, is every effect and its cause. When we say that the sunlight caused the blackening of the film we assert a connection between two tropes; when we say that Sunlight in general causes Blackening in general, we assert a corresponding relation between the corresponding universals. Causation is often said to relate events, and generally speaking (...) any event is a trope: a smile, a sneeze, a scream, an election, a cold snap, a storm, a lightning flash, a conspiracy, perhaps a wave, and so on up to such big and important events that they have proper names, like the Passover and Lulu the H-bomb explosion. We have called a trope a "case" of its universal, while the universal is the "kind" of the trope, so it is no surprise that a medical "case" is a trope--in the sense, at any rate, in which a person is said to have a case of typhoid fever rather than to be a case of it. A high-school boy, uncoached, has assured me, "Of course there's such a thing as Redness--this pencil has a case of it." When a scientist reports a temperature or a velocity or a viscosity he is reporting a trope--not a universal, because it is a once-for-all occurrence, but not a concrete thing either, though doubtless a component of one. He is likely to call it an "aspect" of the thing or, preferably, a "state," and generally speaking a "state" of a thing or a nation is a trope. Recent developments in sub-atomic physics, a none too reliable oracle, suggest that an electron, e.g., just is an existent state, and that the common-sense philosophy of concreta here abdicates altogether in favor of the trope. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  19.  254
    Adequate ideas and modest scepticism in Hume's metaphysics of space.Donald C. Ainslie -2010 -Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 92 (1):39-67.
    In the Treatise of Human Nature , Hume argues that, because we have adequate ideas of the smallest parts of space, we can infer that space itself must conform to our representations of it. The paper examines two challenges to this argument based on Descartes's and Locke's treatments of adequate ideas, ideas that fully capture the objects they represent. The first challenge, posed by Arnauld in his Objections to the Meditations , asks how we can know that an idea is (...) adequate. The second challenge, implicit in Locke's Essay , asks how an empiricist can characterize an idea as inadequate, as both picking out an object and yet failing to capture it fully. In showing how Hume responds to these challenges, his theory of perceptual representation is explained and his treatment of space is related to his scepticism. His conclusion is shown not to be a characterization of space as it exists wholly apart from our powers of conception. Instead, in an adumbration of Kant, his claim is restricted to space as it appears to us. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  20. The Ground of Induction.Donald C. Williams -1947 -Philosophy 24 (88):86-88.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  21. The myth of passage.Donald C. Williams -1951 -Journal of Philosophy 48 (15):457-472.
  22.  49
    Hume on Personal Identity.Donald C. Ainslie -2008 - In Elizabeth Schmidt Radcliffe,A Companion to Hume. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 140–156.
    This chapter contains section titled: Introduction Locke on Personal Identity Hume's Critique of Locke The Belief in Mental Unity Hume's Second Thoughts Some Interpretations Unity in Reflection References.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  23.  55
    Citadel to City-State: The Transformation of Greece, 1200-700 B.C.E. (review).Donald C. Haggis -2001 -American Journal of Philology 122 (1):131-135.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:...
    No categories
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. The Cambridge Companion to Hume's Treatise.Donald C. Ainslie &Annemarie Butler (eds.) -2014 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    Revered for his contributions to empiricism, skepticism and ethics, David Hume remains one of the most important figures in the history of Western philosophy. His first and broadest work, A Treatise of Human Nature, comprises three volumes, concerning the understanding, the passions and morals. He develops a naturalist and empiricist program, illustrating that the mind operates through the association of impressions and ideas. This Companion features essays by leading scholars that evaluate the philosophical content of the arguments in Hume's Treatise (...) while considering their historical context. The authors examine Hume's distinctive views on causation, motivation, free will, moral evaluation and the origins of justice, which continue to influence present-day philosophical debate. This collection will prove a valuable resource for students and scholars exploring Hume, British empiricism and modern philosophy. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25. The Groundless Normativity of Instrumental Rationality.Donald C. Hubin -2001 -Journal of Philosophy 98 (9):445.
    Neo-Humean instrumentalist theories of reasons for acting have been presented with a dilemma: either they are normatively trivial and, hence, inadequate as a normative theory or they covertly commit themselves to a noninstrumentalist normative principle. The claimed result is that no purely instrumentalist theory of reasons for acting can be normatively adequate. This dilemma dissolves when we understand what question neo-Humean instrumentalists are addressing. The dilemma presupposes that neo-Humeans are attempting to address the question of how to act, 'simpliciter'. Instead, (...) they are evaluating actions from the agent's normative perspective. (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  26.  39
    Questioning Bioethics AIDS, Sexual Ethics, and the Duty to Warn.Donald C. Ainslie -1999 -Hastings Center Report 29 (5):26-35.
    Bioethicists have virtually assumed that Tarasoff generated a duty to warn the sexual partners of an HIV‐positive man that they risked infection. Yet given the views of sex and of AIDS that have evolved in the gay community, in many cases the parallels to Tarasoff do not hold. Bioethicists should at the least attend to the community's views, and indeed should go beyond doing mere “professional ethics” to participate in the moral self‐exploration in which these views are located.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27.  73
    Necessary Facts.Donald C. Williams -1963 -Review of Metaphysics 16 (4):601 - 626.
    My main thesis is that the necessary and its necessity are factual, or matters of fact, in the sense that they are realities on the same ontic plane or planes with any other beings there may be, physical, phenomenal, or Platonically transcendent, and are no more creatures of thought and speech than dogs and gravity are; if I think they are all physical actualities, this is only because I think everything is. I have a second thesis, however, which is that (...) the realities objectively characterized by necessity are "facts" in the more special sense in which we say it is a fact that the earth is round but not that the earth is a fact or that roundness is a fact. It is fashionable to declare that necessity and contingency pertain only to statements, judgments, or "propositions"; and though the popularity of this is due, I am afraid, to what is false in it, namely, its subjectivism, its philosophic force is due to a covert truth, that necessity can qualify nothing short of the states of affairs which make statements or judgments necessarily true. Any shifts that can avoid the admission of facts in general as first-class members of the universe can provide for what I shall say of necessary facts, but meanwhile the worth of the category will be so proving itself that I cannot foresee abandoning it, and it is all I shall be meaning hereinafter by the word "facts.". (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  28. Desires, Whims and Values.Donald C. Hubin -2003 -The Journal of Ethics 7 (3):315-335.
    Neo-Humean instrumentalists hold that anagent's reasons for acting are grounded in theagent's desires. Numerous objections have beenleveled against this view, but the mostcompelling concerns the problem of ``aliendesires'' – desires with which the agent doesnot identify. The standard version ofneo-Humeanism holds that these desires, likeany others, generate reasons for acting. Avariant of neo-Humeanism that grounds anagent's reasons on her values, rather than allof her desires, avoids this implication, but atthe cost of denying that we have reasons to acton innocent whims. (...) A version of neo-Humeanismthat holds that an agent has reason to satisfyall of her desires that are not in conflictwith her values appears to allow us to grantthe reason-giving force of innocent whims whiledenying the reason-giving force of alien desires. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  29. The Moral Justification of Benefit/Cost Analysis.Donald C. Hubin -1994 -Economics and Philosophy 10 (2):169-194.
    Benefit/cost analysis is a technique for evaluating programs, procedures, and actions; it is not a moral theory. There is significant controversy over the moral justification of benefit/cost analysis. When a procedure for evaluating social policy is challenged on moral grounds, defenders frequently seek a justification by construing the procedure as the practical embodiment of a correct moral theory. This has the apparent advantage of avoiding difficult empirical questions concerning such matters as the consequences of using the procedure. So, for example, (...) defenders of benefit/cost analysis (BCA) are frequently tempted to argue that this procedurejust isthe calculation of moral Tightness – perhaps that what itmeansfor an action to be morally right is just for it to have the best benefit-to-cost ratio given the accounts of “benefit” and “cost” that BCA employs. They suggest, in defense of BCA, that they have found the moral calculus – Bentham's “unabashed arithmetic of morals.” To defend BCA in this manner is to commit oneself to one member of a family of moral theories (let us call thembenefit/cost moral theoriesorB/C moral theories) and, also, to the view that if a procedure is (so to speak) the direct implementation of a correct moral theory, then it is a justified procedure. Neither of these commitments is desirable, and so the temptation to justify BCA by direct appeal to a B/C moral theory should be resisted; it constitutes an unwarranted short cut to moral foundations – in this case, an unsound foundation. Critics of BCA are quick to point out the flaws of B/C moral theories, and to conclude that these undermine the justification of BCA. But the failure to justify BCA by a direct appeal to B/C moral theory does not show that the technique is unjustified. There is hope for BCA, even if it does not lie with B/C moral theory. (shrink)
    Direct download(9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  30.  66
    Moral relevance.Donald C. Emmons -1967 -Ethics 77 (3):224-228.
  31.  158
    Universals and existents.Donald C. Williams -1986 -Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64 (1):1 – 14.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  32.  115
    Human reproductive interests: Puzzles at the periphery of the property paradigm.Donald C. Hubin -2012 -Social Philosophy and Policy 29 (1):106-125.
  33.  98
    Intellectual Substance as Form of the Body in Aquinas.Donald C. Abel -1995 -Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 69:227-236.
    This article explains Aquinas's attempt to show, within an Aristotelian framework, how the soul can be both a substance in its own right and the form of the body. I argue that although Aquinas' theory is logically consistent, its plausibility is weakened by the fact that it requires a significant modification of the Aristotelian conceptions of both substance and form.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  22
    (1 other version)Fifty readings in philosophy.Donald C. Abel (ed.) -2004 - Boston, Mass.: McGraw-Hill.
    This textbook is a flexible and affordable collection of classic and contemporary primary sources in philosophy. The readings cover seven basic topics of Western Philosophy. The selections are long enough to present a self-contained argument but not so lengthy that students lose track of the main point. The book includes a glossary and an appendix on logic and argumentation.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Principlism.Donald C. Ainslie -1982 - In Warren T. Reich,Encyclopedia of Bioethics. Macmillan.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  141
    The Problem of the National Self in Hume's Theory of Justice.Donald C. Ainslie -1995 -Hume Studies 21 (2):289-313.
  37.  35
    Précis of Hume's True Scepticism.Donald C. Ainslie -2019 -Hume Studies 45 (1):95-99.
    In Hume's True Scepticism, I offer a new interpretation of David Hume's epistemology and philosophy of mind as presented in A Treatise of Human Nature.1 I approach this task by developing what I take to be the first comprehensive2 investigation of Part 4 of Book 1. The arguments Hume offers there have frequently been addressed by the secondary literature in a piecemeal fashion, especially his account of personal identity and of our belief in the external world. But I argue in (...) HTS that they should be read as a sustained investigation of the human temptation to form philosophical systems. Consider its title: "Of the sceptical and other systems of philosophy". Hume, I suggest, is... (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  118
    Consciousness: Introduction.Donald C. Abel -2014 -Essays in Philosophy 15 (2):244-248.
    This is the editorial introduction to the four papers on consciousness comprising the July 2014 issue of Essays in Philosophy (vol. 15, issue 2). The four authors are Keith E. Turausky, John K. Grandy, Adam Green, and Ben Gubran.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  41
    AIDS and Sex: Is Warning a Moral Obligation?Donald C. Ainslie -2002 -Health Care Analysis 10 (1):49-66.
    Common-sense holds that morality requirespeople who know that they are infected with theHuman Immunodeficiency Virus (HIV) to disclosethis fact to their sexual partners. But manygay men who are HIV-positive do not disclose,and AIDS Service Organizations (ASOs) promotepublic-health policies based on safer sex byall, rather than disclosure by those who knowthat they are infected. The paper shows thatthe common-sense view follows from a minimalsexual morality based on consent. ASOs'seeming rejection of the view follows fromtheir need to take seriously widespreadweakness of will (...) in the realm of sexuality. The author argues that gay men take themselvesto follow the common sense view, but hold thatthe possibility of a partner's HIV infection isbackground information that need not bedisclosed for sexual consent. This suggestionis criticized. The paper concludes with aconsideration of HIV disclosure and sexualethics outside of the gay community and oflegal restrictions on the sexuality of theHIV-positive. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  45
    Hume, a Scottish Locke? Comments on Terence Penelhum’s Hume.Donald C. Ainslie -2012 -Canadian Journal of Philosophy 42 (S1):161-170.
    Where Terence Penelhum sees a deep continuity between John Locke's theory of ideas and David Hume's theory of perceptions, I argue that the two philosophers disagree over some fundamental issues in the philosophy of mind. While Locke treats ideas as imagistic objects that we recognize as such by a special kind of inner consciousness, Hume thinks that we do not normally recognize the imagistic content of our perceptions, and instead unselfconsciously take ourselves to sense a shared public world. My disagreement (...) with Penelhum over Hume's debt to Locke helps to explain our disagreement over the nature of Hume's scepticism. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. Hypothetical motivation.Donald C. Hubin -1996 -Noûs 30 (1):31-54.
  42.  16
    Sandino's Communism: Spiritual Politics for the Twenty-First Century.Donald C. Hodges -2013 - University of Texas Press.
    Drawing on previously unknown or unassimilated sources,Donald C. Hodges here presents an entirely new interpretation of the politics and philosophy of Augusto C. Sandino, the intellectual progenitor of Nicaragua's Sandinista revolution. The first part of the book investigates the political sources of Sandino's thought in the works of Babeuf, Buonarroti, Blanqui, Proudhon, Bakunin, Most, Malatesta, Kropotkin, Ricardo Flores Magón, and Lenin—a mixed legacy of pre-Marxist and non-Marxist authoritarian and libertarian communists. The second half of the study scrutinizes the (...) philosophy of nature and history that Sandino made his own. Hodges delves deeply into this philosophy as the supreme and final expression of Sandino's communism and traces its sources in the Gnostic and millenarian occult undergrounds. This results in a rich study of the ways in which Sandino's revolutionary communism and communist spirituality intersect—a spiritual politics that Hodges presents as more realistic than the communism of Karl Marx. While accepting the current wisdom that Sandino was a Nicaraguan liberal and social reformer, Hodges also makes a persuasive case that Sandino was first and foremost a communist, although neither of the Marxist nor anarchist variety. He argues that Sandino's eclectic communist spirituality was more of an asset than a liability for understanding the human condition, and that his spiritual politics promises to be more relevant than Marxism-Leninism for the twenty-first century. Indeed, Hodges believes that Sandino's holistic communism embraces both deep ecology and feminist spirituality—a finding that is sure to generate lively and productive debate. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  41
    Review: Of Bindings and By-Products: Elster on Rationality. [REVIEW]Donald C. Hubin -1986 -Philosophy and Public Affairs 15 (1):82 - 95.
  44. What’s Special about Humeanism.Donald C. Hubin -1999 -Noûs 33 (1):30-45.
    One of the attractions of the Humean instrumentalist theory of practical rationality is that it appears to offer a special connection between an agent's reasons and her motivation. The assumption that Humeanism is able to assert a strong connection between reason and motivation has been challenged, most notably by Christine Korsgaard. She argues that Humeanism is not special in the connection it allows to motivation. On the contrary, Humean theories of practical rationality do connect reasons and motivation in a unique (...) and attractive way, though the nature of this connection has sometimes been misunderstood by both defenders and detractors of the theory. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  45.  82
    Form and matter, II.Donald C. Williams -1958 -Philosophical Review 67 (4):499-521.
    No categories
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  46.  38
    The Metaphysics of Logical Positivism.Donald C. Williams -1955 -Philosophical Review 64 (4):646.
  47.  37
    Hume's "life" and the virtues of the dying.Donald C. Ainslie -2005 - In Thomas Mathien & D. G. Wright,Autobiography as Philosophy: The Philosophical Uses of Self-Presentation. New York: Routledge.
  48.  32
    Reply to My Critics.Donald C. Ainslie -2019 -Hume Studies 45 (1):129-141.
    I owe thanks to Annemarie Butler, Jonathan Cottrell, and Barry Stroud for their thoughtful criticism of my interpretation in Hume's True Scepticism of David Hume's epistemology and philosophy of mind as presented in A Treatise of Human Nature.1 Butler focuses on my account of the mental mechanisms Hume provides for our everyday beliefs about external objects. She also challenges my appeal to what Hume calls "secondary" ideas in my explanation of Humean introspection. Cottrell raises questions about my interpretation of perceptions (...) generally, both introspective and non-introspective, as well as my understanding of Hume's conflicted statements about... (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  76
    Western Conceptions of the Individual. [REVIEW]Donald C. Abel -1993 -Review of Metaphysics 46 (4):863-864.
    This ambitious book examines the conceptions of the human subject held by numerous Western thinkers from various disciplines. The study begins with Descartes and ends with Derrida. For the forty-six principal authors covered, Morris gives a brief biography, an overview of the author's thought in its historical context, an analysis of the author's theory of the human individual as presented in a major work, and a critique of that theory. Writers in addition to these forty-six are also discussed, but in (...) less detail. As is not surprising in a work that spans the fields of philosophy, psychology, anthropology, sociology, and sociobiology, the expositions and critiques rely considerably on secondary sources. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  50
    Meta-Ethical Autonomy.Donald C. Emmons -1971 -Journal of Critical Analysis 3 (2):53-56.
1 — 50 / 959
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp