Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'Daniel M. Lachenman'

974 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  18
    Philosophic Truth and the Existentiell: The Lack of Logic inSein und Zeit.Daniel M.Lachenman -1981 -Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 12 (1):55-73.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  51
    Danielle M. Wenner Replies.Danielle M. Wenner -2019 -Hastings Center Report 49 (2):47-47.
    The author replies to a letter to the editor from Felicitas Sofia Holzer concerning Wenner’s article “The Social Value Requirement in Research: From the Transactional to the Basic Structure Model of Stakeholder Obligations,” in the Hastings Center Report’s January‐February 2019 issue.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Through Action Identification.Daniel M. Wegner &James Frederick -unknown
    Social relations are vitally dependent on shared understanding of one another's actions. To initiate any sort of relationship, and to maintain a relationship once initiated, the partners to the relationship must com-.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  162
    When Jack and Jill Make a Deal*:DANIEL M. HAUSMAN.Daniel M. Hausman -1992 -Social Philosophy and Policy 9 (1):95-113.
    In ordinary circumstances, human actions have a myriad of unintended and often unforeseen consequences for the lives of other people. Problems of pollution are serious examples, but spillovers and side effects are the rule, not the exception. Who knows what consequences this essay may have? This essay is concerned with the problems of justice created by spillovers. After characterizing such spillovers more precisely and relating the concept to the economist's notion of an externality, I shall then consider the moral conclusions (...) concerning spillovers that issue from a natural rights perspective and from the perspective of welfare economics supplemented with theories of distributive justice. I shall argue that these perspectives go badly awry in taking spillovers to be the exception rather than the rule in human interactions. I. Externalities Economists have discussed spillovers under the heading of “externalities.” To say this is not very helpful, since there is so much disagreement concerning both the definition and significance of externalities. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  5.  37
    Some Parting Words:Daniel Hausman and Michael McPherson.Daniel M. Hausman -1995 -Economics and Philosophy 11 (1):i-ii.
  6.  78
    Early modern emotion and the economy of scarcity.Daniel M. Gross -2001 -Philosophy and Rhetoric 34 (4):308-321.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Rhetoric 34.4 (2001) 308-321 [Access article in PDF] Early Modern Emotion and the Economy of Scarcity 1 - [PDF]Daniel M. Gross Where do we get the idea that emotion is kind of excess, something housed in our nature aching for expression? In part, I argue, from The Passions of the Soul (1649), wherein Descartes proposed the reductive psychophysiology of emotion that informs both romantic expressivism (...) and latter-day psychology. Indeed, one goal of this article is simply to recall that we do not just naturally express emotions generated in our amygdala or wherever, but rather that we are first constituted as expressive agents by what the philosophers of the Scottish Enlightenment called "social passions." Contrary, however, to these largely optimistic philosophers, such as Hutcheson and Smith, who anchored social passions in a moral sense equally shared by all, I argue that the constitutive power of emotion derives from their unequal distribution. In what follows I work primarily with Aristotle's Rhetoric and Thomas Hobbes to outline a "political economy" wherein passions are (1) constituted as differences in power and (2) conditioned not by their excess but by their scarcity. Though we may reject the political conclusions reached by Aristotle and Hobbes, their analysis of emotion allows us to address important political questions neutralized in the Cartesian paradigm. 1. Descartes If you are tickled to learn that Aztec culture located passions in the liver, here is something at least as quaint from Descartes: "The ultimate and most proximate cause of the passions of the soul is none other than the agitation with which the spirits move the little gland which is in the middle of the [End Page 308] brain," that is, the pineal gland. Or so Descartes proposes in his 1649 treatise on the passions composed for Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia. Now compare this to Aristotle's Rhetoric, where for instance anger is defined as "desire, accompanied by distress, for conspicuous retaliation because of a conspicuous slight that was directed, without justification, against oneself or those near to one" (1378a 31-33). For Aristotle anger may indeed be accompanied by physical distress, as in the boiling of blood expressed in crimson cheeks, but its proximate cause is anything but that little gland in the middle of the head. Anger is a deeply social passion provoked by perceived slightsunjustified, and it presupposes a public stage where social status is always subject to performative infelicities.Indeed, we can learn a good deal about the rhetoric of human nature in early-modern Europe simply by asking what passions were. When we do, we find not only that their descriptions disagree, but also that the things described as passions seem incommensurable. Are passions tangible "things" residing in the soul, or are they dispositions of the heart or beliefs of the mind? Is passion a matter of personal expression, or is it something essentially social that a person performs? Do they come from our interior, or from the things we perceive? Can they be measured and manipulated--their causes controlled--or do passions elude control by their very nature? Are they divine, diabolical, or human, and can we distinguish them according to the status of their origin? Are they the enabling condition of virtue or its enemy? Are they necessary or disposable? What is their number and what do they do? Exasperated by endless wrangling over such questions, Descartes complains: There is nothing in which the defective nature of the sciences which we have received from the ancients appears more clearly than in what they have written on the passions; for although this is a matter which has at all times been the object of much investigation, and though it would not appear to be one of the most difficult, inasmuch as since everyone has experience of the passions within himself, there is no necessity to borrow one's observations from elsewhere in order to discover their nature. (331) 2With this preliminary remark Descartes renders human nature in its quintessential modern form: it is something housed in a body subject to the self-evidence... (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  135
    Deterrence and the Just Distribution of Harm*:DANIEL M. FARRELL.Daniel M. Farrell -1995 -Social Philosophy and Policy 12 (2):220-240.
    It is extraordinary, when one thinks about it, how little attention has been paid by theorists of the nature and justification of punishment to the idea that punishment is essentially a matter of self-defense. H. L. A. Hart, for example, in his famous “Prolegomenon to the Principles of Punishment,” is clearly committed to the view that, at bottom, there are just three directions in which a plausible theory of punishment can go: we can try to justify punishment on purely consequentialist (...) grounds, which for Hart, I think, would be to try to construct a purely utilitarian justification of punishment; we can try to justify punishment on purely retributive grounds; or we can try to justify punishment on grounds that are some sort of shrewd combination of consequentialist and retributive considerations. Entirely absent from Hart's discussion is any consideration of the possibility that punishment might be neither a matter of maximizing the good, nor of exacting retribution for a wrongful act, nor of some imaginative combination of these things, but, rather, of something altogether different from either of them: namely, the exercise of a fundamental right of self-protection. Similarly, but much more recently, R. A. Duff, despite the fact that he himself introduces and defends an extremely interesting fourth possibility, begins his discussion by writing as though, apart from his contribution, there are available to us essentially just the options previously sketched by Hart. Again, there is no mention here, any more than in Hart's or any number of other recent discussions, of the possibility that we might be able to justify the institution of punishment on grounds that are indeed forward-looking, to use Hart's famous term, but that are not at all consequentialist in any ordinary sense of the word. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  8. The illusion (Ch. 1).Daniel M. Wegner -unknown
    So, here you are, reading about conscious will. How could this have happened? One way to explain it would be to examine the causes of your behavior. A team of scientists could study your reported thoughts, emotions, and motives, your genetics and your history of learning, experience, and development, your social situation and culture, your memories and reaction times, your physiology and neuroanatomy, and lots of other things as well. If they somehow had access to all the information they could (...) ever want, the assumption of psychology is that they could uncover the mechanisms that give rise to all your behavior, and so could certainly explain why you are reading these words at this moment. However, another way to explain the fact of your reading these lines is just to say that you decided to begin reading. You consciously willed what you are doing. The ideas of conscious will and psychological mechanism have an oil and water relationship, having never been properly reconciled. One way to put them together is to say that the mechanistic approach is the explanation preferred for scientific purposes, but that the person’s experience of conscious will is utterly convincing and important to the person – and so must be understood scientifically as well. The mechanisms underlying the experience of will are themselves a fundamental topic of scientific study. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Thought Suppression and Mental.Daniel M. Wegner -unknown
    Consciously attempting not to think about something is a mental control strategy known as thought suppression. This strategy can be successful under certain conditions, but it often promotes an increase in the accessibility of the thought to consciousness, and along with this, a number of ironic processes and unwanted effects.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Unpriming: The Deactivation of Thoughts Through Expression.Daniel M. Wegner &Betsy Sparrow -unknown
    Unpriming is a decrease in the influence of primed knowledge following a behavior expressing that knowledge. The authors investigated strategies for unpriming the knowledge of an answer that is activated when people are asked to consider a simple question. Experiment 1 found that prior correct answering eliminated the bias people normally show toward correct responding when asked to answer yes–no questions randomly. Experiment 2 revealed that prior answering intended to be random did not unprime knowledge on subsequent attempts to answer (...) randomly. Experiment 3 found that exposure to the correct answer did not influence the knowledge bias but that exposure to the incorrect answer increased bias. Experiment 4 revealed that merely expressing the answer for oneself was sufficient to unprime knowledge. Experiment 5 found that each item of activated knowledge needs to be unprimed specifically, in that correctly answering 1 question does not reduce the knowledge bias in randomly answering another. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  2
    Autonomy, Critique and Proceduralism: The Kantian Foundations of Contemporary Liberal Theory.Daniel M. Weinstock -1991
  12.  28
    Christopher D. Frith and.Daniel M. Wolpert -2005 -Journal of Consciousness Studies 12 (2):90-5.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  28
    Examining Illness through Pediatric Poetry and Prose: A Mixed Methods Study.Daniel H. Grossoehme,Nicole Robinson,Sarah Friebert,Miraides Brown &Julie M. Aultman -2022 -Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 12 (1):53-76.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  39
    Intention, Reason, and Action.Daniel M. Farrell -1989 -American Philosophical Quarterly 26 (4):283 - 295.
  15.  71
    Critical studies / book reviews.Daniel M. Hausman -2003 -Philosophia Mathematica 11 (3):354-358.
  16.  57
    Erratum to: Systems without a graphical causal representation.Daniel M. Hausman,Reuben Stern &Naftali Weinberger -2015 -Synthese 192 (9):3053-3053.
    Erratum to: Synthese 191:1925–1930 DOI:10.1007/s11229-013-0380-3 The authors were unaware that points in their article appeared in “Caveats for Causal Reasoning with Equilibrium Models,” by Denver Dash and Marek Druzdzel, published in S. Benferhat and P. Besnard : European Conferences on Symbolic and Quantitative Approaches to Reasoning with Uncertainty 2001, Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence 2143, pp. 192–203. The authors were unaware of this essay and would like to apologize to the authors for failing to cite their excellent work.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. The impossibility of interpersonal utility comparisons-a reply-to Ruth Weintraub, Mind, vol. 105, p. 661, 1996.Daniel M. Hausman -1996 -Mind 105:661.
  18. Author's personal copy.Daniel M. Wegner -unknown
    It has been proposed that inferring personal authorship for an event gives rise to intentional binding, a perceptual illusion in which one’s action and inferred effect seem closer in time than they otherwise would (Haggard, Clark, & Kalogeras, 2002). Using a novel, naturalistic paradigm, we conducted two experiments to test this hypothesis and examine the relationship between binding and self-reported authorship. In both experiments, an important authorship indicator – consistency between one’s action and a subsequent event – was manipulated, and (...) its effects on binding and self-reported authorship were measured. Results showed that action-event consistency enhanced both binding and self-reported authorship, supporting the hypothesis that binding arises from an inference of authorship. At the same time, evidence for a dissociation emerged, with consistency having a more robust effect on self-reports than on binding. Taken together, these results suggest that binding and self-reports reveal different aspects of the sense of authorship. Ó 2009 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Books Et Al.Daniel M. Wegner -unknown
    Imagine a gadget, call it “brain-ovision,” for brain scanning that doesn’t create pictures of brains at all. That’s right, no orbs spattered with colorful “activations” that need to be interpreted by neuroanatomists. Instead, with brain-o-vision, what a brain sees is what you get—an image of what that brain is experiencing. If the person who owns the brain is envisioning lunch, up pops a cheeseburger on the screen. If the person is reading a book, the screen shows the words. For that (...) matter, if the brain owner is feeling pain, perhaps brain-o-vision could reach out and swat the viewer with a rolled-up newspaper. Brain-ovision could give us access to another person’s consciousness. Technologies for brain-o-vision are beginning to seem possible. We are learning how brain activations map onto emotions, memories, and mental processes, and it won’t be long before we might translate activations into Google searches for images of what the brain is thinking. There is a specific brain area linked with face perception, for instance, and even a neuron that fires when it sees Jennifer Aniston. So why, in principle, shouldn’t we be able to scan a brain and discover when it is looking at her—and eventually even learn what she’s wearing? Of course, it may be many years to the beta version. But imagine that everything works out and brain-o-vision goes on sale at Wal- Mart. Could the device solve the problem of whether consciousness causes behavior? With direct evidence of a person’s consciousness, we could do science on the question. We could observe regularities in the relation between consciousness and behavior. If the consciousness always preceded the behavior, we could arrive at the inductive inference of causation and, as scientists, be quite happy that we had established a causal connection. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Mental Control: The War of the Ghosts.Daniel M. Wegner &David J. Schneider -unknown
    Sometimes it feels as though we can control our minds. We catch ourselves looking out the window when we should be paying attention to someone talking, for example, and we purposefully return our attention to the conversation. Or we wrest our minds away from the bothersome thought of an upcoming dental appointment to focus on anything we can find that makes us less nervous. Control attempts such as these can meet with success, leaving us feeling the masters of our consciousness. (...) Yet at other times.. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  58
    :Health Problems.Daniel M. Hausman -2024 -Ethics 134 (4):559-565.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Nature's Witness: How Evolution Can Inspire Faith.Daniel M. Harrell -2008
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Evaluating social policy.Daniel M. Hausman -2012 - In Harold Kincaid,The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Social Science. Oxford University Press.
  24.  40
    The faults of formalism and the magic of markets.Daniel M. Hausman -1998 -Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 12 (1-2):127-138.
    Abstract Contrary to Peter J. Boettke's essay, ?What Went Wrong with Economics??, there is no connection between ?formalism? and the alleged inability of mainstream economists to regard theoretical models as anything other than either depictions of real market economies or bases for criticizing market economies and justifying government intervention. Although Boettke's criticisms of the excesses of formalism are justified, Austrian economists such as Boettke need to justify their view that government interventions into economic affairs are inevitably harmful.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  81
    The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics.Daniel M. Hausman -1992 - Cambridge University Press.
    This book offers a comprehensive overview of the structure, strategy and methods of assessment of orthodox theoretical economics. In Part I Professor Hausman explains how economists theorise, emphasising the essential underlying commitment of economists to a vision of economics as a separate science. In Part II he defends the view that the basic axioms of economics are 'inexact' since they deal only with the 'major' causes; unlike most writers on economic methodology, the author argues that it is the rules that (...) economists espouse rather than their practice that is at fault. Part III links the conception of economics as a separate science to the fact that economic theories offer reasons and justifications for human actions, not just their causes. With its lengthy appendix introducing relevant issues in philosophy of science, this book is a major addition to philosophy of economics and of social science. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   207 citations  
  26.  10
    Being-moved: rhetoric as the art of listening.Daniel M. Gross -2020 - Oakland, California: University of California Press.
    If rhetoric is the art of speaking, who is listening? In Being-Moved,Daniel M. Gross provides an answer, showing when and where the art of speaking parted ways with the art of listening-and what happens when they intersect once again. Much in the history of rhetoric must be rethought along the way. And much of this rethinking pivots around Martin Heidegger's early lectures on Aristotle's Rhetoric, where his famous topic, Being, gives way to being-moved. The results, Gross goes on (...) to show, are profound. Listening to the gods, listening to the world around us, and even listening to one another in the classroom-all of these experiences become different when rhetoric is reoriented from the voice to the ear. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  41
    Integrating basic research with prevention/intervention to reduce risky substance use among college students.Danielle M. Dick &Linda C. Hancock -2015 -Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  19
    Medicina narrativa e bioetica della cura: tre riflessioni sull'atto medico e la distinzione tra malattia e patologia.Daniele M. Cananzi -2023 - Milano: Mimesis.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  42
    Yogācāra Substrata? Precedent Frames for Yogācāra Thought Among Third-Century Yoga Practitioners in Greater Gandhāra.Daniel M. Stuart -2018 -Journal of Indian Philosophy 46 (2):193-240.
    The connection between early yogācāras, or practitioners of yoga, and later Yogācāra-vijñānavāda philosophy has long preoccupied scholars. But these connections remain obscure. This article suggests that a text that has received little attention in modern scholarship, the Saddharmasmṛtyupasthānasūtra, may shed light on aspects of early yogācāra contemplative cultures that gave rise to some of the formative dynamics of Yogācāra-vijñānavāda thought. I show how traditional Buddhist meditative practice and engagement with Abhidharma theoretics come together in the Saddharmasmṛtyuasthānasūtra to produce a novel (...) theory of mind that mirrors many of the philosophical problematics that early and late Yogācāra-vijñānavādins confronted and attempted to work out in śāstric detail. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  35
    The logical privacy of pains.Daniel M. Taylor -1970 -Mind 79 (January):78-91.
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  40
    Feminine Wiles and Masculine Weakness: Seventeenth-Century Visual Responses to Tasso’s Crusade.Daniel M. Unger -2016 -The European Legacy 21 (8):812-835.
    This essay offers a political reading of the artistic choices made by seventeenth-century painters in their depictions of the heroines of Tasso’s Jerusalem Delivered. It discusses the political subtext of Tasso’s epic poem by exploring the roles Tasso assigns to his oriental heroines and their representation in seventeenth-century paintings. Painters and patrons alike were particularly enthusiastic about the love stories that developed around Jerusalem. But Tasso is promoting a crusade, and the visual focus of later painters on Tasso’s seductive female (...) protagonists and their submission to Christian warriors, suggests that their aim was to display the delights that await those who join a military expedition to conquer the Holy Land. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Hidden Complications of Thought Suppression.Daniel M. Wegner -unknown
    Although the suppression of thoughts may seem to be an effective solution when thoughts are unwanted, this strategy can lead to a recurrence of the very thought that one is attempting to suppress. This ironic effect is the most obvious unwanted outcome of suppression and has been investigated empirically for more than two decades. However, even when suppression does not lead to an ironic rebound of the unwanted thought, it puts an insidious cognitive load on the individual attempting to suppress. (...) Moreover, whether or not suppression leads to an exacerbation of the unwanted thought, it is rarely successful, and hence adds to the individual’s distress. In this article we describe the consequences of suppression and consider how it might complicate a range of emotional disorders. Taken together, studies on thought suppression in psychopathology present a more nuanced picture now than was emerging in the early years of its investigation. Some evidence is consistent with the idea that the counterproductive effects of suppression are causally implicated in disorders, but a more parsimonious conclusion is that thought suppression often acts as a complication of disorders. In certain disorders, suppression complicates the disorder by leading to an ironic rebound of the unwanted thoughts. In all disorders, the cost of undertaking suppression is a persistent cognitive load, which undermines the ability to suppress and sets off a cycle of failed expectations and distress. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Sources of the Experience of Will.Daniel M. Wegner &Thalia Wheatley -unknown
    Conscious will is an experience like the sensation of the color red, the percepfion of a friend's voice, or the enjoyment of a fine spring day. David Hume (1739/1888) appreciated the will in just this way, defining it as "nothing but the internal..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  55
    Otfried Höffe, Principes du droit, , Paris, Les Éditions du Cerf, 1993.Daniel M. Weinstock -1996 -Philosophiques 23 (1):196-198.
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  33
    6 Value Pluralism, Autonomy, and Toleration.Daniel M. Weinstock -2022 - In Melissa S. Williams,Moral Universalism and Pluralism: Nomos Xlix. New York University Press. pp. 125-148.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  29
    Motor learning models.Daniel M. Wolpert &Zoubin Ghahramani -2003 - In L. Nadel,Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science. Nature Publishing Group.
  37. Theory of incursive synchronization of delayed systems and anticipatory computing of chaos.Daniel M. Dubois -2002 - In Robert Trappl,Cybernetics and Systems. Austrian Society for Cybernetics Studies. pp. 1--17.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  26
    Legitimate Government and Consent of the Governed.Daniel M. Farrell -1985 -Bowling Green Studies in Applied Philosophy 7:192-203.
  39.  191
    (2 other versions)The Pursuit of Unhappiness: The Elusive Psychology of Well-Being.Daniel M. Haybron -2008 - Oxford University Press.
    Dan Haybron presents an illuminating examination of well-being, drawing on important recent work in the science of happiness. He shows that we are remarkably prone to error in judgements of our own personal welfare, and suggests that we should rethink traditional assumptions about the good life and the good society.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   137 citations  
  40. Motivation and transfer: The role of achievement goals in preparation for future learning.Daniel M. Belenky &Timothy J. Nokes -2009 - In N. A. Taatgen & H. van Rijn,Proceedings of the 31st Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. pp. 1163--1168.
  41.  15
    Strategic Planning and Moral Norms: The Case of Deterrent Nuclear Threats.Daniel M. Farrell -1987 -Public Affairs Quarterly 1 (1):61-77.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Historiography and the limits of (sacred) rhetoric.Daniel M. Gross -2021 - In Michael F. Bernard-Donals & Kyle Jensen,Responding to the sacred: an inquiry into the limits of rhetoric. University Park, Pennsylvania: The Pennsylvania State University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  27
    Introduction: Alva Noë, "In Focus".Daniel M. Gross -2021 -Philosophy and Rhetoric 54 (1):25-27.
    Alva Noë, who is a major figure in establishment philosophy, has been producing work that speaks directly to rhetoric in new ways that are important. This "In Focus" project explores how so, with the help of Carrie Noland on dance, Thomas Rickert on music, and, in a previous issue of Philosophy & Rhetoric 53.1, Nancy Struever on the basics of human inquiry including pictorial, which she thinks almost nobody gets right except for R. G. Collingwood, and perhaps now Noë. In (...) each case you will see how "rhetoric" must be stretched by way of these lateral artistic, and at the same time essential, projects in the discipline per se."Rhetoric" in these considerations is certainly not a vague notion that the things we do... (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  45
    Quantization in the large.Daniel M. Greenberger -1983 -Foundations of Physics 13 (9):903-951.
    A model theory is constructed that exhibits quantization on a cosmic scale. A holistic rationale for the theory is discussed. The theory incorporates a fundamental length, of cosmic size, and preserves the weak, geometrical equivalence principle. The momentum operator is an integral, nonlocal, naturally contravariant operator, in contrast to the usual quantum case. In the limit of high quantum numbers the theory reduces to classical physics, giving rise to a world which is quantized both on the microscopic and cosmic scale, (...) each of which passes over to the usual macroscopic, continuous, classical, world in the highn limit.The theory is applied to two experimental situations, absorption lines in high-z quasars and elliptical rings around normal galaxies, with suggestive but not definitive results. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  18
    “Men of Stone and Children of Struggle”: Latin American Liberationists at the End of History.Daniel M. Bell -1998 -Modern Theology 14 (1):113-141.
  46. In direzione del Diritto e del Linguaggio. L'Informazione dei viventi non umani tra filogenesi e ontogenesi.Daniele M. Cananzi -2001 -Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia Del Diritto 78 (4):487-527.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  20
    15 Tendencies, laws, and the composition of economic causes.Daniel M. Hausman -2001 - In Uskali Mäki,The Economic World View: Studies in the Ontology of Economics. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 293.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  41
    Preference, Value, Choice, and Welfare.Daniel M. Hausman -2011 - Cambridge University Press.
    This book is about preferences, principally as they figure in economics. It also explores their uses in everyday language and action, how they are understood in psychology and how they figure in philosophical reflection on action and morality. The book clarifies and for the most part defends the way in which economists invoke preferences to explain, predict and assess behavior and outcomes. Hausman argues, however, that the predictions and explanations economists offer rely on theories of preference formation that are in (...) need of further development, and he criticizes attempts to define welfare in terms of preferences and to define preferences in terms of choices or self-interest. The analysis clarifies the relations between rational choice theory and philosophical accounts of human action. The book also assembles the materials out of which models of preference formation and modification can be constructed, and it comments on how reason and emotion shape preferences. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  49.  34
    Bearing the Weight of Salvation: The Soteriology of Ignacio Ellacuría – By Michael E. Lee.Daniel M. Bell -2010 -Modern Theology 26 (4):686-689.
  50.  60
    Ordeals, inequalities, moral hazard and non-monetary incentives in health care.Daniel M. Hausman -2021 -Economics and Philosophy 37 (1):23-36.
    This essay begins by summarizing the reasons why unregulated health-care markets are inefficient. The inefficiencies stem from the asymmetries of information among providers, patients and payers, which give rise to moral hazard and adverse selection. Attempts to ameliorate these inefficiencies by means of risk-adjusted insurance and monetary incentives such as co-pays and deductibles lessen the inefficiencies at the cost of increasing inequalities. Another possibility is to rely on non-monetary incentives, including ordeals. While not a magic bullet, these are feasible methods (...) for addressing the inadequacies of market provision of health care, such as moral hazard. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 974
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp