Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'Daniel Joel Shaw'

938 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  23
    Dissociating Profiles of Social Cognitive Disturbances Between Mixed Personality and Anxiety Disorder.Kristína Czekóová,DanielJoelShaw,Zuzana Pokorná &Milan Brázdil -2020 -Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  20
    Dissociating visual perspective taking and belief reasoning using a novel integrated paradigm: A preregistered online study.Rachel Green,DanielJoelShaw &Klaus Kessler -2023 -Cognition 235 (C):105397.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  23
    What Lies Within: Uncovering the Holy Spirit with the Aid of Buddhist Philosophy.Joel D. Daniels -2020 -Buddhist-Christian Studies 40 (1):287-305.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  34
    Uncarved and Unconcerned: Zhuangzian Contentment in an Age of Happiness.Joel D. Daniels -2019 -Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 18 (4):577-596.
    Through the formation of positive psychology, the study of happiness has moved into the scientific domain. Positive psychology’s assertion is that with the proper adjustments, everyone can achieve happiness. The problem, however, is that “happiness” is never defined, causing scientific testing to construct new parameters for each study, inevitably altering the object being examined. Rather than pursuing amorphous happiness, I argue that the Zhuangzi 莊子 provides a more adequate and responsible process or method for living well. After exploring Aristotle’s position (...) on happiness, I investigate the terminological and methodological issues with the scientific study of happiness. For an alternative, I propose Zhuangzian contentment that reorients individuals toward dynamic existence rather than false notions of control, which the scientific method suggests is possible. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  60
    The Fluid Movement of the Spirit: (Re)Conceptualizing Gender in Pentecostalism.Joel D. Daniels -2022 -Journal of Religious Ethics 50 (4):577-599.
    Claiming close to 800 million adherents, Pentecostalism is the fastest growing religious community in the world; nevertheless, the movement remains under‐researched, encouraging more academic investment. This article takes on this task by exploring Pentecostalism regarding gender and sex. Why have Pentecostals ardently supported gender normativity? Why have Pentecostal denominations in the United States adamantly opposed the recent Equality Acts bill? This essay's argument is that Pentecostal belief and practice, rooted in theology and pneumatology, actually denounce gender bifurcation, supporting instead fluid (...) movement with the Holy Spirit into and out of gender performances. Judith Butler's performance theory, Sarah Coakley's Trinitarian theology, and Lisa Stephenson's imago Spiritus frame the overall argument. As Paul declares, there is no longer male or female in Christ. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  22
    The Wind Blows Gently and Fiercely: A Pentecostal Perspective on Love and Anger.Joel D. Daniels -2019 -Buddhist-Christian Studies 39 (1):37-51.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Freedom and indeterminism.Daniel J.Shaw -1989 - In John Heil,Cause, Mind, and Reality: Essays Honoring C.B. Martin. Kluwer Academic Publishers.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  153
    Probabilistic coherence and proper scoring rules.Joel Predd,Robert Seiringer,Elliott Lieb,Daniel Osherson,H. Vincent Poor &Sanjeev Kulkarni -2009 -IEEE Transactions on Information Theory 55 (10):4786-4792.
    We provide self-contained proof of a theorem relating probabilistic coherence of forecasts to their non-domination by rival forecasts with respect to any proper scoring rule. The theorem recapitulates insights achieved by other investigators, and clarifi es the connection of coherence and proper scoring rules to Bregman divergence.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  9. The mastery of hannibal lecter.DanielShaw -2003 - In Steven Jay Schneider & Daniel Shaw,Dark thoughts: philosophic reflections on cinematic horror. Lanham, Md.: Scarecrow Press. pp. 10--24.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  62
    The Influence of Using Novel Predictive Technologies on Judgments of Stigma, Empathy, and Compassion among Healthcare Professionals.Daniel Z. Buchman,Daphne Imahori,Christopher Lo,Katrina Hui,Caroline Walker,JamesShaw &Karen D. Davis -2024 -American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 15 (1):32-45.
    Background Our objective was to evaluate whether the description of a machine learning (ML) app or brain imaging technology to predict the onset of schizophrenia or alcohol use disorder (AUD) influences healthcare professionals’ judgments of stigma, empathy, and compassion. Methods We randomized healthcare professionals (N = 310) to one vignette about a person whose clinician seeks to predict schizophrenia or an AUD, using a ML app, brain imaging, or a psychosocial assessment. Participants used scales to measure their judgments of stigma, (...) empathy, and compassion. Results Participants randomized to the ML vignette endorsed less anger and more fear relative to the psychosocial vignette, and the brain imaging vignette elicited higher pity ratings. The brain imaging and ML vignettes evoked lower personal responsibility judgments compared to the psychosocial vignette. Physicians and nurses reported less empathy than clinical psychologists. Conclusions The use of predictive technologies may reinforce essentialist views about mental health and substance use that may increase specific aspects of stigma and reduce others. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11.  6
    A Study of the Complex and Disputed Philosophical Questions Surrounding Human Action.DanielShaw -2000
    This study presents a dualist account of the nature of human action, dualist in a modest sense in that it defends the claim that actions involve the physical and the mental and cannot be interpreted in functionalist ways.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  44
    The time-intensity relation in visual perception as a function of observer's task.Daniel Kahneman &Joel Norman -1964 -Journal of Experimental Psychology 68 (3):215.
  13.  16
    Incivility Affects Actors Too: The Complex Effects of Incivility on Perpetrators’ Work and Home Behaviors.Daniel Kim,Klodiana Lanaj &Joel Koopman -forthcoming -Journal of Business Ethics:1-28.
    The majority of workplace incivility research has focused on implications of such acts for victims and observers. We extend this work in meaningful ways by proposing that, due to its norm-violating nature, incivility may have important implications for perpetrators as well. Integrating social norms theory and research on guilt with the behavioral concordance model, we take an actor-centric approach to argue that enacted incivility will lead to feelings of guilt, particularly for prosocially-motivated employees. In addition, given the interpersonally burdensome _as (...) well as_ the reparative nature of guilt, we submit that incivility-induced guilt will be associated with complex behavioral outcomes for the actor across both home and work domains. Through an experience sampling study (Study 1) and two experiments (Studies 2a and 2b), we found that enacting incivility led to increased feelings of guilt, especially for those higher in prosocial motivation (Studies 1 and 2a). In addition, supporting our expectations, Study 1 revealed that enacted incivility—via guilt—led to increased venting to one’s spouse that evening at home, increased performance the next day at work, as well as decreased enacted incivility the next day at work. Our findings demonstrate that enacted incivility has complex effects for actors that span the home and work domains. We discuss the theoretical and practical implications of our results. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  63
    Hume's Moral Sentimentalism.DanielShaw -1993 -Hume Studies 19 (1):31-54.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume's Moral SentimentalismDanielShaw In chapter 7 ofhis book, Hume, Barry Stroud considers and rejects a number of standard interpretations of Hume's sentimentalism and then argues for his own 'projectionist' interpretation.1 In this paper I shall commentbriefly on all thesereadings, raise objectionsto Stroud's proposal, and, finally, argue in favour of what I shall call the 'power* interpretation ofHume's sentimentalism. Hume maintains that the vice or virtue (...) ofan action is not a matter offact about the action that can be inferred from anything, by causal orinductive reasoningalone, nor afact that canbe discovered by direct perception ofan action, but that, rather, vice and virtue are matters of moral sentiment. Hume writes, Take any action allow'd to be vicious: Wilful murder, for instance. Examine it in all lights, and see ifyou can find that matter of fact, or real existence, which you call vice. In which-ever way you take it, you find only certain passions, motives, voUtions and thoughts. There is no other matter of fact in the case. The vice entirely escapes you, as long as you consider the object. You never can find it, till you turn your reflexion into your own breast, and find a sentiment of disapprobation which arises in you, towards this action. Here is a matter of fact; but 'tis the object of feeling, not of reason. It lies in yourself, not in the object. So that when you pronounce any action or character to be vicious, you mean nothing, but thatfrom the constitution ofyour nature youhave a feeling or sentiment ofblame from the contemplation of it. Vice andvirtue, therefore, maybe compar'd to sounds, colours, heat and cold, which, according to modern philosophy, are not quaUties in objects, but perceptions in the mind.2 Stroud gives the following explanation ofthis passage: [W]hat we believe or 'pronounce' when we regard an action as vicious is different from and more than anything we can discover by perception of the action or by inference from its observed characteristics to other matters of fact about it. Hume grants that there are certain observable characteristics an action can be known to possess such that when we know Volume XIX Number 1 31DANIELSHAW that the action has them we inevitably regard it as vicious. (H 178) In a case of wilful murder, for example, we can discover by (roughly) causal reasoning that one man deliberately and unnecessarily destroyed a human life, and caused great suffering, pain and hardship both to the victim and to others. (H 177) And Hume would grant that when we know that the man's action has these characteristics we inevitably regard it as vicious. But, he quiterightlyinsists that that does notimply thatregarding that action as vicious is simply believing that it has those observable [and inferrable] characteristics. He thinks that pronouncing an action to be vicious is something different and that is why he says that the vice entirely escapes you as long as you consider only the object thought to be vicious. (H 178) Why does Hume think that, for example, believing an act of wilful murder to be vicious cannot consist simply and entirely in beUeving it to possess the observable and inferrable characteristics of being a deliberate and unnecessary destruction of human life which caused great suffering, pain, etc.? Surely, one might think, to believe all that ofan action is all there need be for believing the action to be a morally vicious action. But, of course, Hume would argue that since the above beliefis itselfmerely a conclusion ofperception and causal reasoning, which in itself has no motivating power, and since, by contrast, the judgement that the act is morally vicious, being a moral judgement, must in itselfbe capable ofmotivating us to act, that is, to refrain from murder and do all we can to prevent murder, the latter active motivational moraljudgement must involve something over and above the former inert conclusion ofreason. I would agree with Stroud that Hume is right about this. Imagine a case ofa psychopath whose ability to argue and draw valid inferences is in perfectly good working order but whose motivational and emotional derangement is so severe that... (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  88
    Power, Horror and Ambivalence.DanielShaw -2001 -Film and Philosophy 4 (Special Edition on Horror):1-12.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  16.  469
    Critical duration for the resolution of form: Centrally or peripherally determined?Daniel Kahneman,Joel Norman &Michael Kubovy -1967 -Journal of Experimental Psychology 73 (3):323.
  17.  27
    Interpretation of the stress dependence of creep by a mixed climb mechanism in TiAl.Joël Malaplate,Daniel Caillard &Alain Couret † -2004 -Philosophical Magazine 84 (34):3671-3687.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  106
    On being philosophical and being John malkovich.DanielShaw -2006 -Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (1):111–118.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  128
    Hume's Theory of Motivation.DanielShaw -1989 -Hume Studies 15 (1):163-183.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:163 HUME'S THEORY OF MOTIVATION In this paper I shall defend a Humean theory of motivation. But first I should like to examine some of the standard criticisms of this theory and some alternative views that are currently in favour. Both in the Treatise and the Enguiry Hume maintains that reason alone never motivates action but always requires the cooperation of some separate, and separately identifiable desire-factor in order (...) to bring about action. What are Hume's grounds for this view? In the Treatise. Hume writes: 'Tis obvious, that when we have the prospect of pain or pleasure from any object, we feel a consequent emotion of aversion or propensity, and are carry 'd to avoid or embrace what will give us this uneasiness or satisfaction.... 'Tis from the prospect of pleasure or pain that the aversion or propensity arises towards any object.... This passage suggests that the way we (and Hume) know about the presence of the separate desire factor which he claims is always needed to motivate our every purposive action is by being directly aware of some desire-feeling, by introspection, each and every time we act. There is however a familiar objection to this argument: no doubt we sometimes are aware of a feeling of desire when we act, e.g., in cases where we are motivated by strong emotions. But much of the time when we act calmly or casually, after having deliberated 'in a cool hour', or when performing routine and trivial acts, we are not directly aware of any desire-feeling at the time of action. 164 Hume is not unaware of this objection -- in reply to it he invokes his notorious doctrine of the calm passions. He writes: 'Tis natural for one, that does not examine objects with a strict philosophic eye, to imagine, that those actions of the mind are entirely the same, which produce not a different sensation, and are not immediately distinguishable to the feeling and perception. Reason, for instance, exerts itself without producing any sensible emotion; and except in the more sublime disquisitions of philosophy, or in the frivolous subtilities of the schools, scarce ever conveys any pleasure or uneasiness. Hence it proceeds, that every action of the mind, which operates with the same calmness and tranquillity, is confounded with reason by all those, who judge of things from the first view and appearance. Now 'tis certain, there are certain calm desires and tendencies, which, tho' they be real passions, produce little emotion in the mind, and are more known by their effects than by the immediate feeling or sensation. These desires are of two kinds; either certain instincts originally implanted in our natures, such as benevolence and resentment, the love of life, and kindness to children; or the general appetite to good, and aversion to evil, consider 'd merely as such. When any of these passions are calm, and cause no disorder in the soul, they are very readily taken for the determination of reason, and are suppos'd to proceed from the same faculty, with that, which judges of truth and falshood. Their nature and principles have been suppos'd the same, because their sensations are not evidently different. (T 417) The most obvious application of this argument would be to cases of cool, seemingly passionless 165 deliberation: e.g., in the course of planning the family budget I set aside funds for the children's education. A cursory inspection (or recollection) of the contents of my conscious mind at the time of acting would reveal to me some purely rational considerations that I had in mind at the time. I had some thoughts at the time whose contents are (roughly) expressible in such words as "If I don't put aside so much per month over so many years we will never be able to see them all through university." But cursory introspection or recollection would not detect any separately identifiable desire-factor present to my conscious mind at the time. Considered philosophical examination, Hume assures us, will reveal one, a 'calm' one -- in this case calm 'kindness to children'. Less obviously, the calm-passions argument, most naturally applicable to cases of deliberation... (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  20.  43
    Special Supplement: Biomedical Ethics and the Shadow of Nazism.Daniel Callahan,Arthur Caplan,Harold Edgar,Laurence McCullough,Tabitha M. Powledge,Margaret Steinfels,Peter Steinfels,Robert M. Veatch,Joseph Walsh,Joel Colton,Lucy S. Dawidowicz,Milton Himmelfarb &Telford Taylor -1976 -Hastings Center Report 6 (4):1.
  21.  59
    Lost in the Rhythm: Effects of Rhythm on Subsequent Interpersonal Coordination.Martin Lang,Daniel J.Shaw,Paul Reddish,Sebastian Wallot,Panagiotis Mitkidis &Dimitris Xygalatas -2016 -Cognitive Science 40 (7):1797-1815.
    Music is a natural human expression present in all cultures, but the functions it serves are still debated. Previous research indicates that rhythm, an essential feature of music, can enhance coordination of movement and increase social bonding. However, the prolonged effects of rhythm have not yet been investigated. In this study, pairs of participants were exposed to one of three kinds of auditory stimuli (rhythmic, arrhythmic, or white‐noise) and subsequently engaged in five trials of a joint‐action task demanding interpersonal coordination. (...) We show that when compared with the other two stimuli, exposure to the rhythmic beat reduced the practice effect in task performance. Analysis of the behavioral data suggests that this reduction results from more temporally coupled motor movements over successive trials and that shared exposure to rhythm facilitates interpersonal motor coupling, which in this context serves to impede the attainment of necessary dynamic coordination. We propose that rhythm has the potential to enhance interpersonal motor coupling, which might serve as a mechanism behind its facilitation of positive social attitudes. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  22.  14
    Cavell on Skepticism: Redeeming the Law.DanielShaw -2018 -Film and Philosophy 22:116-129.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  3
    Incivility Affects Actors Too: The Complex Effects of Incivility on Perpetrators’ Work and Home Behaviors.Daniel Kim,Klodiana Lanaj &Joel Koopman -2025 -Journal of Business Ethics 197 (3):631-658.
    The majority of workplace incivility research has focused on implications of such acts for victims and observers. We extend this work in meaningful ways by proposing that, due to its norm-violating nature, incivility may have important implications for perpetrators as well. Integrating social norms theory and research on guilt with the behavioral concordance model, we take an actor-centric approach to argue that enacted incivility will lead to feelings of guilt, particularly for prosocially-motivated employees. In addition, given the interpersonally burdensome as (...) well as the reparative nature of guilt, we submit that incivility-induced guilt will be associated with complex behavioral outcomes for the actor across both home and work domains. Through an experience sampling study (Study 1) and two experiments (Studies 2a and 2b), we found that enacting incivility led to increased feelings of guilt, especially for those higher in prosocial motivation (Studies 1 and 2a). In addition, supporting our expectations, Study 1 revealed that enacted incivility—via guilt—led to increased venting to one’s spouse that evening at home, increased performance the next day at work, as well as decreased enacted incivility the next day at work. Our findings demonstrate that enacted incivility has complex effects for actors that span the home and work domains. We discuss the theoretical and practical implications of our results. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  36
    Ethics, Reproduction and Genetic Control.Daniel J.Shaw -1989 -Philosophical Books 30 (1):45-47.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  34
    Rorty and Nietzsche: Some Elective Affinities.DanielShaw -1989 -International Studies in Philosophy 21 (2):3-14.
  26.  24
    Two Views about Truth in the Arts.Daniel JosephShaw -2001 -The Journal of Aesthetic Education 35 (2):49.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  86
    Hume's Theory of Motivation — Part 2.DanielShaw -1992 -Hume Studies 18 (1):19-39.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume's Theory ofMotivation — Part 2DanielShaw Introduction and Summary of Part 1 In an earlier paper of the same title1 1 defended a Humean theory of motivation against rationalist views ofB. Stroud and T. Nagel.2 In this paper I shouldlike to relate my theory tomore recent writings, explain its implications for the topic ofmoral motivation and provide further support for the main argument ofmy original (...) paper. To begin with, a summary of my previous discussion: while two critics of Hume's theory, B. Stroud and T. Nagel, disagree about the role ofreason inaction(Stroudaccepts, Nagelrejectsthe Humeanclaim thatreason alone can never produce action) theyboth agree inrejecting Hume's view thatmotivating desire essentially involves feelings which are identifiable by the agent, in his conscious experience, by introspection, as something extra, something over and above any purely rational considerations he may have for taking action. As an alternative to this Humean, experiential view ofmotivating desire, Stroud argues that the concept of motivating desire should be analysednotinterms ofanyintrinsic propertyknowablein experience, butratherin terms ofits function in leading, along withbelief, to action. In Stroud's words: "It might well be that to have a desire for or a propensity towards E is simply to be in a state such that when you come to believe that a certain action will lead to E you are moved to perform that action."3 In a similar spirit4 Nagel claims, contrary to Hume, that there do exist at least some cases (for example, actions motivated by a person's prudential consideration of his own future interests) in which reason alone—that is, the agent's grasp of certain purely rational considerations—is all that motivates action. In the context of these purely rationally motivated actions, Nagel argues, our talk of desire does not refef to anyadditional inclination towards, or preferences for, or sentiment about some goal that we have, but is either just another way of saying that the act is motivated, that is, that we are in some state which disposes us to do whatever we think will lead to a certain result, or else indicates some structural feature ofthe reasoningbehind our behaviour; for example, indicates the fact that in view of purely rational considerations which confront us, it would be irrational of us not to perform the act in question. Volume XVII Number 2 19DANIELSHAW Against any such account ofmotivating desire which denies the necessity of the experiential component (that is, of Hume's introspectible sentiment), I argued that all such accounts have a false implication. They all falsely imply that some purely rational consideration, a bare behef, could, all on its own (unaccompanied by any actual or potential pro- or con-attitude), motivate a purposive action. With the help ofa counter-example I argued5 that although it is logically possible for bare beliefs of that kind to produce overt behaviour, such pure rationalist 'action' never in fact happens; and, more importantly, ifwe carefully consider what such 'action' would be like ifit didhappen, we findit would not count as voluntary, purposive action, in the fullest sense. So Hume, I concluded, was right to maintain that motivating desire essentially involves introspectible feehngs. However, the standard interpretation of Hume's view about the relation between desires and feelings yields an indefensible theory of motivated action. On the standard reading, desires simply are feehngs, and the Humean is left with no adequate reply to the obvious objection that, often enough, for example, when acting after calm deliberation, or when performing routine habit-actions, we are not aware of the occurrence of any such feehng immediately prior to or at the time of action. Hume tells us that in all such cases there is—in addition to the operation of reason—a calm passion present—a passion so calm as to be readily confused with and mistaken for the determinations of reason. But on the standard reading of 'calm passions' as very faint or imperceptible feelings, this is a lame argument. As Stroud points out,6 not only is there no independent justification for the claim that in all such cases there always are such faint or imperceptible feehngs,7 but also that claim is inconsistent... (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  229
    Absurdity and Suicide.DanielShaw -1985 -Philosophy Research Archives 11:209-223.
    Camus’ central thesis in The Myth of Sisyphus is that suicide is not the proper response to, nor is it the solution of, the problem of absurdity. Yet many of his literary protagonists either commit suicide or are self-destructive in other ways. I argue that the protagonists that best live up to the characteristics of the absurd man that Camus outlines in the Myth uniformly either commit suicide or consent to their destruction by behaving in such a manner as to (...) invite death. It is my contention that this raises serious questions abuut the validity of Camus’ arguments that suicide is not the proper response to the recognition that life is absurd. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  48
    Reason and Feeling in Hume's Action Theory and Moral Philosophy.DanielShaw -1992 -Hume Studies 18 (2):349-367.
  30.  62
    The relationship between joint attention and theory of mind in neurotypical adults.Jordan A.Shaw,Lauren K. Bryant,Bertram F. Malle,Daniel J. Povinelli &John R. Pruett -2017 -Consciousness and Cognition 51:268-278.
    Joint attention (JA) is hypothesized to have a close relationship with developing theory of mind (ToM) capabilities. We tested the co-occurrence of ToM and JA in social interactions between adults with no reported history of psychiatric illness or neurodevelopmental disorders. Participants engaged in an experimental task that encouraged nonverbal communication, including JA, and also ToM activity. We adapted an in-lab variant of experience sampling methods (Bryant, Coffey, Povinelli, & Pruett, 2013) to measure ToM during JA based on participants’ subjective reports (...) of their thoughts while performing the task. This experiment successfully elicited instances of JA in 17/20 dyads. We compared participants’ thought contents during episodes of JA and non-JA. Our results suggest that, in adults, JA and ToM may occur independently. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  40
    Stanley Cavell on the Magic of the Movies.DanielShaw -2017 -Film-Philosophy 21 (1):114-132.
    In order to explain Cavell's account of what makes movies so magical, this article will offer a chronological survey of his major writings on film, beginning with the first edition of The World Viewed (1971), where he poses an intriguing theoretical hypothesis about what distinguishes the movies from the other major art forms. The survey will continue by considering the expanded edition of The World Viewed (1979), Pursuits of Happiness: The Hollywood Comedy of Remarriage (1984), and Contesting Tears: The Hollywood (...) Melodrama of the Unknown Woman (1997), and will conclude with an analysis of Cavell's discussion of Emersonian perfectionism in Cities of Words (2005). Throughout, I show how the specific film interpretations he proposes serve as archetypal examples of crucial features of his philosophy. Cavell's general thesis, I take it, is that films can pose particularly satisfying responses to the skepticism we all harbour about our most deeply held values. In a nutshell, the movies are magical because they tell us myths that allow us to see our lives as worth living, helping to restore our faith in the wellsprings of human value: romantic love, individual autonomy, nonconformity, and the search for self-improvement. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  52
    A Rejoinder to Noèl Carrol's The Philosophy of Motion Pictures.DanielShaw -2008 -Film-Philosophy 12 (2):142-151.
    Direct download(10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  42
    Set-theoretic blockchains.Miha E. Habič,Joel David Hamkins,LukasDaniel Klausner,Jonathan Verner &Kameryn J. Williams -2019 -Archive for Mathematical Logic 58 (7-8):965-997.
    Given a countable model of set theory, we study the structure of its generic multiverse, the collection of its forcing extensions and ground models, ordered by inclusion. Mostowski showed that any finite poset embeds into the generic multiverse while preserving the nonexistence of upper bounds. We obtain several improvements of his result, using what we call the blockchain construction to build generic objects with varying degrees of mutual genericity. The method accommodates certain infinite posets, and we can realize these embeddings (...) via a wide variety of forcing notions, while providing control over lower bounds as well. We also give a generalization to class forcing in the context of second-order set theory, and exhibit some further structure in the generic multiverse, such as the existence of exact pairs. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  34.  37
    A Kuhnian metatheory for aesthetics.DanielShaw -1986 -Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 45 (1):29-39.
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  103
    A humean definition of horror.DanielShaw -1997 -Film-Philosophy 1 (1).
    on The Philosophy of Horror by Noel Carroll.
    Direct download(11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36.  76
    The birth of a killer.DanielShaw -2009 -The Philosophers' Magazine 47 (47):67-72.
    If Lecter is merely a psychotic, with no choice but to do what he does, then he is to be pitied, not blamed for his actions. As soon as you start pitying him, thespell is broken and he ceases to be mesmerising. If he can’t control himself, he appears to be much less powerful as a result.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  17
    The Need for Interpretation.DanielShaw -1984 -Philosophical Books 25 (1):36-38.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  15
    A Philosophical Account of the Nature of Art Appreciation.DanielShaw -2000 - Edwin Mellen Press.
    The book has three main aims. The first is give a philosophical account of the nature of art appreciation, as well as, aesthetic appreciation outside the arts. The second aim is to examine the ways in which the artist's intention is relevant to interpreting, appreciating and evaluating works of art. Finally, to explore some of the ways that certain works of art can provide a unique form of understanding of human behavior or morality and of life.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  17
    Contemporary Aesthetics: A Philosophical Analysis.DanielShaw -1984 -Philosophical Books 25 (4):247-249.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  39
    Nietzsche as Sophist.Daniel C.Shaw -1986 -International Philosophical Quarterly 26 (4):331-339.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  29
    Philosophical Aesthetics: An Introduction.Daniel J.Shaw -1994 -Philosophical Books 35 (3):217-219.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  45
    Where the Gods Dwell: a Research Report.Justin L. Barrett,R.DanielShaw,Joseph Pfeiffer &Jonathan Grimes -2019 -Journal of Cognition and Culture 19 (1-2):131-146.
    Are the places that superhuman beings purportedly act and dwell randomly or arbitrarily distributed? Inspired by theoretical work in cognitive science of religion, descriptions of superhuman beings were solicited from informants in 20 countries on five continents, resulting in 108 usable descriptions, including information about these beings’ properties, their dwelling location, and whether they were the target of rituals. Whether superhuman beings are the subject of religious and ritual practices appeared to co-vary in relation to both features of physical geography (...) and cognitive factors. Good gods were more likely the focus of religious practices than evil gods, and where the gods are thought to dwell mattered. If either the being was thought to dwell in a dangerous place or a resource rich place, it was more likely to have practices directed at it. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  21
    Comparing Tactile to Auditory Guidance for Blind Individuals.Arnav Bharadwaj,Saurabh BhaskarShaw &Daniel Goldreich -2019 -Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 13.
  44.  17
    Danto and His Critics.Daniel J.Shaw -1996 -Philosophical Books 37 (4):277-280.
  45. 'Dead Ringers.DanielShaw -1996 -Film & Philosophy (Society for the Philosophic Study of the Contemporary Visual Arts) 3.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  24
    Editor’s Introduction.DanielShaw -2020 -Film and Philosophy 24:2-4.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  16
    (8 other versions)Editor's Introduction.DanielShaw -2001 -Film and Philosophy 4:3-4.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  31
    Essays on Davidson: Actions and Events.Daniel J.Shaw -1986 -Philosophical Books 27 (3):174-178.
  49.  16
    Philosophical Tales.DanielShaw -1989 -Philosophical Books 30 (4):217-218.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  20
    The Nature of Philosophy.Daniel J.Shaw -1982 -Philosophical Books 23 (1):28-30.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 938
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp