Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'Constantine Nicholas Stavrou'

921 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  41
    (1 other version)Mental transportation mediates nostalgia’s psychological benefits.Nicholas D. Evans,Joseph Reyes,Tim Wildschut,Constantine Sedikides &Adam K. Fetterman -forthcoming -Tandf: Cognition and Emotion:1-12.
  2.  95
    A Conversation with NassimNicholas Taleb.Constantine Sandis -2008 -Philosophy Now 69:26-28.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  154
    The limits of ignorance:Nicholas Rescher: Ignorance: On the wider implications of deficient knowledge. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 2009, 160pp, £17.95 HB.Constantine Sandis -2011 -Metascience 21 (2):483-484.
    The limits of ignorance Content Type Journal Article Pages 1-2 DOI 10.1007/s11016-011-9571-z AuthorsConstantine Sandis, Westminster Institute of Education, Oxford Brookes University, Harcourt Hill Campus, Oxford, OX2 9AT UK Journal Metascience Online ISSN 1467-9981 Print ISSN 0815-0796.
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  19
    Constantin VII Porphyrogénète, Le livre des cérémonies, bespr. von Marek Jankowiak.Gilbert Dagron,Bernard Flusin,Denis Feissel &MichelStavrou -2023 -Byzantinische Zeitschrift 116 (3):1075-1095.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  33
    Columbia Companion to Twentieth-Century Philosophies.Constantin V. Boundas (ed.) -2007 - Columbia University Press.
    _Columbia Companion to Twentieth-Century Philosophies_ is the first guide to cover both the Anglo-American analytic and European continental traditions. Organized thematically, the volume thoroughly discusses the major movements and fields of each tradition and features the contributions of highly distinguished specialists in their fields. This book is divided into three sections. The first is devoted to highlighting the multidimensional work of philosophers identified with the analytic tradition, withNicholas Rescher writing on neoidealism, Josephine Donovan commenting on feminist philosophy, Tyler (...) Burge discussing the philosophy of language and mind, and Robert Hanna reflecting on Kant's legacy. The second section presents the thought of those who identified themselves with the continental tradition, featuring Jean Grondin on hermeneutics, Leonard Lawlor on phenomenology, Charles Scott on postmodernism, and Babette Babich on the philosophy of science. This volume also covers logical positivism, naturalism, pragmatism, aesthetics, existentialism, Marxism, the Frankfurt School, structuralism, psychoanalysis, political philosophy, ethics, and the philosophy of religion. The final section addresses concurrent trends in Indian, Chinese, Japanese, and African philosophy, and a comprehensive introduction by the editor not only provides a thorough outline of the problems and issues of the analytic and continental traditions but also boldly challenges the conviction that the two approaches must be rivals. _Columbia Companion to Twentieth-Century Philosophies_ is an invaluable overview of the ideas that have shaped a monumentally important century in the history of philosophy, offering an unusually panoramic perspective that allows readers to form their own interpretations of original materials. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  19
    Religion in the age ofConstantine - (m.) Edwards religions of the Constantinian empire. Pp. XIV + 365. Oxford: Oxford university press, 2015. Cased, £30, us$49.50. Isbn: 978-0-19-968772-5. [REVIEW]Nicholas J. Baker-Brian -2018 -The Classical Review 68 (1):191-192.
  7.  30
    Lorenzo Valla's Oratio on the Pseudo-Donation ofConstantine: Dissent and Innovation in Early Renaissance Humanism.William J. Connell -1996 -Journal of the History of Ideas 57 (1):1-7.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:IntroductionWilliam J. ConnellOne of the more unusual works in the corpus of the Italian humanist Lorenzo Valla is the Oratio in principio sui studii, on the relation between Latin letters and the Christian faith. The speech was written and delivered in October 1455, toward the end of Valla’s life, as a lecture to inaugurate the academic year at the University of Rome where he had held the chair in (...) rhetoric since 1450. It was traditional at Rome to hold such an address each year not only to encourage the assembled students and faculty in their studies but also to thank the papacy for its support of the university, the Studium Urbis. For this reason Valla’s speech ends with customary words praising Pope Calixtus III for having increased the stipends of the lecturers in the university, even though, notwithstanding some remarkable kindnesses to Valla himself, Calixtus’s reputation was not that of a friend to scholarship. Valla’s Schoolyear Inaugural was not lengthy: it can only have lasted fifteen minutes. Nor is there indication that anyone was displeased with it. In fact, that is precisely what is oddest about the Inaugural, for throughout his career Valla had shown himself to be the sort of person who seized on such occasions to make polemical arguments. We read the speech—and it is possible that his audience also listened to it this way—expecting with each step that Valla will let fly a critical or unorthodox statement, but that never happens. 1Beginning with his earliest formal work, a comparison of Cicero and Quintilian written in 1428 and now lost, in which the humanist argued against Cicero on behalf of Quintilian, Valla seemed to delight in challenging established authorities. 2 His next important work, an attack on Bartolus of [End Page 1] Sassoferrato and the scholastic method of contemporary jurists, resulted in his forced departure from the University of Pavia. 3 A continuing combativeness is illustrated in subsequent writings, reaching an apogee in the work on the Donation. Even when Valla was developing another writer’s idea, he had a consistent way of pushing the argument to a daring extreme. This, as Riccardo Fubini argues below, is what Valla did in the De donatione, a work Fubini suggests relied more heavily onNicholas of Cusa’s De concordantia catholica than hitherto realized, but written to promote an agenda far more radical than that of Cusanus. One of the surest indications of Valla’s brilliance as a polemicist is the fact that seventy years after his death humanists of the caliber of Agostino Steuco, the subject of Ronald K. Delph’s essay in this number, were still eager to take up cudgels against him.Valla paid a price for initiating so many disputes. In 1444, when he was called before the Inquisition in Naples after the attack on the Donation ofConstantine, Valla was made to answer charges against not only that work, but also against the De vero bono for its Epicureanism, the De libero arbitrio for its determinism, the De professione religiosorum for its criticism of religious orders, and the Repastinatio totius dialectice et philosophie for various unorthodox statements, especially concerning the Trinity. This last work was the humanist’s most ambitious project, and he seems to have been aware of its explosive quality, since he alluded to a “peril to his life” should it be published. 4The 1455 Schoolyear Inaugural shows no trace of the risks that Valla took in his other writings, of his polemical temperament, or of his past disagreements with the Church. With style and vigor the speech argues that the Church deserves great thanks and praise for having ensured the survival [End Page 2] of Latin letters after the collapse of the Empire. This may seem a notable change of heart in the author who had written the oration On the Falsely Believed and Forged Donation of Constantin—a text which always seems to be lurking in the background of the Inaugural but which finds no explicit reference there. Given the proximity of Valla’s argument to the well-worn medieval theme of the translatio studii, his argument could hardly have been... (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  87
    Lorenzo Valla's "Oratio" on the Pseudo-Donation ofConstantine: Dissent and Innovation in Early Renaissance Humanism.Salvatore I. Camporeale -1996 -Journal of the History of Ideas 57 (1):9.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Lorenzo Valla’s Oratio on the Pseudo-Donation ofConstantine: Dissent and Innovation in Early Renaissance HumanismSalvatore I. CamporealeWhy did I write about the Donation ofConstantine?... Bear one thing in mind. I was not moved by hatred of the Pope, but acted for the sake of the truth, of religion, and also of a certain renown—to show that I alone knew what no one else knew.Valla to Cardinal (...) Trevisan, 1443. 1Lorenzo Valla’s well known work, the Oration on the Falsely-Believed and Forged Donation ofConstantine, was written by the humanist in the year 1440. It was occasioned by the strife between Pope Eugenius IV and Alfonso of Aragon over the Kingdom of Naples. Valla wrote in favor of the Ara-gonese claim, arguing against pretensions of the Papacy to determine who should rule Naples that were based on the pseudo-Constantinian Donation. 2 [End Page 9]The Donation ofConstantine: History and ForgeryAs is now well known, the Constitutum Constantini was a forgery that probably originated in the papal Curia in the eighth century. Subsequently it was often contested by the anti-papal Germanic Imperial tradition. The Constitutum portrayed the popes as assuming the role of the Emperor in the western part of the Empire as a result of the “donation” made byConstantine to the “Roman Pontiff and his successors.” The Donation was said to have taken place at a time subsequent toConstantine’s seizure of the city of Rome with the victory at the Milvian Bridge in a.d. 312, and immediately after his “conversion” to the Christian faith and his “reception of baptism” by the bishop of Rome, Pope (“Saint”) Sylvester.The Constitutum presents itself as an imperial decree, drafted and signed byConstantine himself, dated in Rome with an ambiguous formulation which could indicate the year 315 or 317 or even 330. The most significant and comprehensive passage of the entire document reads as follows:In order that the supreme pontificate may not deteriorate, but may rather be adorned with glory and power even greater than the dignity of earthly rule, behold, we give over and relinquish to the aforesaid our most blessed Pontiff, Sylvester, the universal Pope, our palace, as has been said, and also the city of Rome, and all the provinces, places and cities of Italy and the western regions, and we decree by this our godlike and pragmatic sanction that they are to be controlled by him and by his successors, and we grant that they shall remain under the law of the Holy Roman Church. 3The forgery was based an on older fictional source, the Legenda Sylvestri. It was later (at least as maintained first byNicholas of Cusa, then by Valla) introduced by the canonist Paucapalea (Gratian’s disciple and collaborator) into the collection of canon law that had been made by Gratian, the Concordantia discordantium canonum, or Decretum (c. 1140). 4 Assertions that the Constitutum derived from the Legenda and that it was a later [End Page 10] insertion into the Concordantia represent discrete stages of Valla’s philological procedure. In fact Valla’s argumentation evolves in a kind of concentric movement. After discussing the hagiographic “fiction” of the Legenda, he treats the canonical “inauthenticity” of the Constitutum as a later insertion into the Concordantia. Then Valla returns to the notion that it was “made up” or “fictional” when he declares the Constitutum a juridical “forgery.” 5Valla’s Methodology and Argumentative ProcedureThe Oratio—this was how Valla titled his work—is a confutative discourse, rhetorically structured in the epideictic mode, although particular passages also assume forensic and deliberative modes. The oration was written in accordance with rhetorical norms for investigation and argumentation that Valla had learned from and elaborated on the Institutio oratoria of Quintilian, the writer Valla considered preeminent in the rhetorical tradition. 6“This speech of mine,” Valla emphasizes, is a speech intended for and offered to the universal assembly of Christendom. Although directly addressing the Papacy and in particular the ruling pope, Eugenius IV, the “oration” is conceived as though delivered in the presence of both the ecclesiastical hierarchy and civil authorities (“quasi... (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  14
    You'd Better Watch out….Will Williams -2010 - In Scott C. Lowe,Christmas: Philosophy For Everyone. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 114–124.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Ho, Ho, History Arius and Theological Controversy The Council of Nicaea – a Jolly Occasion Float like an Acolyte, Sting like the See Does Theology Really Matter? Here Comes Santa Claus – into the Twenty‐First Century TheNicholas of History and the Santa of Faith?
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  211
    Verbal Reports and ‘Real’ Reasons: Confabulation and Conflation.Constantine Sandis -2015 -Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18 (2):267-280.
    This paper examines the relation between the various forces which underlie human action and verbal reports about our reasons for acting as we did. I maintain that much of the psychological literature on confabulations rests on a dangerous conflation of the reasons for which people act with a variety of distinct motivational factors. In particular, I argue that subjects frequently give correct answers to questions about the considerations they acted upon while remaining largely unaware of why they take themselves to (...) have such reasons to act. Pari passu, experimental psychologists are wrong to maintain that they have shown our everyday reason talk to be systematically confused. This is significant because our everyday reason-ascriptions affect characterizations of action that are morally and legally relevant. I conclude, more positively, that far from rendering empirical research on confabulations invalid, my account helps to reveal its true insights into human nature. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  11.  39
    Transformative change in Invasion of the Body Snatchers.Nicholas Agar -2018 -Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 21 (3):279-286.
    Transformation is a memorable feature of some of the most iconic works of science fiction. These works feature characters who begin as humans and change into radically different kinds of being. This paper examines transformative change in the context of the Invasion of the Body Snatchers movies. I discuss how humans should approach the prospect of being body snatched. I argue that we shouldn’t welcome the transformation even if we are convinced that we will have very positive experiences as pod (...) aliens. When considering a transformative change, it is appropriate to give priority to your pre-transformation attitudes to potential future experiences and achievements over your predicted post-transformation attitudes. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12. Essays in Philosophical Analysis.Nicholas Rescher -1969 -Foundations of Language 11 (3):471-476.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  13.  17
    An algorithm for probabilistic planning.Nicholas Kushmerick,Steve Hanks &Daniel S. Weld -1995 -Artificial Intelligence 76 (1-2):239-286.
  14. 4 Hermeneutics and Nietzsche's early thought.Nicholas Davey -1991 - In Keith Ansell-Pearson,Nietzsche and Modern German Thought. New York: Routledge. pp. 88.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Ėticheskie problemy sovremennogo Kitai︠a︡.GeorgeConstantine Guins -1927
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  24
    Capitalism and the Camera: Essays on Photography and Extraction, Kevin Coleman and Daniel James (eds) (2021).SimonConstantine -2023 -Philosophy of Photography 14 (1):124-128.
    Review of: Capitalism and the Camera: Essays on Photography and Extraction, Kevin Coleman and Daniel James (eds) (2021) London and New York: Verso, 320 pp., ISBN 978-1-83976-080-8, p/bk, GBP 19.99.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  45
    Imperfect informed consent for prenatal screening: Lessons from the Quad screen.M.Constantine,M. Allyse,M. Wall,R. D. Vries &T. Rockwood -2014 -Clinical Ethics 9 (1):17-27.
    Objective The study evaluated patient informed consent (IC) for the Quad screen and examined differences in IC between test acceptors and test refusers. A multidimensional model of IC was used. Methods Women seeking prenatal care at nine obstetrics clinics in a large Midwestern city completed surveys between February and December 2006. Surveys contained measures for three dimensions of IC: intention, understanding and controlling influence. Results 56.2% of women did not meet criteria for all three of our dimensions of IC and (...) therefore failed to give it. The failure rate was higher among women who choose to screen (72.6%) than women who choose not screen (50%) (p< 0.001). Women who met all criteria for IC were over three times less likley to choose to screen (or = 0.32, CI 0.17–0.62 ( p< 0.01)) than women who did not meet criteria for IC. Conclusion The decision to screen for fetal anomalies is less of a deliberated action than the decision not to screen. Women who lack a fundamental understanding of the purpose and nature of the screen may be operating on the belief that the screen is part of standard care and presents no need to deliberate. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18.  31
    Getting and spending1.Nicholas Abercrombie -2000 -Cultural Values 4 (3):374-382.
    . Getting and spending. Cultural Values: Vol. 4, No. 3, pp. 374-382.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  85
    Belief as the Power to Judge.Nicholas Koziolek -2020 -Topoi 39 (5):1167-1176.
    A number of metaphysicians of powers have argued that we need to distinguish the actualization of a power from the effects of that actualization. This distinction, I argue, has important consequences for the dispositional theory of belief. In particular, it suggests that dispositionalists have in effect been trying to define belief, not in terms of its actualization, but instead in terms of the effects of its actualization. As a general rule, however, powers are to be defined in terms of their (...) actualizations. I thus argue that belief has just one actualization, and that that actualization is a particular kind of mental act that I call a judgment. I explain the resulting view—that belief is the power to judge—and argue that it has some important advantages, not only over other dispositional theories of belief, but also over categorical theories of belief. Since these options are apparently exhaustive, it thus has important advantages over all other theories of belief. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20.  25
    Response to Christopher Insole’sKant and the Divine: From Contemplation to the Moral Law(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020).Nicholas Adams -2021 -Studies in Christian Ethics 34 (3):293-297.
    This is a response given at the book launch for Christopher Insole’s Kant and the Divine: From Contemplation to the Moral Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020), hosted jointly, in November 2020, by the Centre for Catholic Studies, Durham University, and the Australian Catholic University. The response considers the gap between the textual Kant (as set out by Insole), and the received Kant, and reflects on how theologians have been too quick either to condemn and dismiss (a poorly interpreted) Kant, (...) or to rehabilitate Kant for theological projects, which Kant would have been opposed to, given his deepest philosophical commitments. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  10
    Utopia and Reality: Modernity in Sweden 1900-1960.Nicholas Adams -2006 -Utopian Studies 17 (1):289-292.
  22.  18
    Chomsky's “Galilean” Explanatory Style 1.Nicholas Allott,Terje Lohndal &Georges Rey -2021 - In Nicholas Allott, Terje Lohndal & Georges Rey,A Companion to Chomsky. Wiley. pp. 515–528.
    Noam Chomsky pursues a methodology in linguistics that abstracts from substantial amounts of data about actual language use in a way that has met considerable resistance from many other linguists. This chapter argues that Chomsky's observation in fact accords with good explanatory practice elsewhere in science, but it does conflict with a traditional methodology in linguistics. It's striking that the main features of Chomsky's Galilean style are independently taken to be rather obvious features of scientific method in contemporary philosophy of (...) science. The chapter first looks in more detail at the roles that idealization plays in contemporary generative grammar. It then proceeds to explore the congruence between the Galilean style in linguistics and aspects of good scientific methodology. Finally, the chapter sets out and responds briefly to some of the arguments that have been raised against the Galilean style. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Legal speech and the elements of adjudication.Nicholas Allott &Benjamin Shaer -2017 - In Brian G. Slocum,The nature of legal interpretation: what jurists can learn about legal interpretation from linguistics and philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  15
    “Le système de John Law” and the Spectre of Modern Despotism in the Political Thought of Montesquieu.Constantine Vassiliou -2019 -Lumen: Selected Proceedings From the Canadian Society for Eighteenth-Century Studies 38:161.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  14
    The Spirit of Montesquieu’s Persian Letters.Constantine Christos Vassiliou,Jeffrey Church &Alin Fumurescu (eds.) -2023 - Lexington Books.
    The Spirit of Montesquieu’s Persian Letters explores Montesquieu’s careful treatment of the spiritual, ethical, and civic dilemmas France encountered in the early 18th Century. In examining Montesquieu’s response to Bourbon France’s commercial and political culture of this time, it will help deepen our understanding of his political philosophy.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  6
    Introducing the Concept.Nicholas White -2006 - InA Brief History of Happiness. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 1–5.
    This chapter contains section titled: Plural and Conflicting Aims Note.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  18
    Pan Yue's “Study of a Widow” and Its Predecessors.Nicholas Morrow Williams -2012 -Journal of the American Oriental Society 132 (3):347.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  134
    One Fell Swoop.Constantine Sandis -2015 -Journal of the Philosophy of History 9 (3):372-392.
    _ Source: _Volume 9, Issue 3, pp 372 - 392 In this essay I revisit some anti-causalist arguments relating to reason-giving explanations of action put forth by numerous philosophers writing in the late ‘50s and early ‘60s in what Donald Davidson dismissively described as a ‘neo-Wittgensteinian current of small red books’. While chiefly remembered for subscribing to what has come to be called the ‘logical connection’ argument, the positions defended across these volumes are in fact as diverse as they are (...) subtle, united largely by a an anti-scientistic spirit which may reasonably be described as historicist. I argue that while Davidson’s causalist attack was motivated by an important explanatory insight borrowed from Hempel, it caused serious damage to the philosophy of action by effectively brushing over a number of vital distinctions made in the aforementioned works. In seeking to revive these I propose an approach to the theory of action explanation that rescues the anti-causalist baby from the historicist bathwater. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  237
    The objects of action explanation.Constantine Sandis -2012 -Ratio 25 (3):326-344.
    This paper distinguishes between various different conceptions of behaviour and action before exploring an accompanying variety of distinct things that ‘action explanation’ may plausibly amount to viz. different objectives of action explanation. I argue that a large majority of philosophers are guilty of conflating many of these, consequently offering inadequate accounts of the relation between actions and our reasons for performing them. The paper ends with the suggestion that we would do well to opt for a pluralistic understanding of action (...) and its explanations. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30. From Physics to Philosophy.Jeremy Butterfield &Constantine Pagonis -2002 -Philosophical Quarterly 52 (207):268-272.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  47
    The Proper Place for External Motivations for Sport and Why They Need Not Subvert Its Internal Goods.Nicholas Dixon -2018 -Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 12 (4):361-374.
  32.  11
    The Role of Truth in Social Justice Education … and Elsewhere1.Nicholas Burbules -2016 -Philosophy of Education 72:15-18.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  11
    The Motion of the Earth.Nicholas Copernicus -2009 - In Timothy McGrew, Marc Alspector-Kelly & Fritz Allhoff,The philosophy of science: an historical anthology. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 112.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  53
    Aesthetic Reasoning: A Hermeneutic Approach.Nicholas Davey -2013 -Nordic Journal of Aesthetics 23 (46).
    This essay considers the foundations of reasonable evaluation in the arts. These we argue concern the relations that constitute our experience of art, and the ontology of the art work itself. The being of the artwork, the experience and the interpretation of it all involve over-lapping modes of part–whole relations. The experience of meaningfulness is not an experience of a singular object or framework of meaning as closed and complete but an experience of relational meaning whereby exposure to one set (...) of meaningful relations transforms another in an on-going and open manner. This suggests that the experience of art itself provides the norms for reasonableness of evaluation. These norms are not rules in the sense of offering a method. They are characteristic of the features of an experience of meaningfulness itself. The essay suggests that the reasonableness of a response to a work can be considered in terms of its appropriacy relative to the context of its own horizon and the horizon surrounding the production of the work; its plausibility, that is, its internal coherence and consistency as a reading; whether the structure of the response is consistent with, supplements, or expands the intelligible content of the work; and whether it gives a sense of the latent possibilities still held within a work and intimates where the movement of a work’s subject-matter might. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Periphrasis: The Role of Syntax and Morphology in Paradigms.EvansNicholas -2012
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. James C. Edwards, The Authority of Language: Heidegger, Wittgenstein, and the Threat of Philosophical Nihilism Reviewed by.Nicholas F. Gier -1991 -Philosophy in Review 11 (3):181-183.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Late modern civil society.Nicholas Onuf -2005 - In Randall D. Germain & Michael Kenny,The idea of global civil society: politics and ethics in a globalizing era. New York: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  30
    Transitional Passages.Nicholas Poburko -2001 -Renascence 54 (1):23-45.
  39.  19
    Archives and the Boundaries of Early Modern Science.Nicholas Popper -2016 -Isis 107 (1):86-94.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  37
    (1 other version)A moderate among radicals: Timofei nikolaevich granovskii.Nicholas S. Racheotes -1982 -Studies in East European Thought 24 (2):117-146.
  41.  30
    Business Managers in Ancient Rome: A Social and Economic Study of Institores, 200 B.C.-A.D. 250 (review).Nicholas K. Rauh -1996 -American Journal of Philology 117 (3):501-504.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Business Managers in Ancient Rome: A Social and Economic Study of Institores, 200 B.C.–A.D. 250Nicholas K. RauhJean-Jacques Aubert. Business Managers in Ancient Rome: A Social and Economic Study of Institores, 200 B.C.–A.D. 250. Leiden, New York, and Köln: E. J. Brill, 1994. xvi + 520 pp. Cloth, Gld. 220, $125.75 (US). (Columbia Studies in the Classical Tradition, Volume XXI.)Aubert’s declared purpose in this study is to examine the (...) world of Roman business managers (institores)—their social background and status, their role as managers within business enterprises, and their ensuing relations with workers, entrepreneurs, suppliers, and customers. He pursues these themes through five chapters. Chapter 1, “Business Agents and Business Managers,” explores developments in the use and meaning of the term institor through the legal, literary, papyrological, and epigraphical source materials of Republican and Imperial Rome. Chapter 2, “Indirect Agency in Roman Law,” examines the evolution of the Roman laws of indirect agency (particularly the actiones adiecticiae qualitatis) from their inception through the classical jurists to show how Roman law was adjusted to accommodate the needs of the business community. Chapter 3, “Managers of Agricultural Estates,” traces the roots of the Roman system of indirect agency to the management of agricultural estates and to the exploitation of natural resources such as clay, quarries, and manufacturing activities on the Roman farmstead. Chapter 4, “Production and Distribution of Clay Artifacts,” examines the manager’s role in the organization of various types of workshops producing clay artifacts—bricks and tiles, amphoras, terra sigillata, and terracotta lamps—and the subsequent marketing of this production. Chapter 5, “Direct Management and Public Administration: Four Case Studies,” investigates how the vilicus-based system of management became adapted to four areas of [End Page 501] the economy and administration of the Roman empire—imperial tax collection (vectigalia), recreational facilities (including baths, libraries, theaters, amphitheaters, and circuses), the imperial communications system (roads, post, and transport services), and the imperial mint. This cursory outline of A.’s intentions serves to demonstrate the breadth and importance of the task he assumes. In my opinion he handles this with a tremendous degree of authority and even-handedness.A.’s overarching theses are 1) that indirect agency emerged through the increasing absentee management of Roman farm operations and the delegation of Roman estate management to the agent known as the vilicus, 2) that regardless of the type of industry, most managerial operations exploited the practical efficiency and accountability of this vilicus-based system, and 3) that overall developments in Roman business management progressed from a more restrictive reliance on agents directly subservient to the entrepreneur (generally young slaves or family members under the direct potestas of the proprietor) to a more liberal reliance on managers enjoying looser personal connections—freedmen, servi alieni, and freeborn nonrelatives whose services were ensured by the terms of consensual contracts. One of the main points of the first chapter, for example, is the limited quantity of information there is available for institores and the generally derogatory tone it bears. We learn later on that institores were, in fact, relatively few in number and ill-liked precisely because they were so independent (175), and that far more business managers are recorded as vilici precisely because entrepreneurs could more firmly control them.A. argues that due to its extreme formalism rooted in the archaic period, Roman law lacked the concept of direct agency, and that the praetor responded to the needs of businesspeople by creating a legal system based on existing structures of Roman society (slavery and family) with advantages similar to those direct agency could otherwise have offered. With respect to the vilicus-based managerial system this was achieved through the legal fiction of the peculium, “the juristic existence of fictitious assets pertaining de facto to the dependent, but belonging de iure to the principal” (65). Terms of employment and guarantees of liability were inherently trickier for nondependent business agents and evolved during the second and first centuries b.c. through increased reliance on formulary procedure, and particularly through the development of consensual agreements. In this regard A. stresses the importance of the emergence of the... (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  23
    Review Articles.Nicholas Royle -2010 -Research in Phenomenology 40 (1):123-131.
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  45
    Some Remarks on Rovelli's "Why Gauge?".Nicholas Teh -unknown
    Rovelli's "Why Gauge?" offers a parable to show that gauge-dependent quantities have a modal and relational physical significance. We subject the morals of this parable to philosophical scrutiny and argue that, while his overarching point stands, there are subtle disanalogies between his parable and our best gauge theories, e.g. Yang-Mills theory and General Relativity.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  16
    Hoping against hope or Abraham's dilemma.Nicholas Lash -1994 -Modern Theology 10 (3):233-246.
  45.  41
    Abstraction and Dialectics.Nicholas Lobkowicz -1968 -Review of Metaphysics 21 (3):468 - 490.
    IN THIS PAPER I intend to suggest that the tantalizing notion of dialectics as found, for example, in Hegel might be approached by reflecting upon some aspects of the notion of abstraction as found, for example, in Aquinas. It is more or less by accident that the two thinkers I wish to discuss here are Aquinas and Hegel rather than Aristotle and Marx, or even Meinong and Theodor Adorno. It certainly is possible to compare two metaphysicians of the stature of (...) Aquinas and Hegel, particularly if one restricts oneself to a well-defined issue. However, in this paper I do not intend to advance any such comparison in the strict sense of the term. Rather, I would like to show that certain basic features of the Hegelian and post-Hegelian notion of dialectics can be understood as an attempt at avoiding certain conclusions that almost inevitably have to be drawn if one accepts the classical conception of abstraction. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  39
    The Jerusalem Problem: A Note on Legality.Constantine Rackauskas -1950 -Thought: Fordham University Quarterly 25 (1):100-114.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  69
    The Sociological Theories of the French Institutionalists.Nicholas Timasheff -1946 -Thought: Fordham University Quarterly 21 (3):493-512.
  48.  31
    Surveillance and Seeing: A New Way of Reading Mark 12:17, 'Give Back to Caesar..'.Nicholas Townsend -2014 -Studies in Christian Ethics 27 (1):79-90.
    Stoddart writes that the God of Christian faith ‘knew [surveillance’s] gaze [and] suffered its harsh consequences’. That was especially so during the last week of Jesus’ life, when the religious/political leaders engaged him in tension-filled exchanges. Employing Stoddart’s concept of ‘(in)visibility’, I propose a new way of reading the controversy about Roman tax which, taking up insights in Myers’s ‘political’ commentary, shows connections between this text and those immediately preceding it. Jesus makes central in the engagement about tax the same (...) issue as is already at stake: identity and recognition. His ‘amazing’ response makes clear what the leaders are not seeing. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Thoughts about our species’ future: themes from Humanity’s End: Why We Should Reject Radical Enhancement.Nicholas Agar -2010 -Journal of Evolution and Technology 21 (2):23-31.
    This paper summarizes a couple of the main arguments from my new book, Humanity’s End. In the book I argue against radical enhancement – the adjustment of human attributes and abilities to levels that greatly exceed what is currently possible for human beings. I’m curious to see what reaction this elicits in a journal whose readership includes some of radical enhancement’s most imaginative and committed advocates.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Historical Actuality and Bodily Experience.Nicholas Beets -1966 -Humanitas 2:15-28.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 921
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp