Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'Cohen Jonathan'

926 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1. The expected value of control: an integrative theory of anterior cingulate cortex function.Amitai Shenhav,Matthew Botvinick &JonathanCohen -2013 -Neuron 79 (2):217–40.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  2.  391
    Color properties and color ascriptions: A relationalist manifesto.JonathanCohen -2004 -Philosophical Review 113 (4):451-506.
    Are colors relational or non-relational properties of their bearers? Is red a property that is instantiated by all and only the objects with a certain intrinsic (/non-relational) nature? Or does an object with a particular intrinsic (/non-relational) nature count as red only in virtue of standing in certain relations - for example, only when it looks a certain way to a certain perceiver, or only in certain circumstances of observation? In this paper I shall argue for the view that color (...) properties are relational (henceforth, relationalism), and against the view that colors are not relational (henceforth, anti- or non-relationalism). (shrink)
    Direct download(14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  3.  46
    Computation and the Ambiguity of Perception.JonathanCohen -2012 - In Gary Hatfield & Sarah Allred,Visual Experience: Sensation, Cognition, and Constancy. Oxford University Press. pp. 160.
  4. In Nietzsche's Footsteps (2nd edition).Jonathan R.Cohen -2018 - Montreal: 8th House.
    A philosophical travel memoir, discussing Nietzsche's life and philosophy while visiting his three favorite residences, Nice, Turin, and Sils-Maria.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. The experience of time.JonathanCohen -1954 -Acta Psychologica 10:207-19.
  6.  2
    Color relationalism and color phenomenology.JonathanCohen -2010 - In Bence Nanay,Perceiving the world. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 13.
    Color relationalism is the view that colors are constituted in terms of relations between subjects and objects. The most historically important form of color relationalism is the classic dispositionalist view according to which, for example red is the disposition to look red to standard observers in standard conditions (mutatis mutandis for other colors).1 However, it has become increasingly apparent in recent years that a commitment to the relationality of colors bears interest that goes beyond dispositionalism (Cohen, 2004; Matthen, 1999, (...) 2001, 2005; Thompson, 1995). Accordingly, it is an important project for those interested in the metaphysics of color to sort through and assess different forms of color relationalism. There is, however, a powerful and general cluster of objections that has been thought by many to amount to a decisive refutation of any and all forms of color relationalism. Although this idea has been developed in a number of ways, the basic thought is that relationalism — qua theory of color — is at odds with the manifest evidence of color phenomenology, and that this clash between theory and data should be resolved by giving up the theory. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  61
    On the control of automatic processes: A parallel distributed processing account of the Stroop effect.Jonathan D.Cohen,Kevin Dunbar &James L. McClelland -1990 -Psychological Review 97 (3):332-361.
  8.  170
    The Red and the Real: An Essay on Color Ontology.JonathanCohen -2009 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Color provides an instance of a general puzzle about how to reconcile the picture of the world given to us by our ordinary experience with the picture of the world given to us by our best theoretical accounts. The Red and the Real offers a new approach to such longstanding philosophical puzzles about what colors are and how they fit into nature. It is responsive to a broad range of constraints --- both the ordinary constraints of color experience and the (...) more theoretical constraints of color science, psychology, semantics, and ontology. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   138 citations  
  9.  237
    Colour constancy as counterfactual.JonathanCohen -2008 -Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86 (1):61 – 92.
    There is nothing in this World constant but Inconstancy. [Swift 1711: 258] In this paper I argue that two standard characterizations of colour constancy are inadequate to the phenomenon. This inadequacy matters, since, I contend, philosophical appeals to colour constancy as a way of motivating illumination-independent conceptions of colour turn crucially on the shortcomings of these characterizations. After critically reviewing the standard characterizations, I provide a novel counterfactualist understanding of colour constancy, argue that it avoids difficulties of its traditional rivals, (...) and defend it from objections. Finally, I show why, on this improved understanding, colour constancy does not have the philosophical consequences that have been claimed for it in the literature. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  10. Color.JonathanCohen -2009 - In Sarah Robins, John Symons & Paco Calvo,The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Psychology. New York, NY: Routledge.
    Questions about the ontology of color matter because colors matter. Colors are extremely pervasive and salient features of the world. Moreover, people care about the distribution of these features: they expend money and effort to paint their houses, cars, and other possessions, and their clear preference for polychromatic over monochromatic televisions and computer monitors have consigned monochromatic models to the status of rare antiques. The apparent ubiquity of colors and their importance to our lives makes them a ripe target for (...) ontological questions such as the following: " • What is the nature of colors? " • Are they, as they seem to be, properties of objects? (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  11.  139
    (2 other versions)Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind.Brian P. McLaughlin &JonathanCohen (eds.) -2007 - Wiley-Blackwell.
    Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind showcases the leading contributors to the field, debating the major questions in philosophy of mind today. Comprises 20 newly commissioned essays on hotly debated issues in the philosophy of mind Written by a cast of leading experts in their fields, essays take opposing views on 10 central contemporary debates A thorough introduction provides a comprehensive background to the issues explored Organized into three sections which explore the ontology of the mental, nature of the mental (...) content, and the nature of consciousness. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  12.  60
    Context, cortex, and dopamine: A connectionist approach to behavior and biology in schizophrenia.Jonathan D.Cohen &David Servan-Schreiber -1992 -Psychological Review 99 (1):45-77.
  13. Molyneux's Question and the History of Philosophy.JonathanCohen &Mohan Matthen (eds.) -2021 - London: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  305
    True colours.JonathanCohen,C. L. Hardin &Brian P. McLaughlin -2006 -Analysis 66 (4):335-340.
    (Tye 2006) presents us with the following scenario: John and Jane are both stan- dard human visual perceivers (according to the Ishihara test or the Farnsworth test, for example) viewing the same surface of Munsell chip 527 in standard conditions of visual observation. The surface of the chip looks “true blue” to John (i.e., it looks blue not tinged with any other colour to John), and blue tinged with green to Jane.1 Tye then in effect poses a multiple choice question.
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  15.  231
    Objects, places, and perception.JonathanCohen -2004 -Philosophical Psychology 17 (4):471-495.
    In Clark (2000), Austen Clark argues convincingly that a widespread view of perception as a complicated kind of feature-extraction is incomplete. He argues that perception has another crucial representational ingredient: it must also involve the representation of "sensory individuals" that exemplify sensorily extracted features. Moreover, he contends, the best way of understanding sensory individuals takes them to be places in space surrounding the perceiver. In this paper, I'll agree with Clark's case for sensory individuals (.
    Direct download(11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  16.  20
    Definition.JonathanCohen -1951 -Philosophical Quarterly 1 (1):80-81.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  17.  213
    An objective counterfactual theory of information.JonathanCohen &Aaron Meskin -2006 -Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (3):333 – 352.
    We offer a novel theory of information that differs from traditional accounts in two respects: (i) it explains information in terms of counterfactuals rather than conditional probabilities, and (ii) it does not make essential reference to doxastic states of subjects, and consequently allows for the sort of objective, reductive explanations of various notions in epistemology and philosophy of mind that many have wanted from an account of information.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  18.  583
    A better best system account of lawhood.JonathanCohen &Craig Callender -2009 -Philosophical Studies 145 (1):1 - 34.
    Perhaps the most significant contemporary theory of lawhood is the Best System (/MRL) view on which laws are true generalizations that best systematize knowledge. Our question in this paper will be how best to formulate a theory of this kind. We’ll argue that an acceptable MRL should (i) avoid inter-system comparisons of simplicity, strength, and balance, (ii) make lawhood epistemically accessible, and (iii) allow for laws in the special sciences. Attention to these problems will bring into focus a useful menu (...) of novel MRL theories, some of which solve problems the original MRL theory could not. Hence we conceive of the paper as moving toward a better Best System theory of laws. (shrink)
    Direct download(10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   178 citations  
  19.  515
    Conversational Eliciture.JonathanCohen &Andrew Kehler -2021 -Philosophers' Imprint 21 (12).
    The sentence "The boss fired the employee who is always late" invites the defeasible inference that the speaker is attempting to convey that the lateness caused the firing. We argue that such inferences cannot be understood in terms of familiar approaches to extrasemantic enrichment such as implicature, impliciture, explicature, or species of local enrichment already in the literature. Rather, we propose that they arise from more basic cognitive strategies, grounded in processes of coherence establishment, that thinkers use to make sense (...) of the world. Attention to such cases provides a richer and more varied landscape of extrasemantic enrichment than has been appreciated to date. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  20.  235
    A relationalist's guide to error about color perception.JonathanCohen -2007 -Noûs 41 (2):335–353.
    Color relationalism is the view that colors are constituted in terms of relations to perceiving subjects. Among its explanatory virtues, relation- alism provides a satisfying treatment of cases of perceptual variation. But it can seem that relationalists lack resources for saying that a representa- tion of x’s color is erroneous. Surely, though, a theory of color that makes errors of color perception impossible cannot be correct. In this paper I’ll argue that, initial appearances notwithstanding, relationalism contains the resources to account (...) for errors of color perception. I’ll conclude that worries about making room for error are worries the relationalist can meet. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  21.  325
    The grand grand illusion illusion.JonathanCohen -2002 -Journal of Consciousness Studies 9 (5-6):141-157.
    In recent years, a pair of intriguing phenomena has caused researchers working on vision and visual attention to reevaluate many of their assumptions. These phenomena, which have come to be called change blindness (CB) and inattentional blindness (IB), have led many to the conclusion that ordinary perceivers labor under a ``grand illusion'' concerning perception - an illusion that is..
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  22.  186
    On the structural properties of the colours.JonathanCohen -2003 -Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (1):78-95.
    Primary quality theories of color claim that colors are intrinsic, objective, mind-independent properties of external objects — that colors, like size and shape, are examples of the sort of properties moderns such as Boyle and Locke called primary qualities of body.1 Primary quality theories have long been seen as one of the main philosophical options for understanding the nature of color.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  23.  44
    What's for dinner?: Eating well and doing good.JonathanCohen -unknown
    Our choices about what to eat have crucial implications for our stomachs, the welfare of animals, the natural environment, the arrangement of our society, our pleasure, and our health. So a lot is hanging on our decisions about what we eat. Moreover, these are not merely hypothetical ivory tower cases: every one of us typically makes these decisions (or has them made on our behalf) several times daily!
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  165
    (1 other version)Perceptual Constancy.JonathanCohen -2015 - In Mohan Matthen,The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Perception. New York, NY: Oxford University Press UK. pp. 621-639.
    Students of perception have long known that perceptual constancy is an important aspect of our perceptual interaction with the world. Here is a simple example of the phenomenon concerning color perception: there is some ordinary sense in which an unpainted ceramic coffee cup made from a uniform material looks a uniform color when it is viewed under uneven illumination, even though the light reflected by the shaded regions to our eyes is quite different from the light reflected by the unshaded (...) regions to our eyes (see figure 1). Or consider this example concerning size perception: there is some ordinary sense in which two telephone poles look the same size when the first is viewed from 100 meters and when the second is viewed from 1 meter, even though the visual angle subtended by the two poles on our retinae is very different (see figure 2). Or consider this example concerning shape perception: there is some ordinary sense in which a penny looks round both when viewed head on and when viewed from an acute angle, even though the area projected by the penny onto our retinae under these two conditions is very different (see figure 3). Or, finally, consider this example concerning auditory volume perception (which I cannot depict graphically): there is some ordinary sense in which a speaker’s voice sounds the same volume when heard from across the room and when heard from a distance of 1 meter, even though the energy striking our ears under these two conditions is very different. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  25.  131
    Perceptual variation, realism, and relativization, or: How I learned to stop worrying and love variations in color vision.JonathanCohen -2003 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (1):25-26.
    In many cases of variation in color vision, there is no non-arbitrary way of choosing between variants. Byrne and Hilbert insist that there is an unknown standard for choosing, while eliminativists claim that all the variants are erroneous. A better response relativizes colors to perceivers, thereby providing a color realism that avoids the need to choose between variants.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  26.  218
    Color and perceptual variation revisited: Unknown facts, alien modalities, and perfect psychosemantics.JonathanCohen -2006 -Dialectica 60 (3):307-319.
    An adequate ontology of color must face the empirical facts about per- ceptual variation. In this paper I begin by reviewing a range of data about perceptual variation, and showing how they tell against color physicalism and motivate color relationalism. Next I consider a series of objections to the argument from perceptual variation, and argue that they are un- persuasive. My conclusion will be that the argument remains a powerful obstacle for color physicalism, and a powerful reason to believe in (...) color relationalism instead. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  27. Contemporary Debates in the Philosophy of Mind (2nd Edition).JonathanCohen &Brian McLaughlin (eds.) -forthcoming - Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  14
    Los Angeles, CA, USA.Jonathan D.Cohen,Fergus Im Craik,Ieffrey L. Cummings &Lauren Dade -2002 - In Donald T. Stuss & Robert T. Knight,Principles of Frontal Lobe Function. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Tevunah U-Temurah Panim Be-Heker Ha-Filosofiyah Ha-Yehudit Ve-Toldoteha.JonathanCohen -1997
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  112
    Color Ontology and Color Science.JonathanCohen &Mohan Matthen (eds.) -2010 - Bradford.
    Philosophers and scientists have long speculated about the nature of color. Atomists such as Democritus thought color to be "conventional," not real; Galileo and other key figures of the Scientific Revolution thought that it was an erroneous projection of our own sensations onto external objects. More recently, philosophers have enriched the debate about color by aligning the most advanced color science with the most sophisticated methods of analytical philosophy. In this volume, leading scientists and philosophers examine new problems with new (...) analytic tools, considering such topics as the psychophysical measurement of color and its implications, the nature of color experience in both normal color-perceivers and the color blind, and questions that arise from what we now know about the neural processing of color information, color consciousness, and color language. Taken together, these papers point toward a complete restructuring of current orthodoxy concerning color experience and how it relates to objective reality. Kuehni, Jameson, Mausfeld, and Niederee discuss how the traditional framework of a three-dimensional color space and basic color terms is far too simple to capture the complexities of color experience. Clark and MacLeod discuss the difficulties of a materialist account of color experience. Churchland,Cohen, Matthen, and Westphal offer competing accounts of color ontology. Finally, Broackes and Byrne and Hilbert discuss the phenomenology of color blindness. Contributors: Justin Broackes, Alex Byrne, Paul M. Churchland, Austen Clark,JonathanCohen, David R. Hilbert, Kimberly A. Jameson, Rolf Kuehni, Don I.A. MacLeod, Mohan Matthen, Rainer Mausfeld, Richard Niederée,Jonathan Westphal The hardcover edition does not include a dust jacket. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  31.  138
    Color, content, and Fred: On a proposed reductio of the inverted spectrum hypothesis.JonathanCohen -2001 -Philosophical Studies 103 (2):121-144.
  32.  292
    The truth about 'The truth about true blue'.JonathanCohen,C. L. Hardin &Brian P. McLaughlin -2007 -Analysis 67 (2):162-166.
    It can happen that a single surface S, viewed in normal conditions, looks pure blue (“true blue”) to observer John but looks blue tinged with green to a second observer, Jane, even though both are normal in the sense that they pass the standard psychophysical tests for color vision. Tye (2006a) finds this situation prima facie puzzling, and then offers two different “solutions” to the puzzle.1 The first is that at least one observer misrepresents S’s color because, though normal in (...) the sense explained, she is not a Normal color observer: her color detection system is not operating in the current condition in the way that Mother Nature intended it to operate. His second solution involves the idea that Mother Nature designed our color detection systems to be reliable with respect to the detection of coarse-grained colors (e.g., blue, green, yellow, orange), but our capacity to represent the fine-grained colors (e.g., true blue, blue tinged with green) is an undesigned spandrel. On this second solution, it is consistent with the variation between John and Jane that both represent the color of S in a way that complies with Mother Nature’s intentions: both represent S as exemplifying the coarse-grained color blue, and since (we may assume) S is in fact blue, both represent it veridically. Of course, they also represent fine-grained colors of S, and, according to Tye, at most one of these representations is veridical (Tye says that only God knows which). But at the level of representation for which Mother Nature designed our color detection systems, both John and Jane (qua Normal observers) are reliable detectors. (shrink)
    Direct download(11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  33.  358
    On the epistemic value of photographs.JonathanCohen &Aaron Meskin -2004 -Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 62 (2):197–210.
    Many have held that photographs give us a firmer epistemic connection to the world than do other depictive representations. To take just one example, Bazin famously claimed that “The objective nature of photography confers on it a quality of credibility absent from all other picture-making” ([Bazin, 1967], 14). Unfortunately, while the intuition in question is widely shared, it has remained poorly understood. In this paper we propose to explain the special epistemic status of photographs. We take as our starting place (...) (in §1) Kendall Walton’s startling proposal that photographs are special because they are “transparent” [Walton, 1984] — that is, that they are special because, unlike other depictive representations, they enable us literally to see their depicta.1 Walton’s proposal has not convinced many; however, it has proven surprisingly difficult to say just what is wrong about the transparency thesis. In §§2–4 we’ll rise to this challenge and show why photographs are not transparent in Walton’s sense. Finally, in §§5–7 we’ll propose and defend a novel diagnosis of what is epistemically special about photographs. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  34.  221
    Indexicality and the Puzzle of the Answering Machine.JonathanCohen -2013 -Journal of Philosophy 110 (1):5-32.
  35.  256
    Indexicality and The Answering Machine Paradox.JonathanCohen &Eliot Michaelson -2013 -Philosophy Compass 8 (6):580-592.
    Answering machines and other types of recording devices present prima facie problems for traditional theories of the meaning of indexicals. The present essay explores a range of semantic and pragmatic responses to these issues. Careful attention to the difficulties posed by recordings promises to help enlighten the boundaries between semantics and pragmatics more broadly.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  36.  399
    Special Sciences, Conspiracy and the Better Best System Account of Lawhood.JonathanCohen &Craig Callender -2010 -Erkenntnis 73 (3):427 - 447.
    An important obstacle to lawhood in the special sciences is the worry that such laws would require metaphysically extravagant conspiracies among fundamental particles. How, short of conspiracy, is this possible? In this paper we'll review a number of strategies that allow for the projectibility of special science generalizations without positing outlandish conspiracies: non-Humean pluralism, classical MRL theories of laws, and Albert and Loewer's theory. After arguing that none of the above fully succeed, we consider the conspiracy problem through the lens (...) of our preferred view of laws, an elaboration of the MRL view that we call the Better Best System (BBS) theory. BBS offers a picture on which, although all events supervene on a fundamental level, there is no one unique locus of projectibility; rather there are a large number of loci corresponding to the different areas (ecology, economics, solid-state chemistry, etc.) in which there are simple and strong generalizations to be made. While we expect that some amount of conspiracy-fear-inducing special science projectibility is inevitable given BBS, we'll argue that this is unobjectionable. It follows from BBS that the laws of any particular special or fundamental science amount to a proper subset of the laws. From this vantage point, the existence of projectible special science generalizations not guaranteed by the fundamental laws is not an occasion for conspiracy fantasies, but a predictable fact of life in a complex world. (shrink)
    Direct download(12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  37.  89
    Philosophy 132: Epistemology.JonathanCohen -manuscript
    This is a course in recent and contemporary approaches to the theory of knowledge. We'll be looking at some of the major debates in epistemology, including those over the structure of knowledge, the proper analysis of knowledge, justification, and related notions, as well as some meta-epistemological issues that have arisen in recent discussions of so-called naturalized epistemology. The course will not presuppose any exposure to the relevant literatures, and will be a broad overview of some of the going accounts and (...) controversies. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  138
    Color, Variation, and the Appeal to Essences: Impasse and Resolution.JonathanCohen -2007 -Philosophical Studies 133 (3):425-438.
    Many philosophers have been attracted by the view that colors are mind-independent properties of object surfaces. While this view has come in for a fair bit of criticism for failing to do justice to the facts about perceptual variation, Byrne and Hilbert have recently argued that perceptual variation involving color is no more problematic for physicalism about color than representational variation involving temperature is for physicalism about temperature. Unfortunately, the analogy on which this response rests is no less controversial than (...) the disputed view about color, and so the response leads to a standoff rather than a resolution of the debate. However, we can appeal to facts about our inferential treatment of color and other properties as a way of resolving this impasse; doing so gives us defeasible reason for rejecting the Byrne and Hilbert response, and so for rejecting their mind-independent conception of color. (shrink)
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  39.  204
    It's not easy being green : Hardin and color relationalism.JonathanCohen -2010 - In Jonathan Cohen & Mohan Matthen,Color Ontology and Color Science. Bradford.
    But Hardin hasn’t contented himself with reframing traditional philosoph- ical issues about color in a way that is sensitive to relevant empirical con- straints. In addition, he has been a staunch defender of color eliminativism — the view that there are no colors, qua properties of tables, chairs, and other mind-external objects, and a vociferous critic of several varieties of re- alism about color that have been defended by others (e.g., [Hardin, 2003], [Hardin, 2005]). These other views include the so-called (...) color physical- ism of [Hilbert, 1987], [Byrne and Hilbert, 1997a], [Byrne and Hilbert, 2003], and [Tye, 2000],1 and, inconveniently, even the relationalist view defended in [Cohen, 2003a], [Cohen, 2004a], [Cohen, 2003b], [McLaughlin, 2003], and [Jakab and McLaughlin, 2003]. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40.  206
    (1 other version)Information and content.JonathanCohen -2002 - In Luciano Floridi,Blackwell guide to the philosophy of information and computing. Blackwell.
    Mental states differ from most other entities in the world in having semantic or intentional properties: they have meanings, they are about other things, they have satisfaction- or truth-conditions, they have representational content. Mental states are not the only entities that have intentional properties - so do linguistic expressions, some paintings, and so on; but many follow Grice, 1957 ] in supposing that we could understand the intentional properties of these other entities as derived from the intentional properties of mental (...) states. Of course, accepting this supposition leaves us with a puzzle about how the non-derivative bearers of intentional properties could have these properties. In particular, intentional properties seem to some to be especially difficult to reconcile with a robust commitment to ontological naturalism - the view that the natural properties, events, and individuals are the only properties, events, and individuals that exist. Fodor puts this intuition nicely in this oft-quoted passage: " I suppose that sooner or later the physicists will complete the catalogue they've been compiling of the ultimate and irreducible properties of things. When they do, the likes of _spin_, _charm_, and _charge_ will perhaps appear upon their list. But _aboutness_ surely won't; intentionality simply doesn't go that deep.... If aboutness is real, it must be really something else. " Some philosophers have reacted to this clash by giving up one of the two views generating the tension. For example, Churchland, 1981 ] opts for intentional irrealism in order to save ontological naturalism, while. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41. Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind, Second Edition.Brian McLaughlin &JonathanCohen (eds.) -forthcoming - Wiley.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  61
    Schellenberg on Perceptual Capacities.JonathanCohen -2019 -Analysis 79 (4):720-730.
    Did we but compare the miserable scantiness of our capacities with the vast profundity of things, truth and modesty would teach us wary language. –Joseph Glanvill, Scepsis Scientifica, XXIII.2.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43.  947
    Nietzsche’s Musical Conception of Time.Jonathan R.Cohen -2008 - In Manuel Dries,Nietzsche on Time and History. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 291.
  44.  191
    Colors, functions, realizers, and roles.JonathanCohen -2005 -Philosophical Topics 33 (1):117-140.
    You may speak of a chain, or if you please, a net. An analogy is of little aid. Each cause brings about future events. Without each the future would not be the same. Each is proximate in the sense it is essential. But that is not what we mean by the word. Nor on the other hand do we mean sole cause. There is no such thing.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45.  723
    (1 other version)There Is No Special Problem About Scientific Representation.Craig Callender &JonathanCohen -2006 -Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 21 (1):67-85.
    We propose that scientific representation is a special case of a more general notion of representation, and that the relatively well worked-out and plausible theories of the latter are directly applicable to thc scientific special case. Construing scientific representation in this way makes the so-called “problem of scientific representation” look much less interesting than it has seerned to many, and suggests that some of the (hotly contested) debates in the literature are concerned with non-issues.
    Direct download(9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  46.  171
    Holism: Some reasons for buyer's remorse.JonathanCohen -1999 -Analysis 59 (2):63-71.
  47. On the neural implementation of optimal decisions.Patrick Simen,Philip Holmes &Jonathan D.Cohen -2009 - In Ezequiel Morsella, John A. Bargh & Peter M. Gollwitzer,Oxford handbook of human action. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  262
    Binding arguments and hidden variables.JonathanCohen &Samuel C. Rickless -2007 -Analysis 67 (1):65-71.
    o (2000), 243). In particular, the idea is that binding interactions between the relevant expressions and natural lan- guage quantifiers are best explained by the hypothesis that those expressions harbor hidden but bindable variables. Recently, however, Herman Cappelen and Ernie Lepore have rejected such binding arguments for the presence of hid- den variables on the grounds that they overgeneralize — that, if sound, such arguments would establish the presence of hidden variables in all sorts of ex- pressions where it is (...) implausible that they exist (Cappelen and Lepore (2005), Cappelen and Lepore (2002)).1 In what follows we respond to Cappelen’s and Lepore’s attempted reductio by bringing out crucial disanalogies between cases where the binding argument is successful and cases where it is not. But we have a deeper purpose than merely to respond to Cappelen and Lepore: we think the attempted reductio goes wrong by not taking sufficiently seriously the nature of the binding relation that holds between quantifiers and arguments/variables, and that our criticism will serve to highlight the nature and importance of this relation. (shrink)
    Direct download(10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  49.  189
    Sounds and temporality.JonathanCohen -2010 -Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 5:303-320.
    What is the relationship between sounds and time? More specifically, is there something essentially or distinctively temporal about sounds that distinguishes them from, say, colors, shapes, odors, tastes, or other sensible qualities? And just what might this distinctive relation to time consist in? Apart from their independent interest, these issues have a number of important philosophical repercussions. First, if sounds are temporal in a way that other sensible qualities are not, then this would mean that standard lists of paradigm secondary (...) qualities offered by Locke, Galileo, and other modern philosophers — lists which include colors, odors and sounds without any significant distinctions — overlook significant metaphysical differences. This, in turn, would threaten to undermine the coherence of the modern understanding of secondary qualities itself. Moreover, a number of authors have recently urged that the essential temporality of sounds makes it impossible to understand sounds as properties (except on a trope theory of properties; see note 3). If true, and given the more or less universal view that colors are properties, this last conclusion would make potentially inapplicable to sounds much of the comparatively well-developed philosophical taxonomy and apparatus that has arisen in philosophical disputes over the status of colors (for presentations of this taxonomy and apparatus see, for example, Byrne and Hilbert (2003);Cohen (2008b)).1 Therefore, the conclusion that sounds are distinctively temporal would be a serious blow to hopes for a theoretically unified treatment of the sensory qualities.2 For all these reasons, quite a lot seems to hang on the question of the temporality of sounds. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  50.  170
    Perception and computation.JonathanCohen -2010 -Philosophical Issues 20 (1):96-124.
    Students of perception have long puzzled over a range of cases in which perception seems to tell us distinct, and in some sense conflicting, things about the world. In the cases at issue, the perceptual system is capable of responding to a single stimulus — say, as manifested in the ways in which subjects sort that stimulus — in different ways. This paper is about these puzzling cases, and about how they should be characterized and accounted for within a general (...) theory of perception. After rehearsing the sort of case at issue (§1), I’ll examine critically some of the strategies by which philosophers and perceptual psychologists have attempted to account for them (§2). Finally, I’ll present an alternative computational account of the puzzle cases, argue that this view is superior to its competitors, and examine some of its implications (§3). (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
1 — 50 / 926
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp