Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'Claire Lougarre'

977 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  30
    Clarifying the Right to Health through Supranational Monitoring: The Highest Standard of Health Attainable.ClaireLougarre -2018 -Public Health Ethics 11 (3):251-264.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  49
    Clarifying the Right to Health through Supranational Monitoring: The Highest Standard of Health Attainable.ClaireLougarre -2015 -Public Health Ethics:phv037.
    As recognized by Gostin in Global Health Law, the principles of equality and dignity put human rights law in a unique position to promote progress towards global health equity. This seems particularly relevant for the right to health, which entitles everyone to ‘the highest standard of health attainable’. However, it is still unclear what such a standard entails, and in order for the right to health to be adequately enforced and, thus, to effectively channel progress towards global health equity, it (...) is fundamental that its scope of interests be clarified. Supranational human rights bodies have a key role in that regard. Not only can they clarify the legal content of the right to health for key actors through their monitoring procedures, they can also set common standards for states under their jurisdictions. Therefore, their contributions should be examined and optimized. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  92
    Understanding Deleuze.Claire Colebrook -2002 - Crows Nest, N.S.W.: Allen & Unwin.
    An accessible introduction to the contemporary thought of Deleuze. It makes concepts clear, showing their political and theoretical complexity, elaborating their social and artistic relevance. Australian author (previously at Monash University) now living in Edinburgh.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  4.  31
    Varieties of affect.Claire Armon-Jones -1991 - Buffalo: University of Toronto Press.
    In this new and original book,Claire Armon-Jones examines the concept of affect and various philosophical positions which attempt to define and characterize it: the standard view, the neo-cognitivist view, and the objectual thesis. She contends that these views radically distort our understanding of affect by disregarding modes of affect which fail to conform to the accounts they each employ. Against the standard and neo-cognitivist views she argues that the notions they use to characterize affect are neither necessary nor (...) sufficient; and against the objectual thesis she further argues that affective states exhibit degrees of independence from the concept of an object. She develops a new theory of the varieties of affect that explains their cognitive nature, their felt aspect, their special logic and the relationship between their objectless and object-directed forms. Armon-Jones concludes by suggesting that her arguments call into question certain assumptions about the rationality and moral status of affect and require a revision of the conception of the good in affect. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  5. Does overruling Roe discriminate against women (of colour)?Joona Räsänen,Claire Gothreau &Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen -2022 -Journal of Medical Ethics 48 (12):952-956.
    On 24 July 2022, the landmark decision Roe v. Wade (1973), that secured a right to abortion for decades, was overruled by the US Supreme Court. The Court decision in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organisation severely restricts access to legal abortion care in the USA, since it will give the states the power to ban abortion. It has been claimed that overruling Roe will have disproportionate impacts on women of color and that restricting access to abortion contributes to or (...) amounts to structural racism. In this paper, we consider whether restricting abortion access as a consequence of overruling Roe could be understood as discrimination against women of color (and women in general). We argue that banning abortion is indirectly discriminatory against women of color and directly (but neither indirectly, nor structurally) discriminatory against women in general. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  22
    Introduction.Claire Colebrook -2006 -Feminist Theory 7 (2):131-142.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  7.  41
    Sex and the (Anthropocene) City.Claire Mary Colebrook -2017 -Theory, Culture and Society 34 (2-3):39-60.
    In this essay I explore three concepts: sex, the city, and the Anthropocene. I argue that the condition for the possibility of the city is the assemblage of sexual drives for the sake of relative stability, but that those same drives also exceed the city's self-preservative function. Further, I argue that the very conditions that further the city and that enable philosophical and scientific concepts to be formed (and that allow for the Anthropocene to be discerned as an epoch) rely (...) upon a geological politics that enables new ways of thinking about what counts as the political as such. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8.  50
    The Play of the World: The End, the Great Outdoors, the Outside, Alterity and the Real.Claire Colebrook -2016 -Derrida Today 9 (1):21-35.
    Both in his earliest debates with thinkers such as Foucault and Levinas, and in later critiques of political immediacy, Derrida invoked the inescapable burden of a necessary but impossible universalism. By raising the stakes so high it would seem that deconstruction generates hyperbolic conceptions of ethics and justice, but also precludes any form of day to day political positivity. In this essay I pursue the seemingly less ‘ethical’ conception of play in Derrida's work to argue for a multiple universalism.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9.  19
    1. On the Very Possibility of Queer Theory.Claire Colebrook -2009 - In Chrysanthi Nigianni & Merl Storr,Deleuze and Queer Theory. Edinburgh University Press. pp. 11-23.
  10.  16
    Pratiques de danse et discours de genre, une histoire connectée.ElizabethClaire -2017 -Clio 46:7-18.
    En 1797, un article du Journal des Luxus und der Moden fustige une nouvelle pratique de danse, « bacchanale » prisée par les habitantes de Breslau qui pivotent « comme une figure androgyne déformée » où les pieds « suppriment toute beauté » avec leur « enthousiasme ivre ». Quelques années plus tard, dans ses « Lettres d’un médecin », le rédacteur en chef de la Gazette de santé déplore une forme de lutte entre les sexes qui touche à l’« (...) envie des femmes » (leurs désirs et leurs passions) et nu... (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11.  132
    Challenge and Threat: A Critical Review of the Literature and an Alternative Conceptualization.Mark A. Uphill,Claire J. L. Rossato,Jon Swain &Jamie O’Driscoll -2019 -Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Prompted by the development of the Theory of Challenge and Threat States in Athletes (Jones et al, 2009), recent years has witnessed a considerable increase in research examining challenge and threat in sport. This manuscript provides a critical review of the literature examining challenge and threat in sport, tracing its historical development and some of the current empirical ambiguities. In an attempt to reconcile some of these ambiguities, and utilising neurobiological evidence associated with approach- and avoidance-motivation (cf. Elliot & Covington, (...) 2001), this paper draws upon the Evaluative Space Model (ESM: Cacioppo et al., 1997) and considers the implications for understanding challenge and threat in sport. For example, rather than see challenge and threat as opposite ends of a single bipolar continuum, the ESM implies that individuals could be (1) challenged, (2) threatened, (3) challenged and threatened, or (4) neither challenged or threatened by a particular stimulus. From this perspective it could be argued that the appraisal of some sport situations as both challenging and threatening could be advantageous, whereas the current literature seems to imply that the appraisal of stress as a threat is maladaptive for performance. In drawing upon the ESM, we outline the Evaluative Space Approach to Challenge and Threat and provide several testable hypotheses for advancing understanding of challenge and threat (in sport). We also outline a number of cardiovascular and experiential measures that can be used to examine these hypotheses. In sum, this paper provides a significant theoretical, empirical and practical contribution to our understanding of challenge and threat (in sport). (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12.  129
    Matter Without Bodies.Claire Colebrook -2011 -Derrida Today 4 (1):1-20.
    Materialism is at once the most general of concepts, capable of gesturing to anything that seems either foundational or physicalist, and yet is also one of the most rhetorical of gestures: operating as a way of reducing, criticising or ‘‘exorcising’’ forms of idealism and ideology. Derrida's early, supposedly ‘‘textualist’’ works appear to endorse a materiality of the letter (including syntax, grammar, trace and writing) while the later works focus on matter as split between that which is posited and that which (...) will always appear as a receding ground. It is more important than ever that materialism not be accepted too readily as a way of overcoming a supposedly linguistic or textualist Derrida in order that Derrida might be smuggled into the contemporary heaven of naturalism and physicalism. On the contrary, it is the dispersed, inhuman and inorganic materiality beyond bodies, physis and substance that offers itself for genuinely deconstructive thinking. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13.  30
    Posthumous Life: Theorizing Beyond the Posthuman.Jami Weinstein &Claire Colebrook (eds.) -2017 - New York: Columbia University Press.
    Posthumous Life launches critical life studies: a mode of inquiry that neither endorses nor dismisses a wave of recent "turns" toward life, matter, vitality, inhumanity, animality, and the real. Questioning the nature and limits of life in the natural sciences, the essays in this volume examine the boundaries and significance of the human and the humanities in the wake of various redefinitions of what counts as life. They explore the possibility of theorizing life without assuming it to be either a (...) simple substrate or an always-mediated effect of culture and difference. Posthumous Life provides new ways of thinking about animals, plants, humans, difference, sexuality, race, gender, identity, the earth, and the future. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  25
    Incorporeality: The ghostly body of metaphysics.Claire Colebrook -2000 -Body and Society 6 (2):25--44.
    For the past two decades, the issue of the body and essentialism has dominated feminist theory. In general, it is assumed that the body has been devalued and repressed by the Western metaphysical tradition. In this article, I make two claims to the contrary. First, as poststructuralist theory has tirelessly demonstrated, Western thought has continually tried to ground thought in some foundational substance, such as the body. Second, the most provocative, fruitful and radical aspects of recent feminism and poststructuralism concern (...) the event of incorporeality. What makes incorporeality such an urgent issue is its tie with anti-foundationalism. If there is not a direct or proper passage between what is and what is thought, then thinking can be considered as a force or event in its own right. By disrupting the traditional philosophical series that ties thought to some grounding body, thinkers as diverse as Deleuze, Derrida, Irigaray and Foucault have opened the possibility of a theory of the incorporeal. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  5
    The Counter-Oceanic Sea.Claire Colebrook -2025 -Angelaki 30 (1):26-39.
    When Freud described the “oceanic feeling” of intimated plenitude that haunted the boundaries of consciousness he both intensified a post-enlightenment aesthetics that imagined the beyond of civilization is female, fluid, and undifferentiated and gave modernist poetics a theory of an almost unthinkable serenity beyond the limits of identity. European Romanticism and modernism, for all their differences, operated largely with the assumption that being a subject required abandoning an original maternal plenitude. In The Deep, Rivers Solomon provides a counter-oedipal politics and (...) aesthetics that affirms a difference and intensity in the depths of history and the sea, taking life and difference beyond the binaries of male/female and nature/culture. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  35
    Linking Biodiversity with Health and Well-being: Consequences of Scientific Pluralism for Ethics, Values and Responsibilities.Serge Morand &Claire Lajaunie -2019 -Asian Bioethics Review 11 (2):153-168.
    This paper investigates the ethical implications of research at the interface between biodiversity and both human and animal health. Health and sanitary crises often lead to ethical debates, especially when it comes to disruptive interventions such as forced vaccinations, quarantine, or mass culling of domestic or wild animals. In such debates, the emergence of a “Planetary health ethics” can be highlighted. Ethics and accountability principles apply to all aspects of scientific research including its technological and engineering applications, regardless of whether (...) they are considered “hard sciences”, such as state-of-the-art technology in the fields of medicine, veterinary medicine, agronomy, or environment, or “soft”, such as local or global governance, health, socio-ecosystems, and the environment. Ethical reflection in the interdisciplinary field of biodiversity and health requires the examination of relevant scientific domains, such as biology, ecology, evolution, human medicine, animal medicine, anthropology, and law, and their epistemology and representation as well as scientific pluralism, which is crucial to establish genuine interdisciplinarity. Navigating the ethics-scape necessitates going beyond the hierarchy of science by recognising that scientific knowledge has implications for both scientific and non-scientific perspectives on the study of nature. The example of a Nipah virus outbreak is used to illustrate how the so-called “modern epidemiological” approach often focuses on risk factors associated with individual behavioural characteristics or collective practices, whereas the so-called “eco-social” approach focuses on global, socio-economic, and environmental factors that are the contextual causes of the health problem affecting the community. “Modern epidemiologists” aim to “correct” individual or practice factors using a “minimal set” of ethics, whereas “eco-social” scientists have to act systemically, which requires integrated research that acknowledges scientific pluralism, avoids the hierarchy of sciences, but accepts the pluralism of ethics and values. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  18
    Pour une approche phénoménologique de la maladie.Claire Crignon -2024 -Archives de Philosophie 1:113-119.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  28
    Bacon et les formes de l’expérience. Nouvelles lectures.Claire Crignon &Sandrine Parageau -2021 -Archives de Philosophie 84 (1):7-15.
    Cet article traite des stratégies de lecture inductive spécifiques que les lecteurs du Novum Organum sont invités à mettre en place afin de mieux saisir le sens que Bacon donne à l’induction dans cet ouvrage : un exercice d’apprentissage cognitif au cours duquel des inférences générales sont construites en faisant l’expérience directe des choses. Conséquence supplémentaire, le lecteur a également accès par l’induction à une forme de connaissance des composantes ultimes de l’être, car il découvre que toutes les choses de (...) la nature, animées et inanimées, sont mues par des stratégies inductives de survie conformes à l’idée de Bacon selon laquelle les mouvements sont des appétits. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  23
    Peut-on faire une histoire naturelle de l’air?Claire Crignon -2021 -Archives de Philosophie 84 (1):93-113.
    Imperceptibles, difficiles à observer, l’air et les vents ne sont pas seulement appréhendés par le recours aux instruments, au sein de l’espace fermé du laboratoire. Leur connaissance peut requérir des qualités de mémorisation et d’observation auxquelles les voyageurs, les marchands, les agriculteurs pourront, peutêtre, plus facilement prétendre que des savants experts. Partant de l’exposition du projet d’une histoire naturelle et de son application au cas spécifique de l’air et des vents dans l’oeuvre de Francis Bacon, l’article examine les moyens mis (...) en oeuvre par les auteurs qui ont revendiqué le legs baconien (Boyle, Hooke, Childrey, Plot) afin de surmonter les obstacles qui s’attachent à la connaissance de l’air et à celle de ses effets sur le développement des maladies ou la poursuite de la santé. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  75
    Questioning Representation.Claire Colebrook -2000 -Substance 29 (2):47-67.
  21.  23
    Introduction: Anthropocene Feminisms: Rethinking the Unthinkable.Claire Colebrook &Jami Weinstein -2015 -philoSOPHIA: A Journal of Continental Feminism 5 (2):167-178.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:IntroductionAnthropocene Feminisms: Rethinking the UnthinkableClaire Colebrook and Jami WeinsteinIn her recent lecture on the Anthropocene (to which she adds the Capitalocene and the Chthulucene), Donna Haraway expresses some alarm that after two major insights into what counts as thinkable, it was “anthropos” that became the term for the post-Holocene (Haraway 2014). Haraway declares, with emphasis, that it is “literally unthinkable” to work with the individual unit of “man” if (...) one is to do good intellectual work. For Haraway, the two knowledge events that ought to have precluded the use of the figure of the “anthropos” are: first, the acceptance that any seeming individual is the outcome of a series of complex relations and must be studied as such (so there would be no epoch with anything, let alone “man,” as its first cause), and, second, intellectual inquiry has acknowledged a general becoming-with, such that in order to be anything at all, “one” must be in a dynamic relation. Haraway’s work is exemplary of post-liberal feminist resistance to the figure of man—as subject, agent, and center of knowing. Terms like “Woman” or “the feminine” do not extend the field occupied by man; they instead create a different intensity. So when Haraway questions the “anthropos” of the Anthropocene she neither asks that women, too, be included in those who have scarred the planet, nor does she claim that “Woman” would occupy some innocent outside. Instead, she proposes that one think of the “anthropos” as untimely, as out of sync with an intellectual milieu that theorizes the death of the subject and the eclipse of the human, and has even begun to renounce the notion of life in itself. It is odd that in the face of this destruction of any possibility of thinking by [End Page 167] way of individualism, the epic gesture of the present deploys the figure of the “anthropos,” as it should be unthinkable today to return to the figure of man.When Haraway invokes what is literally unthinkable, and then gestures to the Anthropocene, she suggests that perhaps the figure of the Anthropocene is a form of unthinking, and that it is precisely when complexities, timescales, predictions, manageability, and any form of sustainability ought to disturb and trouble our logics that we cease to think and ask for a single cause for an entire epoch. If this is so, and the “anthropos” of the Anthropocene is a reaction formation, then we might see the skirmishes and turf wars that surround the golden spike1 as diversions. If we spend our time disputing just when it was that man started to change the planet, then we allow a contested point in time to pass itself off as thinking, all the while allowing the intensive multiplicity of what has come to be known as the Anthropocene to remain unthought. By asking when the Anthropocene began, we revive a modified version of the time of man; once again, man is placed as the agent of history, albeit unwittingly, and he can look back upon and assess the past of his own making. Haraway is not alone in suggesting that such conceptions of a single line of time, and a conception of first cause, are highly gendered and racialized. The figure of “man” who creates his own history and recognizes himself as having come into being through a time that is readable is bound up with hegemonic conceptions of modernity, and has long been the target of feminist, poststructuralist, and postcolonial critique (e.g., Foucault 1970; Amin 1989; Grosz 2004). If it is literally unthinkable to do good work from the premises of a methodological individualism, then asking who or what caused the Anthropocene, or when it began, would amount to a form of un-thinking or not-thinking. At the same time, perhaps the Anthropocene is literally unthinkable in a sense that marks a more positive and profound absurdity. Let us accept, following Haraway, that all “good work” both acknowledges the impossibility of accounting for the complexity of life by way of bounded, individual singularity, and dispenses with the exceptional man of reason as its foundation. If we do, what the Anthropocene... (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  6
    Servitude et aliénation : relire La Boétie à l’aune de la clinique.Claire Crignon -2024 -Archives de Philosophie 87 (4):149-154.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  15
    Notes de lecture.Claire Crignon &Laurent Gallois -2021 -Archives de Philosophie 84 (1):145-152.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  50
    Inappropriate regret.Claire Pouncey -2009 -Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 16 (3):233-234.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Inappropriate RegretClaire Pouncey (bio)Keywordsanxiety, inappropriate guilt, moral sentiments, supererogation, regretThis delightful and provocative vignette has many interesting clinical facets, and I thank Dr. Bailey for his candid introspection. For me, this essay calls attention to an asymmetry in our culture, in which women tend to feel more comfortable than men in expressing anxieties about our unpredictable and often dangerous world. Women's fears, however, often are dismissed or minimized, revealing (...) an overall social discomfort with expressed anxiety, and a sense that anxiety itself is, somehow, feminine. When I read Dr. Bailey's essay, I am struck that two self-aware men need the metaphors of war and heroism to address their own anxieties.The vignette builds around a soldier, Colin, who presents with guilt about having been deployed to Iraq, but not engaging in combat. Guilt is a moral sentiment, a feeling that one ought to have acted otherwise in a given situation. It is a self-imposed sanction for a moral failure. In mental health care, we use the term ‘inappropriate guilt’ to describe a clinical symptom commonly associated with depression. Clinicians understand inappropriate guilt as a manifestation of the self-criticism and low self-esteem often associated with depressive disorders. In Colin's case, it did fit with a constellation of symptoms that suggested depression. Dr. Bailey's essay explores the psychodynamics of Colin's guilt, and possible responses to it.As I understand the situation, Colin sees himself as having a moral obligation to exceed his contractual obligation to the military. In the terminology of ethics, he imposes upon himself a duty to be supererogatory, that is, a duty to go beyond the call of duty, which some moral philosophers have considered oxymoronic. For Colin to feel guilty about not engaging in combat, he must have understood a moral obligation to participate in combat that goes beyond his obligation to follow orders. It seems to me that soldiers have a nonmoral, contractual obligation to train, deploy, follow orders, and if circumstances so dictate, fight. But if the circumstances do not lead to combat (Nagel might call this good moral luck), it does not seem to me that a soldier has failed either a contractual or a moral obligation by not being sent into battle. Supererogation aside, to my mind, Colin's guilt is inappropriate: he is holding himself to an unreasonable moral standard, according to which he is required not only to do what the military demands, but also to sacrifice or suffer from the experience in some meaningful way.Although the notion of inappropriate guilt fits with the description of Colin's depression, it occurs to me that the word ‘guilt’ may be too strong here. Perhaps what Dr. Bailey is seeing is better characterized as ‘inappropriate regret’ that Colin missed “his last, best chance to be a hero.” ‘Regret’ is the sentiment that one could have (rather than should have) acted otherwise, perhaps to a better eventual end. Dr. Bailey agrees that Colin's guilt is inappropriate, that no one is ever required [End Page 233] to be a hero. But he seems to share, and even encourage, what I am calling Colin's ‘inappropriate regret,’ which suggests that if Colin had engaged in combat, he would not experience feelings of helplessness or insecurity in our uncertain world. What fascinates me is that Dr. Bailey accepts this premise, and even reflects on his own fears about self-protection in his own urban setting.Rather than challenging it, Dr. Bailey clearly shares Colin's concern that he may not be able to respond adequately should a real threat arise. Both therapist and patient seem to want reassurance that they can keep themselves and their families safe when danger strikes. But this is not a matter of achieving or going beyond the call of duty. Rather, it is an expression of familiar and diffuse anxiety that is unrelated to wartime. In the essay, heroism seems to serve as a metaphor, a filter that makes the expression of anxiety more palatable to both the patient and the therapist. I am fascinated that these two sensitive and introspective interlocutors need to filter their anxieties through... (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  38
    L’exposition anatomique « Our Body » : une atteinte à la dignité du cadavre?GwénaëlleClaire -2011 -Médecine et Droit 2011 (108):136-142.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  136
    Paradigm transitions in mathematics.Claire L. Parkinson -1987 -Philosophia Mathematica (2):127-150.
  27.  43
    Rosenzweig and Heidegger: Between Judaism and German Philosophy (review).Claire Elise Katz -2005 -Journal of the History of Philosophy 43 (1):124-125.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Rosenzweig and Heidegger: Between Judaism and German PhilosophyClaire Elise KatzPeter Eli Gordon. Rosenzweig and Heidegger: Between Judaism and German Philosophy. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2003. Pp. xxix + 328. Cloth, $65.00.Peter Gordon's recent book brings together two seemingly disparate authors—Franz Rosenzweig and Martin Heidegger. Gordon intends to demonstrate that although Franz Rosenzweig is most frequently viewed as a Jewish thinker, this perspective obfuscates his German background, which (...) Gordon argues plays an even more prominent role in his thinking. His claim is that Rosenzweig should be situated within his German background and within German thought in order to gain a broader and more accurate perspective of who he was and what his work means.The book is coherently organized with a substantial introduction that lays the groundwork for the rest of the argument. Here, Gordon introduces us to Rosenzweig, Heidegger, and modern German and Jewish thought. Subsequent discussions explore primary philosophical influences on Rosenzweig's thought, for example, the roots of Rosenzweig's "New Thinking" found in Hermann Cohen and the need for a critique of totality found in Hegel. The central chapters, which offer a re-reading of Rosenzweig's Star of Redemption, are clearly written and are alone worth the time of this book.In these two chapters, Gordon outlines the significance of Rosenzweig's thought as situated within the canon of western philosophy by demonstrating that Rosenzweig's work engages central questions and concerns within the history of philosophy. Primarily, Rosenzweig believes that western philosophy has concerned itself too much with death, the death of the individual and a need to transcend completely from this world. Rosenzweig, contra the history of western philosophy, argues for a philosophical position that emphasizes life here and now—the everyday—and, more importantly, that we remain in time and the world (179). And here he draws interesting comparisons to Heidegger, indicating that these philosophers had a similar relationship to the history of philosophy, both of which were influenced by the German milieu in which they wrote and thought.Gordon ends his study of the relationship between Rosenzweig and Heidegger by drawing our attention to Rosenzweig's last writings, which were in the form of newspaper articles. These writings attended to the Davos Disputation, the now infamous debate between Heidegger and Ernst Cassirer. In these articles Rosenzweig indicates his partiality to Heidegger's position, in particular his position on redemption (285 ff.), indicating that Heidegger's philosophical stance represented most clearly Rosenzweig's New Thinking.Regardless of whether one agrees with Gordon's main thesis, this book is an original and significant contribution to philosophy and Jewish thought. Clearly Heidegger does not represent philosophy proper, since we still see grave signs of the split between analytic and "contemporary continental" philosophy; however, he does loom large as a central figure within European philosophy and specifically within German thought. To engage Rosenzweig's views with those of Heidegger brings Rosenzweig into a conversation from which he is normally excluded. And unfortuntately, when Rosenzweig is studied along with other figures such as Emmanuel Levinas, philosophers whose work is outside of Jewish thought will simply claim that Levinas is even more "Jewish" than they thought rather than admit that Rosenzweig is a philosophical thinker worthy of engagement. Although Gordon might hope that Rosenzweig scholars take more notice of the German background of Rosenzweig's thought, instead of circumscribing him within a strictly Jewish context, the engagement with Heidegger might be of more importance for Heidegger scholars and scholars of contemporary European philosophy.My sense is that Rosenzweig scholars in fact do notice the Germanic influence but also see the significance of treating Jewish philosophy as philosophy in its own right. It is "mainstream" philosophy that might need the reminder that Jewish philosophy is also philosophy. As a result, my primary concern is that Gordon's book might have de-emphasized the "Jewish" in order to make room for the "German." At the beginning of the book Gordon tells us that "Levinas was always suspicious of Heidegger." That, actually, is not true. Levinas attended the Davos debate and sided with Heidegger. But the events of the early 1930s led him... (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  66
    Responses to “An Ethical Analysis of the Barriers to Effective Pain Management” by Ben A. Rich (CQ Vol 9, No 1).Claire Brett -2001 -Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 10 (1):88-98.
    Ben Rich, J.D., Ph.D., presents a scholarly, passionate view of the ethics of the His manuscript is detailed, analytical, and compassionate. No reasonable sensitive person, especially a physician committed to caring for patients, can disagree with the proposal that human beings should have their physical, emotional, and spiritual pain tended to aggressively, meticulously, and compassionately. Similarly, the same individuals advocating for such pain management would agree that no one should go to jail unless he or she is guilty of a (...) serious crime, that decent people should not be robbed or murdered, that children should not be hungry or homeless, and that all citizens of the United States deserve healthcare. Our society attempts to achieve these goals. Laws are written, discussed, and approved by state and federal congresses, voted on by citizens, and theoretically upheld by the courts, churches, and decent individuals. But, unless the world suddenly becomes inhabited by virtuous, ethical humans who can unfailingly differentiate from then, in spite of an abundance of laws and lawyers, doctors, and nurses, this world will continue to have pain and suffering. And, although we want to hold our doctors, politicians, educators, champion athletes, and others to than the average citizen, it is best to remind ourselves frequently that all humans can be weak and are bound to make imprecise judgments, that there is not a homogenous definition of that values and religious beliefs are variable. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  28
    The sense of atrocity and the passion for justice.Claire Valier -2004 -Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 7 (2):145-159.
    A penal ethics for today examines the connections between affect and morality. It scrutinises closely the felt moralities within the apprehension of crime. These felt moralities underpin interventions that are seemingly mobilised by a passion for justice. A penal ethics questions whether these sensibilities really do move moral actors as just feelings. This proposition is readily defended by reference to the emotive moralism in some notable areas. These include legitimation of the death penalty as ‘closure’ for victims, and the emergent (...) imperative to wage ‘virtuous’ wars. Developing an ethics that challenges the contemporary penal field requires a sophisticated theoretical elaboration. An approach of this kind entails the conceptual determination and phenomenological analysis of moral sensibilities. This essay accordingly explores the feeling of being moved by a sense of atrocity. It considers the feeling of being moved to respond justly to one globally noted death from crime. This was a death thought to have reinforced the West’s sense of moral purpose in the movement toward ‘virtuous war’ upon an Iraqi regime framed as ‘brutal’. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  16
    Virginie Valentin, L’art chorégraphique occidental, une fabrique du féminin. Essai d’anthropologie esthétique.ElizabethClaire -2014 -Clio 40:323-323.
    Dans son livre d’anthropologie esthétique sur L’art chorégraphique occidental, une fabrique du féminin, inspiré de sa thèse soutenue en 2005 à l’Université de Toulouse 2, Virginie Valentin propose d’étudier le « nœud entre émotion esthétique et danse classique » (p. 11) qui donnerait aujourd’hui aux jeunes filles françaises l’envie de pratiquer le ballet. Croisant entretiens de danseuses professionnelles et amatrices sur leurs expériences de l’apprentissage du ballet, avec une analyse littéra...
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  45
    (1 other version)Introduction Part I.Claire Colebrook -2008 -Deleuze and Guatarri Studies 2 (Suppl):1-19.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  22
    Is There Something Wrong With the Task of Thinking?Claire Colebrook -2020 -Environmental Philosophy 17 (1):39-58.
    One way to approach the widely acknowledged failure to act on climate change would be to turn to the philosophical tradition, going back to Kant at least, that diagnoses all the internal impediments to thinking. It is with Heidegger, however, that thinking is curiously divided between a disclosure of the world, and the world’s occlusion. Rather than pursue Heidegger’s project of destroying throught’s accretions and returning to the world I will argue that it is the very concept of ‘thinking’ in (...) the grand sense that needs to be destroyed if we are to be open to the future. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  7
    Jean-Luc Nancy.Claire Colebrook -2009 - In Felicity Colman,Film, Theory and Philosophy: The Key Thinkers. Acumen Publishing. pp. 154-163.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  93
    Modernism without Women: The Refusal of Becoming-Woman (and Post-Feminism).Claire Colebrook -2013 -Deleuze and Guatarri Studies 7 (4):427-455.
    Just as becoming-woman is a divided concept, looking back to a seemingly redemptive figure of the feminine beyond rigid being, but also forward to a positive annihilation of fixed genders, so modernism was also a doubled movement. But modernism was a pulverisation of ‘the’ subject for the sake of a plural and multiplying point of view, and like ‘becoming-woman’, should be read as a defiant and affirmative refusal.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  49
    On the uses and abuses of repetition.Claire Colebrook -2009 -Angelaki 14 (1):41 – 49.
  36.  14
    Preface: Postscript On the Posthuman.Claire Colebrook &Jami Weinstein -2017 - In Jami Weinstein & Claire Colebrook,Posthumous Life: Theorizing Beyond the Posthuman. New York: Columbia University Press.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  26
    Pragmatic Rights.Claire Colebrook -2015 -Law and Critique 26 (2):155-171.
    In this essay I explore competing senses and tensions of the relation between the etymology of ta pragmata and praxis, with specific attention paid to Heidegger’s theorization of modernity. In so doing I question the relation between rights and persons, and whether there might not be a new way of thinking about rights that does not presuppose or privilege the agency of personhood. Pragmatic rights would not assume the liberal values of self-determination that underpin personhood, and would enable a notion (...) of rights beyond liberal humanism more appropriate for twenty-first century political concerns and problems. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  60
    Slavery and the Trumpocene: It's Not the End of the World.Claire Colebrook -2019 -Oxford Literary Review 41 (1):40-50.
    There is something more catastrophic than the end of the world, especially when ‘world’ is understood as the horizon of meaning and expectation that has composed the West. If the Anthropocene is th...
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  17
    Specters of Non-Marxist Life: An Epoch of Extinction.Claire Colebrook -2012 -Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 43 (2):117-130.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  40
    The becoming-photographic of cinema.Claire Colebrook -2015 -Philosophy of Photography 6 (1):5-24.
    Both Gilles Deleuze and Bernard Stiegler have sought a renewal of life, perception and philosophy by way of the radical temporality of cinema. In doing so they have, in part, contributed to a long-standing moralism in philosophy that defines itself against the still or photographic image. Rather than see photography as a fragment of a flow of time, and therefore as on its way to becoming cinematic, I argue that the photograph that is cut off from the flow of time (...) provides a more provocative and post-moral way of approaching the relation between philosophy and the arts. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  32
    The Future-To-Come: Derrida and the Ethics of Historicity.Claire Colebrook -1998 -Philosophy Today 42 (4):347-360.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  22
    The Memory of Thought: An Essay on Heidegger and Adorno, by Alexander Garcia Duttmann.Claire Colebrook -2004 -Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 35 (2):218-219.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  11
    The Real and the Phantom of Happiness.Claire Colebrook -2004 -Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 35 (3):246-260.
    (2004). The Real and the Phantom of Happiness. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology: Vol. 35, Phenomenology and French Thought, pp. 246-260.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  136
    The Secret of Theory.Claire Colebrook -2010 -Deleuze and Guatarri Studies 4 (3):287-300.
    This article focuses on the concept of the secret in Deleuze and Guattari's philosophy, with specific attention to the related concepts of becoming-woman and literature. It contrasts Deleuze and Guattari's immanent mode of reading with oedipal theories of the text and hermeneutics. Whereas Deleuze and Guattari argue for the positivity of the secret, where there is content that is not disclosed and that therefore creates lines of perception and interpretation, the oedipal mode of reading regards the secret as a (negative) (...) effect of reading. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  44
    Time Travels: Feminism, Nature Power, by Elizabeth Grosz.Claire Colebrook -2008 -Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 39 (3):331-333.
  46.  13
    The Trope of Economy and Representational Thinking: Heidegger, Derrida and Irigaray.Claire Colebrook -1997 -Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 28 (2):178-191.
  47.  55
    The Work of Art that Stands Alone.Claire Colebrook -2007 -Deleuze and Guatarri Studies 1 (1):22-40.
  48. L'instrument de musique considéré comme objet d'art: conservation et restauration du décor.Claire Combe -2002 -Techne: La Science au Service de l'Histoire de l'Art Et des Civilisations 16:76-85.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  28
    Citizenship education and global migration: implications for theory, research, and teaching.Claire E. Crawford -2018 -British Journal of Educational Studies 66 (4):560-563.
  50.  35
    (2 other versions)The loss of God.Claire Creffield -2013 -Philosophers' Magazine 60 (-1):32 - 37.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 977
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp