Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'Brdford Skow'

71 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  349
    Are There Non-Causal Explanations (of Particular Events)?BrdfordSkow -2013 -British Journal for the Philosophy of Science (3):axs047.
    Philosophers have proposed many alleged examples of non-causal explanations of particular events. I discuss several well-known examples and argue that they fail to be non-causal. 1 Questions2 Preliminaries3 Explanations That Cite Causally Inert Entities4 Explanations That Merely Cite Laws I5 Stellar Collapse6 Explanations That Merely Cite Laws II7 A Final Example8 Conclusion.
    Direct download(9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  2.  76
    Objective Becoming.BradfordSkow -2015 - Oxford: Oxford University Press UK.
    What does the passage of time consist in? There are some suggestive metaphors. âEvents approach us, pass us, and recede from us, like sticks and leaves floating on the river of time.â âWe are moving from the past into the future, like ships sailing into an unknown ocean.â There is surely something right and deep about these metaphors. But how close are they to the literal truth? In this book BradfordSkow argues that they are far from the literal (...) truth. Skowâs argument takes the form of a defense of the block universe theory of time, a theory that, in many ways, treats time as a dimension of reality that closely resembles the three dimensions of space. Opposed to the block universe theory of time are theories that take the metaphors more seriously: presentism, the moving spotlight theory, the growing block theory, and the branching time theory. These are theories of ârobustâ passage of time, or âobjective becoming.âSkow argues that the best of these theories, the block universe theoryâs most worthy opponent, is the moving spotlight theory, the theory that says that âpresentnessâ moves along the series of times from the past into the future.Skow defends the moving spotlight theory against the objection that it is inconsistent, and the objection that it cannot answer the question of how fast time passes. He also defends it against the objection that it is incompatible with Einsteinâs theory of relativity.Skow proposes several ways in which the moving spotlight theory may be made compatible with the theory of relativity. Still, this book is ultimately a defense of the block universe theory, not of the moving spotlight theory.Skow holds that the best arguments against the block universe theory, and for the moving spotlight theory, start from the idea that, somehow, the passage of time is given to us in experience.Skow discusses several different arguments that start from this idea, and argues that they all fail. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  3.  379
    Experience and the passage of time.BradfordSkow -2011 -Philosophical Perspectives 25 (1):359-387.
    Some philosophers believe that the passage of time is a real phenomenon. And some of them find a reason to believe this when they attend to features of their conscious experience. In fact this “argument from experience” is supposed to be one of the main arguments for passage. What exactly does this argument look like? Is it any good?
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  4.  116
    Reasons Why.BradfordSkow -2016 - Oxford, England and New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press UK.
    This book first argues that what philosophers are really after, or at least should be after, when they seek a theory of explanation, is a theory of answers to why-questions. The book's main thesis, then, is a theory of reasons why. Every reason why some event happened is either a cause, or a ground, of that event. Challenging this thesis are many examples philosophers have thought they have found of "non-causal explanations." Reasons Why uses two ideas to show that these (...) examples are not counterexamples to the theory it defends. First is the idea that not every part of a good response to a why-question is part of an answer to that why-question. Second is the idea that not every reason why something is a reason why an event happened is itself a reason why that event happened. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  5.  247
    Are shapes intrinsic?BradfordSkow -2007 -Philosophical Studies 133 (1):111 - 130.
    It is widely believed that shapes are intrinsic properties. But this claim is hard to defend. I survey all known theories of shape properties, and argue that each theory is either incompatible with the claim that shapes are intrinsic, or can be shown to be false.
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  6.  34
    Causation, Explanation, and the Metaphysics of Aspect.BradfordSkow -2018 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    BradfordSkow examines important philosophical questions about causation and explanation. His answers rely on a pair of connected distinctions: the distinction between acting and not acting, and that between situations in which an event happens and when something is in some state.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  7.  188
    Once Upon a Spacetime.BradfordSkow -2005
  8.  98
    The Moodless Theory of Modality: An Introduction and Defence.BradfordSkow -2022 -Australasian Journal of Philosophy 100 (2):279-295.
    This paper proposes a new reductive theory of modality, called the moodless theory of modality. This theory, and not modal realism, is the closest modal analogue of the tenseless theory of time. So, if the tenseless theory is true, and the temporality–modality analogy is good, it is the moodless theory that follows. I also argue that the moodless theory, considered on its own, is better than modal realism: arguments often thought to be decisive against modal realism are weak against it.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  62
    When (Imagined) Evidence Explains Fictionality.BradfordSkow -2022 -Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 80 (4):464-476.
    Sometimes, a proposition is fictional in a story in virtue of the fact that other fictional truths are good evidence for it. Cases are presented in which this evidential rule, and not some rule that invokes counterfactuals or intentions, is what explains what is fictional. Applications are made to the question of interpretive pluralism and the problem of imaginative resistance. In the background is pluralism about fictionality: the evidential rule is one of a variety of rules that are needed to (...) account for what is fictional in a story. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  468
    Why Does Time Pass?BradfordSkow -2011 -Noûs 46 (2):223-242.
    According to the moving spotlight theory of time, the property of being present moves from earlier times to later times, like a spotlight shone on spacetime by God. In more detail, the theory has three components. First, it is a version of eternalism: all times, past present and future, exist. (Here I use “exist” in its tenseless sense.) Second, it is a version of the A-theory of time: there are nonrelative facts about which times are past, which time is present, (...) and which times are future. That is, it is not just that the year 1066 is past relative to 2007. The year 1066 is also past full-stop, not relative to any other time. (The A-theory is opposed to the B-theory of time, which says that facts about which times are past are relative to other times.) And third, on this view the passage of time is a real phenomenon. Which moment is present keeps changing. As I will sometimes put it, the NOW moves from the past toward the future.1 And this does not mean that relative to different times, different times are present. Even the B-theory can say that 1999 is present relative to 1999 but is not present relative to 2007. No, according to the moving spotlight theory, the claim that which moment is present keeps changing is supposed to be true, even from a perspective outside time. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  11.  288
    ‘‘One Second Per Second’’.BradfordSkow -2012 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85 (2):377-389.
  12.  261
    Deep metaphysical indeterminacy.BradfordSkow -2010 -Philosophical Quarterly 60 (241):851 - 858.
    A recent theory of metaphysical indeterminacy says that metaphysical indeterminacy is multiple actuality: there is metaphysical indeterminacy when there are many 'complete precisifications of reality'. But it is possible for there to be metaphysical indeterminacy even when it is impossible to precisify reality completely. The orthodox interpretation of quantum mechanics illustrates this possibility. So this theory of metaphysical indeterminacy is not adequate.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  13.  130
    Are There Non-Causal Explanations (of Particular Events)?BradfordSkow -2014 -British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 65 (3):445-467.
    Philosophers have proposed many alleged examples of non-causal explana- tions of particular events. I discuss several well-known examples and argue that they fail to be non-causal.
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  14.  64
    Questioning Imaginative Resistance and Resistant Reading.BradfordSkow -2021 -British Journal of Aesthetics 61 (4):575-587.
    It is widely accepted that readers will resist imagining that a character in a story did something morally wrong, even if the story endorses this judgement. This paper argues, first, that readers will not resist if the question of whether that act was wrong is not salient as they read; and, second, that asking a certain question can be part of correctly appreciating a story—even if that question is not in the foreground of the story, and even if the story (...) itself discourages readers from asking it, as is common in some forms of the ‘hermeneutics of suspicion’. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  30
    Groll on Bionormativity and the Value of Genetic Knowledge.BradfordSkow -2023 -International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 16 (1):182-192.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Groll on Bionormativity and the Value of Genetic KnowledgeBradfordSkow (bio)1. IntroductionShould people who plan to use donated sperm and/or eggs to conceive a child use an open donor who agrees ahead of time that any resulting children may be told who the donor is? In Conceiving People: Genetic Knowledge and the Ethics of Sperm and Egg Donation (Groll 2021), Daniel Groll answers yes. He argues that using (...) an anonymous donor would be wrong. Groll does not discuss adoption in detail, but his ideas also support the claim that people who adopt a child should adopt from parents who agree ahead of time that their child may be told who their biological parents are. It is not OK to have a closed adoption, in which information about the child's biological parents that would otherwise be public (for example, information on their original birth certificate) is kept secret by the government, and where (in some cases) the biological parents are promised that their children will never learn who they are. I was adopted in a closed adoption and met my biological family when I was twenty, and I think Groll's answer to his main question is right. That, however, does not mean I agree with all of his reasons. Here I examine those reasons and sketch some places where I would depart from them.2. The argument in outlineThe basic outline of Groll's argument, in simple terms, is as follows.1. If a child's knowing who their genetic parents are will likely benefit them—that is, if it will make their life go better, or increase their wellbeing—and if this is foreseeable, then that is a reason for parents to make the child's learning this possible (at some "appropriate" time).2. That knowledge will likely benefit the child …3.. … and this is foreseeable. [End Page 182]4. This reason favoring parents making genetic knowledge possible is strong enough that, except in maybe very special circumstances, parents should make this knowledge possible.The first point is hard to dispute. If the second point is true, then the third point is also plausible, since it is foreseeable that a child born from gamete donation (or an adopted child) will likely try to learn who their genetic (or biological) parents are. These searches are common and widely known to occur. Most of the action, therefore, is in the second point. Why think that knowing who your genetic or biological parents are is likely to make your life go better? Here the path diverges into a wood.3. First try: getting what you want makes your life go betterThe simplest way to argue that knowing who your genetic parents are is a benefit is to note that many, if not most, people conceived through gamete donation (or adoption) will, at some point, want—intensely want—to know who their genetic (or biological) parents are. One can then appeal to the idea that getting what you want makes your life go better, other things being equal.1Groll does not like this justification. His objection is that it does not show "that there is anything resembling a deep connection between genetic knowledge and well-being" (Groll 2021, 65). On Groll's view, knowing who your genetic (biological) parents are is a benefit, but this is not simply because it is something you want to know. I might know ahead of time that my child will want to live in a red house, and they might therefore be better off if they get to, and I might do my best to make that possible; but the reason I have to make genetic knowledge available to them is much stronger and much weightier than my reason to help them live in the right colored house. (It may be that this is where the fourth point of the argument, about the strength of reasons, comes in.)So why is the reason to provide genetic knowledge stronger? Groll, I think, holds that some things are more worth wanting than others. Getting what you want may benefit you, but getting what you want when what you want is something... (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  463
    Relativity and the Moving Spotlight.BradfordSkow -2009 -Journal of Philosophy 106 (12):666-678.
  17.  176
    How to Adjust Utility for Desert.BradfordSkow -2012 -Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90 (2):235-257.
    It is better when people get what they deserve. So we need an axiology according to which the intrinsic value of a possible world is a function of both how well-off and how deserving the people in that world are. But how should these ?desert-adjusted? values of possible worlds be calculated? It is easy to come up with some qualitative ideas. But these qualitative ideas leave us with an embarrassment of riches: too many quantitative functions that implement those qualitative ideas. (...) In this paper I will select one of these quantitative functions and defend its superiority. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  18.  482
    Preferentism and the paradox of desire.BradfordSkow -2009 -Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 2009 (3):1-17.
    The paradox of desire is an objection to desire-satisfaction, or preferentist, theories of welfare. In a nutshell, the objection goes like this. I can certainly desire that I be badly off. But if a desire-satisfaction theory of welfare is true, then—under certain assumptions—the hypothesis that I desire that I be badly off entails a contradiction. So much the worse for desire-satisfaction theories of welfare.
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  19.  198
    What makes time different from space?BradfordSkow -2007 -Noûs 41 (2):227–252.
    No one denies that time and space are different; and it is easy to catalog differences between them. I can point my finger toward the west, but I can’t point my finger toward the future. If I choose, I can now move to the left, but I cannot now choose to move toward the past. And (as D. C. Williams points out) for many of us, our attitudes toward time differ from our attitudes toward space. We want to maximize our (...) temporal extent and minimize our spatial extent: we want to live as long as possible but we want to be thin.1 But these differences are not very deep, and don’t get at the essence of the difference between time and space. That’s what I want to understand: I want to know what makes time different from space. I want to know which difference is the fundamental difference between them. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  20.  50
    The role of mathematics in explanation.BradfordSkow -2024 -Metascience 33 (2):169-171.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  350
    Haecceitism, anti-haecceitism, and possible worlds: A case study.BradSkow -2008 -Philosophical Quarterly 58 (230):97-107.
    Possible-worlds talk obscures, rather than clarifies, the debate about haecceitism. In this paper I distinguish haecceitism and anti-haecceitism from other doctrines that sometimes go under those names. Then I defend the claim that there are no non-tendentious definitions of ‘haecceitism’ and ‘anti-haecceitism’ using possible-worlds talk. That is, any definition of ‘haecceitism’ using possible-worlds talk depends, for its correctness, on a substantive theory of the nature of possible worlds. This explains why using possible-worlds talk when discussing haecceitism causes confusion: if the (...) parties to the discussion presuppose different theories of the nature of possible worlds, then they will mean different things by ‘haecceitism’. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  22.  320
    On the meaning of the question “How fast does time pass?”.BradSkow -2011 -Philosophical Studies 155 (3):325-344.
    In this paper I distinguish interpretations of the question ``How fast does time pass?’’ that are important for the debate over the reality of objective becoming from interpretations that are not. Then I discuss how one theory that incorporates objective becoming—the moving spotlight theory of time—answers this question. It turns out that there are several ways to formulate the moving spotlight theory of time. One formulation says that time passes but it makes no sense to ask how fast; another formulation (...) says that time passes at one second per supersecond; and a third says that time passes at one second per second. I defend the intelligibility of this final version of the theory. (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  23.  47
    (1 other version)Two Concepts of Double Prevention.BradfordSkow -2022 -Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 9.
    Is double prevention causation? Some say yes and some say no, but the answer is yes and no. Interrupting double prevention, where A prevents B from continuing to prevent something, is causation, while blocking double prevention, where A intervenes before B has begun preventing anything, is not. I present two arguments for this thesis. First, it sorts canonical examples of double prevention correctly. Second, well-known theoretical arguments that double prevention is not causation only show that blocking double prevention is not (...) causation. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  19
    The Report Versus the Transparency Models of Appreciation: The Case of Comics.BradfordSkow -2023 -Canadian Journal of Philosophy 53 (7-8):548-558.
    On the report model of appreciating fiction, one imagines learning about a fictional world through a report: reading or viewing someone’s account or listening to them tell their story. On the transparency model, one simply imagines the things that are fictional in the story, without imagining anything about how that information is acquired. It is argued that the transparency model is the default, in literature and cinema, but in comics, it is the report model that is the default.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  44
    On a Symmetry Argument for the Guidance Equation.BradfordSkow -unknown
    Bohmian mechanics faces an underdetermination problem: when it comes to solving the measurement problem, alternatives to the Bohmian guidance equa- tion work just as well as the official guidance equation. Dürr, Goldstein, and Zanghì have argued that of the candidate guidance equations, the official guid- ance equation is the simplest Galilean-invariant candidate. This symmetry argument—if it worked—would solve the underdetermination problem. But the argument does not work. It fails because it rests on assumptions about how Galilean transformations act on the (...) wavefunction that are unwarranted. My discussion has larger morals about the phys- ical significance of certain mathematical results in non-orthodox interpretations of quantum mechanics. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  75
    Against Understanding (as a condition on explanation).BradfordSkow -2017 - In Stephen Robert Grimm,Making Sense of the World: New Essays on the Philosophy of Understanding. New York, NY, United States of America: Oxford University Press.
    Argues that there is no interpretation of the commonly-accepted idea that "explanation is that which produces understanding" on which it is of any use for finding what philosophers looking for a theory of explanation have been after. Contains a close examination of a couple of philosophers' attempts to use this idea for that purpose.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  27. The Metaphysics of Quantities and Their Dimensions.BradfordSkow -2017 - In Karen Bennett & Dean W. Zimmerman,Oxford Studies in Metaphysics: Volume 10. Oxford University Press UK. pp. 171-198.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  28.  229
    Are There Genuine Physical Explanations of Mathematical Phenomena?BradfordSkow -2015 -British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 66 (1):69-93.
    There are lots of arguments for, or justifications of, mathematical theorems that make use of principles from physics. Do any of these constitute explanations? On the one hand, physical principles do not seem like they should be explanatorily relevant; on the other, some particular examples of physical justifications do look explanatory. In this article, I defend the idea that physical justifications can and do explain mathematical facts. 1 Physical Arguments for Mathematical Truths2 Preview3 Mathematical Facts4 Purity5 Doubts about Purity: I6 (...) Doubts about Purity: II7 How Physical Arguments Might Explain: I8 How Physical Arguments Might Explain: II9 Conclusion. (shrink)
    Direct download(11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  29.  188
    More on haecceitism and possible worlds.BradfordSkow -2011 -Analytic Philosophy 52 (4):267-269.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  30.  183
    A Solution to the Problem of Indeterminate Desert.BradfordSkow -2012 -Mind 121 (481):37-65.
    A desert-sensitive moral theory says that whether people get what they deserve, whether they are treated as they deserve to be treated, plays a role in determining what we ought to do. Some popular forms of consequentialism are desert-sensitive. But where do facts about what people deserve come from? If someone deserves a raise, or a kiss, in virtue of what does he deserve those things? One plausible answer is that what someone deserves depends, at least in part, on how (...) well he meets his moral requirements. The wicked deserve to suffer and the decent do not. Shelly Kagan (2006) has argued that this plausible answer is wrong. But his argument for that conclusion does not succeed. I will show how to formulate a desert-sensitive moral theory (and also a desert-sensitive version of consequentialism) on which this answer is correct. (shrink)
    Direct download(9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  184
    Sklar's Maneuver.BradfordSkow -2007 -British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (4):777-786.
    Sklar ([1974]) claimed that relationalism about ontology-the doctrine that space and time do not exist-is compatible with Newtonian mechanics. To defend this claim he sketched a relationalist interpretation of Newtonian mechanics. In his interpretation, absolute acceleration is a fundamental, intrinsic property of material bodies; that a body undergoes absolute acceleration does not entail that space and time exist. But Sklar left his proposal as just a sketch; his defense of relationalism succeeds only if the sketch can be filled in. I (...) argue that this cannot be done. There can be no (relationalist) dynamical laws of motion based on Sklar's proposal that capture the content of Newton's theory. So relationalists must look elsewhere for a relationalist interpretation of Newtonian mechanics. (shrink)
    Direct download(11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  32.  488
    Earman and Roberts on empiricism about laws.BradfordSkow -2007 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (1):158–162.
    Earman and Roberts (2005) argue that a standard definition of “empiricism about laws of nature” is inadequate, and propose an alternative definition they think is better. But their argument against the standard definition fails, and their alternative is defective.
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  149
    (1 other version)The role of chance in explanation.BradfordSkow -2013 -Australasian Journal of Philosophy (1):1-21.
    ?Those ice cubes melted because by melting total entropy increased and entropy increase has a very high objective chance.? What role does the chance in this explanation play? I argue that it contributes to the explanation by entailing that the melting was almost necessary, and defend the claim that the fact that some event was almost necessary can, in the right circumstances, constitute a causal explanation of that event.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  34.  59
    Of strawberries and energy conservation: Marc Lange: Because without cause: non-causal explanation in science and mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017, xxii+489pp, $74.00 HB.BradfordSkow -2017 -Metascience 27 (1):11-18.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  35.  122
    Extrinsic temporal metrics.BradfordSkow -2009 - In Dean Zimmerman,Oxford Studies in Metaphysics: Volume 5. Oxford University Press UK.
    When distinguishing absolute, true, and mathematical time from relative, apparent, and common time, Newton wrote: “absolute, true, and mathematical time, in and of itself and of its own nature, without reference to anything external, flows uniformly” [Newton 2004b: 64]. Newton thought that the temporal metric is intrinsic. Many philosophers have argued—for empiricist reasons or otherwise—that Newton was wrong about the nature of time. They think that the flow of time does involve “reference to something external.” They think that the temporal (...) metric is extrinsic. Among others, Mach, Poincaré, and Grünbaum seem to accept this view.1 And these are not the only two views available. Perhaps both Newton and his opponents are wrong and there is no temporal metric at all. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  100
    The Tenseless Theory of Time and the Moodless Theory of Modality.BradfordSkow -2018 -Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 100 (2):506-524.
    This paper develops a moodless theory of modality, intended to be as closely analogous to the tenseless theory of time as possible. It is argued that the new theory is distinct from David Lewis' modal realism and that it solves certain problems better than modal realism does, namely, the problem of advanced modalizing, the problem of necessitism, and the problem of conflict with common opinion.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  124
    On a Symmetry Argument for the Guidance Equation in Bohmian Mechanics.BradfordSkow -2010 -International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 24 (4):393-410.
    Bohmian mechanics faces an underdetermination problem: when it comes to solving the measurement problem, alternatives to the Bohmian guidance equation work just as well as the official guidance equation. One way to argue that the guidance equation is superior to its rivals is to use a symmetry argument: of the candidate guidance equations, the official guidance equation is the simplest Galilean-invariant candidate. This symmetry argument---if it worked---would solve the underdetermination problem. But the argument does not work. It fails because it (...) rests on assumptions about how Galilean transformations (especially boosts) act on the wavefunction that are (in this context) unwarranted. My discussion has larger morals about the physical significance of certain mathematical results (like, for example, Wigner's theorem) in non-orthodox interpretations of quantum mechanics. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  38.  92
    Replies to Deasy and Maudlin.BradfordSkow -2018 -Philosophical Studies 175 (7):1815-1823.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  136
    Some thoughts on Experiencing Time.BradfordSkow -2018 -Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 61 (3):302-314.
    This paper examples several arguments from Simon Prosser's book Experiencing Time. His argument against the doctrine of the specious present is applauded. His argument that even if time passes, nothing can detect the passage of time, is questioned. Also challenged are his claims that our experience represents things as enduring, rather than perduring, and represents things as having contradictory properties.
    No categories
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  104
    Local and Global Relativity Principles.BradfordSkow -2008 -Philosophers' Imprint 8:1-14.
    Local versions of the (special) principle of relativity say that if the same type of experiment is conducted in two isolated, unaccelerated laboratories, then the outcomes of those experiments must be the same. Global versions of the principle say that if you take a physically possible world and boost the entire material content of that world, you get another physically possible world. Some authors say that the local and the global principles are logically independent, and that the local version is (...) more important. These authors are wrong. I argue that the global version entails the local version, and discuss why a counterexample to this entailment offered by Tim Budden fails. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  112
    The Dynamics of Non-Being.BradfordSkow -2010 -Philosophers' Imprint 10.
    Maybe there is something rather than nothing because the nothingness force acted on itself, and when the nothing nothings itself it produces something. Robert Nozick suggested this as a candidate explanation of the fact that there is something rather than nothing. If he is right that it is a candidate explanation, we should pay attention: there are not many candidates out there. But his "explanation" looks, instead, like a paradigm case of philosophical nonsense. In this paper I describe a "metaphysical (...) dynamics" that makes sense out of Nozick's apparent nonsense. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  79
    Replies to Cameron, Wilson and Leininger.BradfordSkow -2018 -Analysis 78 (1):128-138.
    © The Author 2018. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of The Analysis Trust. All rights reserved. For Permissions, please email:[email protected] Cameron thinks that MST-Supertime, MST-Supertense and MST-Time are defective as versions of the moving spotlight theory and goes on to describe what he thinks they are missing. But I don’t think they are defective; and what Cameron says is missing from these theories is actually present in a version of MST-Time that appears in the book.Cameron thinks that (...) MST-Supertime, to start with, is inconsistent, and so the worst of the lot. He thinks McTaggart’s argument shows it to be inconsistent. But the theory is not inconsistent. We can draw a picture of what reality is like according to the theory, and the picture doesn’t confuse us the way M. C. Escher's pictures of inconsistent situations do. Figure 1 contains such a picture: the arrows... (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  43.  106
    Levels of Reasons and Causal Explanation.BradfordSkow -2017 -Philosophy of Science 84 (5):905-915.
    I defend the theory that the reasons why some event occurred are its causes. Many “counterexamples” to this theory turn on confusing two levels of reasons. We should distinguish the reasons why an event occurred from the reasons why those reasons are reasons. An example that treats a second-level reason as a first-level reason will look like a counterexample if that second-level reason is not a cause. But second-level reasons need not be first-level reasons.
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44.  166
    Notes on the Grandfather Paradox.BradfordSkow -manuscript
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  151
    Does Temperature Have a Metric Structure?BradfordSkow -2011 -Philosophy of Science 78 (3):472-489.
    Is there anything more to temperature than the ordering of things from colder to hotter? Are there also facts, for example, about how much hotter (twice as hot, three times as hot...) one thing is than another? There certainly are---but the only strong justification for this claim comes from statistical mechanics. What we knew about temperature before the advent of statistical mechanics (what we knew about it from thermodynamics) provided only weak reasons to believe it.
    Direct download(10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  46
    Kagan, Shelly. The Geometry of Desert.Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012. Pp. xviii+656. $74.00.BradfordSkow -2014 -Ethics 124 (2):417-426.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  55
    Precis of Objective Becoming.BradfordSkow -2018 -Philosophical Studies 175 (7):1787-1789.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  78
    Some Questions about The Moving Spotlight.BradfordSkow -2017 -Analysis 77 (4):800-810.
    © The Author 2017. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of The Analysis Trust. All rights reserved. For Permissions, please email:[email protected] don’t like sports, but it is a sports metaphor that comes to mind: if my team were out of the playoffs, I’d be rooting for Cameron. Unlike Cameron, I think that The Block Universe Theory of Time is true, but like Cameron I’ve argued that the best alternative, the theory it should be squaring off against in the (...) World Series of The Philosophy of Time, is The Moving Spotlight Theory. I came to Cameron’s book, therefore, curious about how his argument for this claim was going to go.1...Parts of the book really opened my eyes. I’m thinking especially of Cameron’s discussion of the argument that the presentist can, while the moving spotlight theorist cannot, accept the claim that they know that they are... (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  84
    Review of Harvey R. brown,Physical Relativity: Space-Time Structure From a Dynamical Perspective[REVIEW]BradfordSkow -2006 -Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2006 (5).
  50.  33
    Review: Shelly Kagan, The Geometry of Desert. [REVIEW]Review by: BradfordSkow -2014 -Ethics 124 (2):417-426,.
1 — 50 / 71
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp