Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for 'Blake Karl Winter'

933 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  9
    Sword of Philosophy: An Ontological Study.BlakeKarlWinter -2008 - Lanham: Upa.
    Sword of Philosophy attempts to address some of the fundamental questions in philosophy. The problem of the nature of values and ethics, the nature of logic and mathematics, and the nature of God is also considered.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Platon.ErnstKarlWinter -1930 - Wien,: Gsur.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  2
    Platon.ErnstKarlWinter -1930 - Wien,: Gsur.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Die Sozialmetaphysik der Scholastik.ErnstKarlWinter -1929 -Annalen der Philosophie Und Philosophischen Kritik 8:130-130.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5. (1 other version)Austria: Guilt and virtue—II.ErnstKarlWinter -forthcoming -Social Research: An International Quarterly.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  49
    Society and Religion in Early Ottoman Egypt. Studies in the Writings of ʿAbd al-Wahhāb al-ShaʿrānīSociety and Religion in Early Ottoman Egypt. Studies in the Writings of Abd al-Wahhab al-Sharani.Karl K. Barbir,MichaelWinter,ʿAbd al-Wahhāb al-Shaʿrānī &Abd al-Wahhab al-Sharani -1986 -Journal of the American Oriental Society 106 (3):589.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  3
    Die Sozialmetaphysik der Scholastik.ErnstKarlWinter -1929 - und Wien,: F. Deuticke.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. The rise and fall of austrian labor.ErnstKarlWinter -forthcoming -Social Research: An International Quarterly.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  51
    Rudolph IV. von Osterreich, I.Rudolph IV. von Osterreich, II.Philip E. Mosely &ErnstKarlWinter -1937 -Philosophical Review 46 (4):441.
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  46
    Voluntary and Involuntary Migrants: On Migration, Safe Third Countries, and the Collective Unfreedom of the Proletariat.MichaelBlake -2023 -Ethics and International Affairs 37 (4):427-451.
    The claims of those who are compelled to migrate are, in general, taken to be more urgent and pressing than the claims of those who were not forced to do so. This article does not defend the moral relevance of voluntarism to the morality of migration, but instead seeks to demonstrate two complexities that must be included in any plausible account of that moral relevance. The first is that the decision to start the migration journey is distinct from the decision (...) to stop that journey, through resettlement; the latter may involve voluntary choice, without that voluntarism impugning the involuntary nature of the former. The second is that the migration decision of the individual might be voluntary, even while that individual's family or social network might be compelled to insist upon some particular individual member's migration. That is, the fact that any particular person might be free to refuse migration does not contradict the fact that the group in question does not have the effective freedom to avoid the migration of some group members. Once these two complexities are understood, I argue, the moral relevance of voluntarism in the ethics of migration becomes more complex and nuanced than is generally understood. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  24
    Ontoepistemological interpretation of Jaspers and Heidegger from Holzapfel.Hugo Campos-Winter -2017 -Cinta de Moebio 58:74-88.
    Resumen: Este artículo tiene como propósito interpretar los pensamientos deKarl Jaspers y Martin Heidegger con los parámetros amalgama y sinergia de Cristóbal Holzapfel, y a partir de estos derivar proyecciones hacia la ontoepistemología de las ciencias sociales y humanas. Para esto se lleva a cabo un análisis comparativo entre las principales estructuras existenciales del esclarecimiento existencial presente en "Filosofía II" de Jaspers y la analítica existencial presente en "Ser y tiempo" de Heidegger. A partir de las amalgamas evidenciadas (...) entre ambas analíticas se deducen determinados existenciales que son analizados en su sinergia epistémica y proyectados hacia el esbozo de una posible ontoepistemología con base en las estructuras: concepto de ser humano, relación sujeto-objeto y relación investigador-investigado. Se obtuvo una concepción situada y proyectiva de ser humano, una relación sujeto-objeto como escisión compleja y una relación investigador-investigado fundada en una comunicación existencial enmarcada en la tradición discursiva de su respectiva comunidad semiótica.: This article intends to interpret the thoughts ofKarl Jaspers and Martin Heidegger with the parameters amalgam and synergy of Cristóbal Holzapfel in order to propose an ontoepistemology of the social and human sciences. For this objective, a comparative analysis is carried out between the main existential structures of the existential enlightenment present in "Philosophy II" of Jaspers and the existential analytic present in "Being and time" of Heidegger. From the amalgams evidenced between the two analytics, certain existential are deduced that are analyzed in their epistemic synergy and projected towards the outline of a possible ontoepistemology based on the structures: concept of human being, subject-object relationship and researcher-researched relationship. It was obtained a situated and projective conception of the human being, a subject-object relationship as a complex cleavage and a researcher-researched relationship founded on an existential communication framed in the discursive tradition of their respective semiotic community. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  65
    The Argument from Design: What Is at Stake Theologically?Anna Case-Winters -2000 -Zygon 35 (1):69-81.
    This article offers a brief overview of the argument for God's existence grounded in the evidence of design. It gives particular attention to the way the argument has evolved over time and in relation to changing scientific perspectives. The argument from de‐sign has in fact been formulated and reformulated in response to the discoveries and challenges it has encountered from the field of science. The conclusion of the article explores the theological importance of this argument—its extent and its limits.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  108
    Journey to transcendence: Dostoevsky’s theological polyphony in Barth’s understanding of the Pauline KRISIS.Elizabeth A.Blake &Rubén Rosario -2007 -Studies in East European Thought 59 (1):3-20.
    Anticipating Mikhail Bakhtin’s appreciation for the unfinalizability of Fedor Dostoevskij’s universe, prominent Protestant theologianKarl Barth celebrates the Russian novelist’s presentation of “the impenetrable ambiguity of human life” characteristic of both the ending of Dostoevsky’s novels and Paul’s Epistle to the Romans. Barth’s unique reading of The Brothers Karamazov not only demonstrates the barrenness of the “theocratic dream” but also complements Bakhtin’s discussion of polyphony with an explicitly theological dimension by focusing on the dialogue between Creator and the created. (...) Dostoevsky’s prophetic voice provides Barth with a poetic expression of the divine command that highlights the ethical dimension inherent in every theological choice. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  37
    Ein protokoll aus husserls logikseminar vomwinter 1925.Hans Reiner &Karl Schuhmann -1989 -Husserl Studies 6 (3):199-204.
  15.  25
    Philosophy and Poetry.Karl Britton -1961 -Philosophy 36 (136):74 - 76.
    Professor Brett has some direct acquaintance with a Joint Honours Degree in English Literature and Philosophy: and it is therefore on the basis of his own experience that he warns us that poetry and philosophy are “difficult pursuits for any man to combine” . This book has an introductory chapter and a short epilogue which deal in a philosophical way with meaning in poetry and in imaginative literature generally and with the nature of critical interpretation.In the four middle chapters the (...) author gives his account of four well-known and much discussed poems: Lycidas, the Essay on Man, the Ancient Mariner and the Four Quartets . One could imagine these chapters presented independently as interpretations and discussions of the literary and historical background of the poems: but they certainly illustrate Mr. Brett's theory of meaning in poetry and this provides a certain unity. Parts of Chapter I were first published by the author in Philosophy . What is new is the particular application of the theory to didactic and discursive poetry. To this is now added a discussion of rival theories of interpretation: first, the view expressed by Wimsatt and Beardsley in “The Intentional Fallacy” ; and, second, the views expressed by Miss Kathleen Raine in her essay onBlake. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Die Formalität der formalen Anzeige als deren Prinzipialität. Die Allgemeinheit philosophischer Begriffe.Karl Kraatz -2022 -Eksistenz. Philosophical Hermeneutics and Intercultural Philosophy 1 (1):91-110.
    The function of the formal indication is the mediation between concept and thing. This mediation is the concretization of the concept. I show that the formality of formal indications is the specific generality (Allgemeinheitscharakter) of philosophical concepts. This formality is their principality (Prinzipialität). Accordingly, a formally indicating concept would be a concept which gives the direction for the concretion as principally as possible. A principality which secures the repeatability and comprehensibility of philosophical insights. Looking at Heidegger’s lecture of the (...) class='Hi'>winter semester 1921/22, it is shown that 1) Heidegger understands the principality as the Being of beings, 2) that philosophical language is about the mediation between the principality of concepts and the concreteness of things; and 3) that this principality is identified with the formality of the formal indication. This early lecture is decisive for Heidegger’s whole philosophy because it lays bare the necessary relation between ontology and philosophy of language. (shrink)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Errors and traditions: Remarks on ErnstKarlwinter's article," the rise and fall of austrian labor".Charles A. Gulick &Alexander Gerschenkron -forthcoming -Social Research: An International Quarterly.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  58
    Als student bei Husserl: Ein brief vomwinter 1924/25. [REVIEW]Herbert Spiegelberg &Karl Schuhmann -1985 -Husserl Studies 2 (3):239-243.
  19.  34
    (1)Septimana Spinozana Acta Conventus oecumenici in memoriam Benedicti de Spinoza diei natalis trecentesimi Hagae comitis habiti curis Societatis Spinozanae edita. (Hagae comitis apud Martinum Nijhoff, MXMXXXIII Pp. xii + 321. Price 8 guilders net.)(2)Spinoza Festschrift. Herausgegeben von Siegfried Hessing. (Heidelberg:KarlWinter. 1933. Pp. xviii + 224. Price GM. 10.)(3)Spinoza, the Man and His Thought. Addresses delivered at the Spinoza Tercentenary sponsored by the Philosophy Club of Chicago. Edited by Edward L. Schaub. (Chicago: The Open Court Pub. Co. 1933. Pp. x + 61. Price 3s. 6d. net.). [REVIEW]A. Wolf -1936 -Philosophy 11 (42):211-.
  20. (1 other version)Winter, ErnstKarl, Die Sozialmetaphysik der Scholastik. [REVIEW]Johannes Hessen -1932 -Société Française de Philosophie, Bulletin 37:164.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  13
    81Alcuin undKarl der Große imWinter 769.Dietrich Lohrmann -2018 -Frühmittelalterliche Studien 52 (1):81-97.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Frühmittelalterliche Studien Jahrgang: 52 Heft: 1 Seiten: 81-97.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  44
    Interpretations of PolybiusKarl Friedrich Eisen: Polybiosinterpretationen: Beobachtungen zu Prinzipien griechischer und römischer Historiographie bei Polybios. (Bibliothek der klassischen Altertumswissenschaften, N. F. 2. Reihe.) Pp. 200. Heidelberg:Winter, 1966. Paper, DM. 20. [REVIEW]F. W. Walbank -1967 -The Classical Review 17 (01):35-36.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  35
    Vulgar LatinKarl Vossler: Einführung ins Vulgärlatein. Herausgegeben und bearbeitet von Helmut Schmeck. Pp. viii+215. Munich: Hueber, 1954. Paper, DM. 11.80. Helmut Schmeck: Aufgaben und Methoden der modemen vulgärlateinischen Forschung. Pp. 34. Heidelberg:Winter, 1955. Paper, DM. 3. [REVIEW]Robert Browning -1956 -The Classical Review 6 (3-4):252-254.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  59
    Die Hausschwelle in Sprache und Religion der Römer. Meister VonKarl. (Heidelberger Sitzungsberichte, 1924–25, 3. Abh.) Pp. 48. Heidelberg: CarlWinter, 1925. 2 marks. [REVIEW]H. J. Rose -1927 -The Classical Review 41 (1):41-41.
    No categories
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Phenomena and Mental Functions.Karl Bühler and Stumpf's Program in Psychology.Denis Fisette -2016 -Brentano Studien 14:191-228.
    This study focuses on the influence of the work of Carl Stumpf on the thought ofKarl Bühler. Our working hypothesis is based on the philosophical program that Bühler attributes to Stumpf and to which several of his works are largely indebted. It is divided into five parts. The first is intended to establish a relationship between Bühler and the School of Brentano to which Stumpf belongs. In the second, I show that Bühler became aware of Brentano's ideas and (...) of Stumpf's program during a stay at the Institute of Psychology of Berlin during thewinter semester 1904-1905, and I briefly comment, in the third part, Bühler's references to the work of Stumpf and two of his books in which he defends Stumpf's program against his critics. After having established the solid knowledge that Bühler had of Stumpf's work, I outline, in the fourth part, the main aspects of this program and evaluate, in the fifth, how Bühler uses it in the field of sensory phenomena (gestalt). I conclude this study with several remarks on Stumpf's positive evaluation of the work of Bühler. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  21
    Escaping the Shadow.Ryan Lam -2022 -Voices in Bioethics 8.
    Photo byKarl Raymund Catabas on Unsplash “After Buddha was dead, they still showed his shadow in a cave for centuries – a tremendous, gruesome shadow. God is dead; but given the way people are, there may still for millennia be caves in which they show his shadow. – And we – we must still defeat his shadow as well!” – Friedrich Nietzsche[1] INTRODUCTION Friedrich Nietzsche famously declared that “God is dead!”[2] but lamented that his contemporaries remained living in (...) the shadow of God. For Nietzsche, the morality of his time was still based in the Christian tradition, even though faith in God was waning. Bioethics lives under a similar shadow: the shadow of Enlightenment Era-rationalism. Bioethics curricula focus on principles derived from Kantian deontology and utilitarianism. The allure of maintaining a moral framework that provides a rational method that can be handily applied to any situation remains strong. The principlist approach advanced by Tom Beauchamp and James Childress is taught to nearly all medical students in the United States,[3] and is essentially the canonical ethical framework of bioethics. In this model, the principle of autonomy is Kantian in nature, and the principles of beneficence and non-maleficence are utilitarian in nature.[4] Moreover, the presented framework is an approach that, when applied rationally to any healthcare scenario, will yield an outcome “considered moral.”[5] This reflects a faulty conception of philosophy that plagues much of bioethics, wherein the only contribution of philosophy pertinent to bioethics is moral philosophy elucidated by European thinkers in the Enlightenment Era. The landscape of moral philosophy has evolved significantly from the 18th century. However, the bioethical world has not kept up with the philosophical world, remaining instead in the shadow of antiquated moral thinking. Also lacking in bioethics are other disciplines of philosophy, such as philosophy of language, existentialism, and aesthetics, which are often given no consideration at all. The inclusion of both modern moral philosophy and other philosophical fields is necessary if bioethics is to survive its transition into modernity. l. The Shadow of Enlightenment Enlightenment Era philosophers such as Immanuel Kant argued that one need only employ reason to obtain knowledge; emotion bore no relevance when determining ethical behavior. Kant’s moral theories thus privileged a duty to act according to moral imperatives over feelings. Other Enlightenment Era philosophers such as John Locke developed systems that attempted to quantify human goods and human ills. This quantification potentially reduces human welfare and suffering to utility. Today, in the world of philosophy, such a “neutral analysis,” as Cora Diamond noted, is “dead or moribund.”[6] Bernard Williams remarked that such moral philosophy is “empty and boring,”[7] and G. E. M. Anscombe stated that it “no longer generally survives.”[8] And yet, just as the atheists in Nietzsche’s world dwelt in the moral code of a dead God, bioethicists still pursue a unified moral system that takes an input, applies some moral rules, and generates a moral outcome, like the four principles approach that Beauchamp and Childress laid out.[9] Some detractors of principlism take issue with their approach for not being unified enough and want to replace it with a procedural framework that is even more systematic and complicated. They argue that the resulting moral framework would be a “comprehensive decision procedure for arriving at answers”[10] that retains the “impartiality that is an essential part of morality.”[11] The shadow of rationalist morality has caused bioethical decision making to become detached and rigid when bioethics should concern itself with the humans whose lives it affects. A rational, divorced-from-emotion way of thinking ultimately fails to yield satisfactory results when decisions are made by and for emotional beings. Dr. Paul Farmer, among others, championed the idea that bioethics should be de-philosophized, as philosophy, cold and calculated, fails to adequately respond to the realities of those worst off.[12] Instead, Dr. Farmer emphasized the inclusion of the social sciences, like sociology and anthropology, in bioethics. Undoubtedly, Dr. Farmer was on the right track; bioethics should certainly engage directly with the people whom its decisions involve. If the narrow band of moral philosophy currently found in bioethics – that of stringent rationalism – were all that philosophy had to offer, I, too, would advocate for a de-philosophization. Ludwig Wittgenstein notes that to attempt to capture the complexity of moral thinking in a manner that employs reason alone and casts aside emotion is a “hopeless task,” like reconstructing a sharp image “from a blurred one.”[13] Unfortunately, bioethics is mired in the remnants of this hopeless task. To Dr. Farmer, the dominant moral framework was too restrictive and was unresponsive to the social and humanitarian needs of those whom bioethics is meant to help. As such, he wished to free bioethics from the shadow of a morality derived from rationalist thinkers. ll. Beyond Rationalism Like Nietzsche, who tried to resolve Europe’s post-religion vacuum by providing his society with a new way to live, Dr. Farmer wanted to replace the rationalist philosophy upon which bioethics was built with a “resocialization” of the field.[14] I agree with Dr. Farmer’s call for resocialization, as well as his denouncement of philosophy as it exists in bioethics. Evaluating risks and benefits along a predetermined array of moral principles is far too rigid and impersonal to guide what are often the most important decisions one will make. For Dr. Farmer, the most needed change was restoring the social element of bioethics. However, in advocating for this resocialization, Dr. Farmer casts philosophy as the antithesis of social science, noting that “few would regard philosophy … as a socializing discipline.”[15] I disagree. Rationalist moral philosophy may be lacking in socializing force, but there are other fields of philosophy that are responsive to our social reality. Rather than de-philosophizing bioethics, it makes more sense to replace the antisocial philosophies predominant in bioethics with prosocial philosophies better suited to it. Of course, the contribution of philosophy to bioethics is more than moral theories from the Enlightenment Era. There are more recent philosophical contributions from outside the field of moral philosophy that have roused bioethical interest. Jennifer Blumenthal-Barby, et al., argue for philosophy’s continued place in bioethics, citing Derek Parfit’s “non-identity problem,” which altered the landscape of reproductive ethics, and David Chalmers’ contributions to philosophy of consciousness, which have implications for the moral status of brain organoids.[16] Still, these are narrow applications of philosophy to highly specialized areas of bioethics, which not all bioethicists are inclined to delve into. Philosophy in bioethics should not be confined to niche applications in specialist fields but should influence all bioethical thought. Fortunately, there remains untapped a wealth of philosophical disciplines that pertains to exactly this. Philosophy of language investigates the nature of meaning and understanding in communication, which is a necessary social action. Successfully deciphering and conveying moral values in discourse is a bioethicist’s bread and butter, as is resolving disagreements and reaching agreements. Indeed, it is often the case that miscommunication lies at the root of an impasse between a doctor and a patient. An understanding of the nature of the disagreement would help resolve the conflict, as different types of disagreements require different interventions for resolution. For instance, a “substantive disagreement,”[17] in which two parties use the same terms in the same ways and have a fundamental disagreement on which outcome is more desirable, can be resolved only if one party yields to the other. On the other hand, a “merely verbal dispute,”[18] in which two parties use the same terms to represent entirely different concepts and values, requires standardization of terminological usage for its resolution. As such, no one can overstate the moral importance of successful communication in bioethics, and an exploration of language itself would prove invaluable to a bioethicist’s training. Existentialism is another subset of philosophy that acknowledges the social nature of human existence, noting that one’s being in the universe is concomitant with the existence of others sharing the same universe.[19] Thus, there is the recognition that whatever existence is, it is not complete without the existence of others. With this as a starting point, existentialists examined how to live meaningfully with others in this world. Since ethics crucially involves others, it is no surprise that existentialists pondered how to live moral lives. Existentialist conceptions of morality did not revolve around acting in accordance with a set of rules, but rather, recognized individual freedom in choosing how to act and emphasized acting authentically. In this vein, bioethicists should commit to doing what is right rather than committing to applying a set of principles. Existentialism, while part of the broader bioethics literature, is less common throughout bioethics curricula and deserves more prominence. Martin Heidegger, for instance, emphasized the difference between two types of thinking: “calculative thinking” and “meditative thinking.” Heidegger characterizes calculative thinking as a computation, wherein from some given starting conditions “definite results”[20] are determined, and contrasts this with meditative thinking, which he describes as “thinking which contemplates the meaning which reigns in everything that is.”[21] Heidegger was critical of the pervasiveness of calculative thinking, seeing it as the “ground of thoughtlessness,”[22] in which we only relate to the world in a meaningless, mechanical way. This is the emphasized type of thinking in rationalist conceptions of morality popular in bioethics; from a set of starting conditions, a series of rules are applied, and a moral outcome is calculated. Such a technique, however, discounts the personal meaning individuals place on the aspects of their lives relevant to their decision making, as well as the meaning in committing to doing what is right. Under calculative thinking, such a commitment is reduced to rote rule-following. A turn to meditative thinking would ensure that bioethical decisions comport with living meaningful lives. Even aesthetics, a discipline devoted to examining beauty and taste,[23] has a place in bioethics. Just as the viewing of a painting, the listening of a song, or the reading of a book elicits an effective response, hearing a patient’s story leaves an emotional imprint. The recounting of a traumatic moment imparts sadness, and a joyous occasion begets joy in the listener as well. As acknowledged in the field of everyday aesthetics, these aesthetic experiences often spur us to act:[24] The unsightly appearance of a polluted riverbank drives us to remove the trash; the presence of sorrow in one’s life drives us to ameliorate it. To be mindful of aesthetic experiences and allow them to affect us emotionally is paramount to the motivation of a bioethicist to serve the patient, not out of an obligation to a job description, but out of a desire to truly avail the patient of their anguish. For example, the new field of narrative medicine utilizes critical reading and literary techniques to train clinicians and bioethicists in emotional understanding and listening skills that stress the social aspects of medicine beyond rational analysis and decision making. CONCLUSION Dr. Farmer is absolutely correct; bioethics is in dire need of resocialization. It should not be the case that the justification for a moral action is essentially that “the rules say so,” or that simply by teaching such rules to medical students, the very act of making bioethical decisions that diverge from those determined by principles can be seen as an act of “bad faith … hubris or, worse, malpractice.”[25] As bioethicists are coming to realize, the rationalist philosophical traditions that bioethics was founded upon are past their expiry, and the time for change is now. Indeed, as Dr. Farmer urges, “socializing disciplines” like anthropology, history, political economy, and sociology are necessary to humanize the field of bioethics.[26] So too, however, can philosophy be a socializing discipline, if we know where to look. Bioethics should evolve. Its new goal should be to focus on meaningful human relationships, and to phase out rigid, impersonal modes of moral thinking. The limited sampling of unsatisfying moral theories from hundreds of years ago leaves many bioethics students cold, and it is easy to see why bioethicists are ready to part ways with philosophy. I believe this is a move in the wrong direction; there is a place for philosophy in the future of bioethics. Just as bioethics needs a resocialization, it is also needs of a re-philosophization. These enrichments complement one another. There is more to bioethics than mechanically determining the right course of action in a healthcare setting. Bioethics engages with the most ancient of philosophical questions: questions of what makes human existence meaningful, what makes us who we are, how we want to relate to others, how and why we feel, what our place in the world is, how we can communicate what we think, and why our moral intuitions are so compelling. We would be remiss if we did not begin to investigate additional contributions to morality from a wider range of philosophies that try to provide answers to such questions, as they offer a richness to moral thinking that cannot be gleaned from traditional bioethical approaches alone. - [1] Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche, The Gay Science: With a Prelude in German Rhymes and an Appendix of Songs, ed. Bernard Williams, Josefine Nauckhoff, and Adrian Del Caro, Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy, 109. [2] Nietzsche, 120. [3] Daniel C O’Brien, “Medical Ethics as Taught and as Practiced: Principlism, Narrative Ethics, and the Case of Living Donor Liver Transplantation,” The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy: A Forum for Bioethics and Philosophy of Medicine 47, no. 1 : 97, https://doi.org/10.1093/jmp/jhab039. [4] K. D. Clouser and B. Gert, “A Critique of Principlism,” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 15, no. 2 : 219–36, https://doi.org/10.1093/jmp/15.2.219. [5] O’Brien, “Medical Ethics as Taught and as Practiced,” 97. [6] Cora Diamond, “Having a Rough Story about What Moral Philosophy Is,” New Literary History 15, no. 1 : 168, https://doi.org/10.2307/468998. [7] Bernard Williams, Morality: An Introduction to Ethics, Canto ed, xvii. [8] G. E. M. Anscombe, “Modern Moral Philosophy,” Philosophy 33, no. 124 : 1, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0031819100037943. [9] Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress, Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 7th ed, 13. [10] Clouser and Gert, 233. [11] Clouser and Gert, “A Critique of Principlism,” 235. [12] Paul Farmer and Nicole Gastineau Campos, “Rethinking Medical Ethics: A View from Below,” Developing World Bioethics 4, no. 1 : 17–41, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1471-8731.2004.00065.x. [13] Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, ed. Joachim Schulte, trans. P. M. S. Hacker, 4th edition, 40. [14] Farmer and Campos, “Rethinking Medical Ethics,” 20. [15] Farmer and Campos, 20. [16] Jennifer Blumenthal-Barby et al., “The Place of Philosophy in Bioethics Today,” The American Journal of Bioethics: AJOB, June 30, 2021, 3–5, https://doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2021.1940355. [17] Brendan Balcerak Jackson, “Verbal Disputes and Substantiveness,” Erkenntnis 79, no. S1 : 31–54, https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9444-5. [18] C. S. I. Jenkins, “Merely Verbal Disputes,” Erkenntnis 79, no. 1 : 11–30, https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9443-6. [19] Steven Crowell, “Existentialism,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta, Summer 2020, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/existentialism/; Anita Avramides, “Other Minds,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta,Winter 2020, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/other-minds/. [20] Martin Heidegger, Discourse on Thinking, Harper Torchbooks, 46. [21] Heidegger, 46. [22] Heidegger, 45. [23] Nick Zangwill, “Aesthetic Judgment,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta,Winter 2021, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/aesthetic-judgment/. [24] Yuriko Saito, “Aesthetics of the Everyday,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta, Spring 2021, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/aesthetics-of-everyday/. [25] O’Brien, “Medical Ethics as Taught and as Practiced,” 112. [26] Farmer and Campos, “Rethinking Medical Ethics,” 20. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. (1 other version)A World of Propensities.Karl R. Popper -1991 -Mind 100 (1):161-162.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  28.  58
    Kant's Theory of Mind.Karl Ameriks -1984 -Philosophical Quarterly 34 (137):514-515.
  29. The longstanding interest in business ethics.Karl-Erik Wärneryd &Alan Lewis -1994 - In Alan Lewis & Karl Erik Wärneryd,Ethics and economic affairs. New York: Routledge. pp. 1--14.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30.  21
    Joint contributions of collaborative facilitation and social contagion to the development of shared memories in social groups.Magdalena Abel &Karl-Heinz T. Bäuml -2023 -Cognition 238 (C):105453.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Existenzphilosophie.Karl Jaspers -1939 -Philosophical Review 48:556.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  32.  372
    Kant and the objectivity of taste.Karl Ameriks -1983 -British Journal of Aesthetics 23 (1):3-17.
  33.  10
    The initial brain concept: A work in progress.Karl Zilles &Gerd Rehkämper -1988 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):105-106.
  34.  21
    Abtreibung - Ja oder Nein: Ein synoptischer Beitrag zur Diskussion der Reformvorschläge im Strafrecht.Karl Horst Wrage -1971 -Zeitschrift Für Evangelische Ethik 15 (1):239-251.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  21
    Philosophische Autobiographie.Karl Jaspers -1977 - München: Piper.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  36.  12
    Die Religion Innerhalb Der Grenzen Der Blossen Vernunft. Hrsg. Und Mit Einer Einleitung Sowie Einem Personen- Und Sach-Register Versehen VonKarl Vorlander.Immanuel Kant &Karl Vorlander -2016 - Wentworth Press.
    This work has been selected by scholars as being culturally important, and is part of the knowledge base of civilization as we know it. This work was reproduced from the original artifact, and remains as true to the original work as possible. Therefore, you will see the original copyright references, library stamps (as most of these works have been housed in our most important libraries around the world), and other notations in the work. This work is in the public domain (...) in the United States of America, and possibly other nations. Within the United States, you may freely copy and distribute this work, as no entity (individual or corporate) has a copyright on the body of the work. As a reproduction of a historical artifact, this work may contain missing or blurred pages, poor pictures, errant marks, etc. Scholars believe, and we concur, that this work is important enough to be preserved, reproduced, and made generally available to the public. We appreciate your support of the preservation process, and thank you for being an important part of keeping this knowledge alive and relevant. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  25
    Reason and Existenz: five lectures.Karl Jaspers -1997 - Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.
    With the publication of Reason and Existenz, originally delivered as a series of five lectures at the University of Groningen in 1935, one of the most important of Jaspers's philosophic works is made available to the English-speaking world. It concerns itself with a general statement of the principal philosophic categories which have given uniqueness to Jaspers's thinking: existence, freedom, and history, and the limit-situations of death, suffering, and sin. Written shortly after Jaspers's major systematic work and before his analysis of (...) the problem of truth, Reason and Existenz occupies a primary position in the development of his thought. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  38. (2 other versions)Zur Psychologie des produktiven Denkens.Karl Duncker -1936 -Philosophical Review 45:427.
  39. Die Spiele der Menschen.Karl Groos -1899 -Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 48:87-96.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  52
    Northrop Frye: The Critical Passion.Angus Fletcher -1975 -Critical Inquiry 1 (4):741-756.
    I shall never forget my astonishment and delight on reading the 1949 essay, "The Function of Criticism at the Present Time," which in turn became the Polemic Introduction to Anatomy of Criticism, and my even greater astonishment and delight at the appearance of "Towards a Theory of Cultural History" , which eventually served as Essay 1 of the Anatomy, when revised and expanded. The remarkable thing about these articles was not so much their content as their assumption, namely, that criticism (...) could at least try to become a science. This assumption was couched in the form of most general scientific orientations, in that Frye took literature in its own terms,1 to begin with, and then did not prejudicially segregate and then destroy the claims of particular "minority groups" within the whole commonwealth of literary life. I did not know it at the time, but Frye was then, as now, fighting for a mode of civil rights. He was then, as now, a libertarian. He first made his name writing onBlake— freedom enough, perhaps—but it has always seemed to me that his center is as much Milton asBlake. But then, to knowBlake truly is to understand Milton. · 1. This assumption is to be distinguished from that of "early" Richards, which held that a science for literary studies had to come at literature from the outside, with chiefly psychological instruments. Richards' career has been the most complex critical "life" in our century, I believe, and it should be observed that he has held, and abandoned, more than one assumptive high ground during the course of his long and magnificent involvement with poetry. Angus Fletcher's numerous writings include Allegory: The Thought of a Symbolic Mode, The Prophetic Moment: An Essay on Spenser, The Transcendental Masque: An Essay on Milton's Comus, The Stranger God: A Theoretical Study of the Myth of Dionysus, and Thresholds: A Critical Approach to the English Renaissance. Northrop Frye's response, "Expanding Eyes" appears in theWinter 1975 issue. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  7
    Kalte Kunst?Karl Gerstner -1957 - Teufen AR, Schweiz,: A. Niggli.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Die vorsokratische Philosophie.Karl Goebel -1910 - Bonn,: C. Georgi.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Der Aufbau der Systeme.Karl Groos -1924 - Leipzig,: F. Meiner.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  13
    Judaism: Intra-Religious Plurality as a Chance for Discourse between Religions.Karl-Erich Grözinger -2003 - In Peter Koslowski,Philosophy bridging the world religions. Boston: Kluwer Academic. pp. 38--53.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Wie ist Wirtschaftsethik als Wissenschaft möglich? Zur Theoriestrategie einer modernen Wirtschaftsethik.Karl Homann &Ingo Pies -1994 -Ethik Und Sozialwissenschaften 5 (1):94-108.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  10
    Briefwechsel 1945-1968.Karl Jaspers -1983 - New York: Springer. Edited by Renato De Rosa & K. H. Bauer.
    Als Fritz Linder, Schtiler und Nachfolger von K. H. Bauer auf dem Heidelberger Lehrstuhl rur Chirurgie, am 12. Juli 1978 am Grabe seines Lehrers im Namen aller Freunde und Schuler sprach, erfuh­ ren wir, daB der Entschlafene "auf dem todlichen Krankenlager" noch seinen Briefwechsel mitKarl Jaspers las und ordnete. Diese letztwillige Vergegenwartigung einer freundschaftlichen Ver­ bindung aus den Jahren nach 1945 schien uns groBe menschliche Bedeutung zu haben, und wir waren erfreut, spater von Frau Bauer und Heinz Gotze, (...) Mitinhaber des Springer-Verlages, den Auftrag zur Herausgabe der Briefe zu erhalten, zumal sich mit beiden Kor­ respondenzpartnern eigene, dankbare Erinnerungen seit 1940 ver­ banden. Der Briefwechsel begann unmittelbar nach der ersten Begegnung yom 5.4. 1945 im Hause von Jaspers, als der Krieg rur Heidelberg vorbei war und politisch unbelastete Professoren vor der Aufgabe standen, die inzwischen geschlossene Universitat im Einvernehmen mit der Besatzungsbehorde wieder zu eroffnen und die Vorausset­ zungen rur die Wiederaufnahme freier Forschung und Lehre zu schaff en. Fur diesen Neubeginn, der natiirlich ein Neubeginn im Geiste des unveranderlich Gultigen sein sollte, war die daran anknupfende Freundschaft zwischen Bauer und Jaspers entscheidend. Die Person­ lichkeiten erganzten sich, und was beide damals suchten, war jeweils beim Partner zu finden: bei Jaspers die lebendige Idee in ihrem kla­ ren, wenn auch geschichtlich wandelbaren Wahrsein, bei Bauer die anpassungsfahige Vitalitat und die Gabe, Denken und Handeln zu verbinden. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Vom Sinn der Wissenschaft.Karl Ochsner -1953 - Winterthur,: Literarische Vereinigung, Kommissionsverlag W. Vogel.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Law as fact.Karl Olivecrona -1939 - London,: Oxford University PRess.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  122
    How to save Kant's deduction of taste.Karl Ameriks -1982 -Journal of Value Inquiry 16 (4):295-302.
  50.  15
    Essays in Philosophy: From David Hume to George Santayana.Houston Peterson -1974 - Pocket Books.
    With essays by David Hume, Jacques Rousseau, Immanuel kant, WilliamBlake, Jeremy Bentham, Richard Whately, John Henry Newman,Karl Marx, James Whistler, Friedrich Nietzsche, William James, etc.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 933
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp