Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs

Results for ' post-Kantian tradition'

943 found
Order:

1 filter applied
  1.  23
    Walter Benjamin and thePost-KantianTradition.Phillip Homburg -2017 - New York: Rowman & Littlefield International.
    Walter Benjamin and thePost-KantianTradition engages with Benjamin as a theorist of a historical and philosophical problematic, and demonstrates how Benjamin moves from an aspiring idealist philosopher to a politically engaged Marxist critic without abandoning the theoretical project he develops early on.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  83
    Re‐Reading thePostKantianTradition with Milbank.Gordon E. Michalson -2004 -Journal of Religious Ethics 32 (2):357-383.
    The essay explores the meaning and implications of Milbank's claim that thepostKantian presuppositions of modern theology must be eradicated. After defining and locating thepostKantian element in the context of Milbank's broader concerns, the essay employs a comparison between Milbank and Barth to draw out the differences between radical orthodoxy and neo‐orthodoxy with respect to theKantian ideal of “mediation” between theology and culture. The essay concludes with comparisons of Milbank's metanarrative concerning “modern” thought (...) with those offered by Hans Blumenberg and James Edwards. The effect is not only to suggest the apparent arbitrariness of Milbank's account, but also to indicate the evident futility of arguing with Milbank's theological position on the basis of alternative accounts of thepostKantiantradition. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  20
    Sacrifice in thePost-KantianTradition Perspectivism, Intersubjectivity, and Recognition.Paolo Diego Bubbio -2014 - Albany: State University of New York Press.
    _An examination of the philosophical notion of sacrifice from Kant to Nietzsche._.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  4. Deleuze, Hegel, and thePost-KantianTradition.Daniel W. Smith -2000 -Philosophy Today 44 (Supplement):119-131.
  5.  27
    Sacrifice in thePostKantianTradition: Perspectivism, Intersubjectivity, and Recognition. By Paolo Diego Bubbio. Pp. xiv, 212, Albany, NY, SUNY Press, 2014, $85.00. [REVIEW]Patrick Madigan -2017 -Heythrop Journal 58 (4):694-695.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  9
    Autonomy and Sympathy: APost-Kantian Moral Image.Filimon Peonidis -2005 - Upa.
    Individuals who value personal autonomy and sympathize with others can be guided by a set of central obligations that are familiar to those sharing in the Western moraltradition. These obligations may not be applicable to every imaginable situation, but the informed determination to act upon them is necessary for combating serious and easily identifiable moral evils. This overall argument is called apost-Kantian moral image. Here, "moral image" is understood as a comprehensive pattern of ethical thought (...) that retains a high level of generality and imposes some order on our normative considerations. The characterization "post-Kantian" indicates that the proposed moral image is inspired by and draws upon Kant's practical philosophy. At the same time it avoids certain problematicKantian positions and incorporates others that have been vehemently rejected by Kant— like the key role of emotion— in undertaking and justifying morality. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  22
    Autonomy and Sympathy: APost-Kantian Moral Image. By Filimon Peonidis.Irene Switankowsky -2006 -Maritain Studies/Etudes Maritainiennes 22:132-134.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  21
    G. Fichte as aPost-Kantian Philosopher and His Political Theory: A Return to Romanticism.Özgür Olgun Erden -2018 -IAFOR Journal of Ethics, Religion and Philosophy 4 (1):17-25.
    This paper fundamentally deals with J. G. Fichte’s philosophical views, which reshapes intellectual-philosophical bases of thepost-Enlightenment era and makes a strong criticism ofKantian thinking. Philosophically, Fichte’s philosophy, more representing a return to romanticism, will be debated on the basis of some concepts, among of which has been reason, science,tradition, religion, state, individual, and community. From his viewpoint, it will interrogate relationships among ego, morality and moral order. Based on these relationships, it will be tried (...) to explain what man’s moral nature is and how moral consciousness is conceptualized in Fichte’ thought. The debates between these concepts will provides basis for a political theory framed by Fichte. Also, it will indicate how a political theory there was developed, outlined by Fichte for German nation over two basic concepts, moral nature and moral consciousness. Taking account of all these discussions, in conclusion it will argue that his political theory had more liberal-conservative implications, along with nationalist ones. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  22
    Nineteenth-Century and Early Twentieth-CenturyPost-Kantian Philosophy.Paul Franks -2016 - In Herman Cappelen, Tamar Gendler & John Hawthorne,The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    This article examines three moments of thepost-Kantian philosophicaltradition in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries: Kantianism,Post-Kantian Idealism, and Neo-Kantianism. It elucidates the distinctive methods of atradition that has never entirely disappeared and is now acknowledged once again as the source of contemporary insights. It outlines two problematics—naturalist scepticism and historicist nihilism—threatening the possibility of metaphysics. The first concerns sceptical worries about reason, emerging from attempts to extend the methods of natural (...) science to the study of human beings. Kant’s project of a critical and transcendental analysis of reason, with its distinctive methods, should be considered a response. The second arises from the development of new methods of historical inquiry, seeming to undermine the very possibility of individual agency. Also considered are Kant’s successors’ revisions of the critical and transcendental analysis of reason, undertaken to overcome challenges confronting the original versions of Kant’s methods. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  45
    The Hegelian Dialectic andPost-Kantian Idealism.Vernon J. Bourke -1942 -Modern Schoolman 19 (4):66-69.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  42
    The Being of Negation inPost-Kantian Philosophy.Gregory S. Moss (ed.) -2022 - Springer Verlag.
    By drawing on the insights of diverse scholars from around the globe, this volume systematically investigates the meaning and reality of the concept of negation inPost-Kantian Philosophy—German Idealism, Early German Romanticism, and Neo-Kantianism. The reader benefits from the historical, critical, and systematic investigations contained which trace not only the significance of negation in these traditions, but also the role it has played in shaping the philosophical landscape ofPost-Kantian philosophy. By drawing attention to historically neglected (...) thinkers and traditions, and positioning the dialogue within a global and comparative context, this volume demonstrates the enduring relevance ofPost-Kantian philosophy for philosophers thinking in today’s global context. This text should appeal to graduate students and professors of German Idealism,Post-Kantian philosophy, comparative philosophy, German studies, and intellectual history. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. The Impact of Idealism: Volume 4, Religion: The Legacy ofPost-Kantian German Thought.Nicholas Adams (ed.) -2013 - Cambridge University Press.
    The first study of its kind, The Impact of Idealism assesses the impact of classical German philosophy on science, religion and culture. This fourth volume explores German Idealism's impact on theology and religious ideas in the nineteenth, twentieth and twenty-first centuries. With contributions from leading scholars, this collection not only demonstrates the vast range of Idealism's theological influence across different centuries, countries, continents, traditions and religions, but also, in doing so, provides fresh insight into the original ideas and themes with (...) which Kant, Hegel, Fichte, Schelling and others were concerned. As well as tracing out the Idealist influence in the work of nineteenth- and twentieth-century theologians, philosophers of religion, and theological traditions, from Schleiermacher, to Karl Barth, to Radical Orthodoxy, the essays in this collection bring each debate up to date with a strong focus on Idealism's contemporary relevance. (shrink)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  191
    From 'Convention' to 'Ethical Life': Hume's Theory of Justice inPost-Kantian Perspective.Kenneth Westphal -2010 -Journal of Moral Philosophy 7 (1):105-132.
    Hume and contemporary Humeans contend that moral sentiments form the sole and sufficient basis of moral judgments. This thesis is criticised by appeal to Hume’s theory of justice, which shows that basic principles of justice are required to form and to maintain society, which is indispensable to human life, and that acting according to, or violating, these principles is right, or wrong, regardless of anyone’s sentiments, motives or character. Furthermore, Hume’s theory of justice shows how the principles of justice are (...) artificial without being arbitrary. In this regard, Hume’s theory belongs to the unjustly neglected modern natural lawtradition. Some key merits of this strand in Hume’s theory are explicated by linking it to Kant’s constructivist method of identifying and justifying practical principles (à la O’Neill), and by showing how and why Hegel adopted and further developed Kant’s constructivism by re-integrating it with Hume’s central natural law concern with our actual social practices. (Slightly revised English translation by the author of „Von der Konvention zur Sittlichkeit. Humes Begründung einer Rechtsethik aus nach-Kantischer Perspektive“, on which see below.). (shrink)
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  14.  49
    Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development ofPost-Kantian Idealism. By George di Giovanni and H. S. Harris. [REVIEW]Victoria S. Wike -1988 -Modern Schoolman 65 (3):213-213.
  15. Kantian origins : one possible path from Transcendental Idealism to a "PostKantian" philosophical theology.Paul Redding -2012 - In Paolo Diego Bubbio & Paul Redding,Religion after Kant: God and Culture in the Idealist Era. Newcastle upon Tyne, UK: Cambridge Scholars Press.
    After two centuries of Kant interpretation there is still no general agreement over the nature of Kant’s most basic philosophical commitments. One issue in particular about which it is difficult to find consensus is his metaphilosophical attitude towards the very project of metaphysics itself. Recently, a type of deflationist reading of Kant has been appealed to in order to address the problems inherent in his more traditional construal as a metaphysical skeptic who denies us the capacity to have any knowledge (...) of “things in themselves”, but who nevertheless seems to centrally rely on the existence of just such things.1 But how is either deflationism or skepticism consistent with Kant’s avowed intention in the Critique of Pure Reason to put metaphysics on the path of science,2 or with his signaled but unfulfilled intention to write a “Metaphysics of Nature”? (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  64
    The Critical Function of the Epigenesis of Reason and Its Relation toPost-Kantian Intellectual Intuition.Dalia Nassar -2017 -Philosophy Today 61 (3):801-809.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Kantian origins: one possible path from Transcendental Idealism to a "PostKantian" philosophical theology.Paul Redding -2012 - In Paolo Diego Bubbio & Paul Redding,Religion after Kant: God and Culture in the Idealist Era. Newcastle upon Tyne, UK: Cambridge Scholars Press.
    After two centuries of Kant interpretation there is still no general agreement over the nature of Kant’s most basic philosophical commitments. One issue in particular about which it is difficult to find consensus is his metaphilosophical attitude towards the very project of metaphysics itself. Recently, a type of deflationist reading of Kant has been appealed to in order to address the problems inherent in his more traditional construal as a metaphysical skeptic who denies us the capacity to have any knowledge (...) of “things in themselves”, but who nevertheless seems to centrally rely on the existence of just such things.1 But how is either deflationism or skepticism consistent with Kant’s avowed intention in the Critique of Pure Reason to put metaphysics on the path of science,2 or with his signaled but unfulfilled intention to write a “Metaphysics of Nature”? (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  17
    Isaiah Berlin: aKantian andpost-idealist thinker.Robert Kocis -2022 - [Cardiff]: University of Wales Press.
    This book argues that the Russian-British philosopher Isaiah Berlin should primarily be understood through British idealism. Though he adoptedKantian methodology and a view of people as purposive beings, he rejected the Idealists' monism and theories of positive liberty. Robert A. Kocis demonstrates how, like Michael Oakeshott and R. G. Collingwood, Berlin can be seen as a 'post-Idealist' thinker, invested in the implications of that richtradition.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  39
    What is aPost-HegelianKantian?Robert Piercey -2007 -Philosophy Today 51 (1):26-38.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  46
    Tradition(S): Refiguring Community and Virtue in Classical German Thought.Stephen H. Watson -1997 - Indiana University Press.
    Tradition(s) accomplishes this through a series of original readings of Kant andpost-Kantian German philosophy, in which topics such as Kant on friendship, nature inpost-Kantian thought, HeideggerÕs relationship to Hobbes, and HegelÕs ...
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  29
    Post-Neo-Kantianism. What is this?Andrzej Jan Noras -2020 -RUDN Journal of Philosophy 24 (1):89-98.
    The article attempts to define the concept of “post-neo-Kantianism” based on the nature of its relationship to the concept of “neo-Kantianism”. Concerning this matter, the author poses the following tasks: to characterize the phenomenon of neo-Kantianism, to point out the problems of its definition, to identify the relevance of the term “post-neo-Kantianism” and its relation to the philosophy of I. Kant in particular. The author emphasizes the need to introduce this term in the classification of philosophy of the (...) XX century with the appropriateness of building the model of “Kantianism - Neo-Kantianism - Neo-Neo-Kantianism -Post-Neo-Kantianism”, where each new stage is determined by the nature of the reflection of thinkers of a certain period over the fundamental philosophical problems articulated in Kant's “Critics”. Among thepost-Neo-Kantians, A. Noras names thinkers traditionally considered to be german phenomenologists, such as E. Husserl and M. Heidegger: it is from the philosophical concept of Husserl that one can speak of the emergence ofpost-Neo-Kantianism, and the semantically correct interpretation of Heidegger, according to author, is most clearly understood in the framework of Baden Neo-Kantianism. Investigating the phenomenon ofpost-Neo-Kantianism, the need is established for answering a question regarding the preceding Neo-Kantiantradition, within which there is still a number of contradictions unresolved in the history of philosophy regarding the classification of Neo-Kantian schools and the distinction between the two periods of Neo-Kantianism: early and late. Neo-Kantianism shows the relevance ofKantian philosophy, highlighting the ongoing debate about understanding theKantian “Critique of Pure Reason”.Post-Neo-Kantianism plays an important role in terms of the perspectives of modern Kant studies, which include Gottfried Martin, Manfred Brelage, or Hans-Michael Baumgartner. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  226
    Going beyond theKantian philosophy: On McDowell's Hegelian critique of Kant.Robert Stern -1999 -European Journal of Philosophy 7 (2):247–269.
    The Kant-Hegel relation has a continuing fascination for commentators on Hegel, and understandably so: for, taking this route into the Hegelian jungle can promise many advantages. First, it can set Hegel’s thought against a background with which we are fairly familiar, and in a way that makes its relevance clearly apparent; second, it can help us locate Hegel in the broader philosophicaltradition, making us see that the traditional ‘analytic’ jump from Kant to Frege leaves out a crucial period (...) inpost-Kantian thought; third, it can show Hegel in a progressive light, as attempting to take thattradition further forward; fourth, it can help us locate familiar philosophical issues in Hegelian thought that otherwise can appear wholly sui generis; and finally, and perhaps most importantly of all, focusing on this relation can help raise and crystalise some of the fascinating ambiguities concerning Hegel’s outlook, regarding whether Hegel’s response to Kant shows him to have been a reactionary, Romantic, pre-critical thinker, who sought to turn the philosophical clock back to a time before Kant had written, or a modernist, Enlightened and essentially critical one, who remained true to the spirit if not the letter of Kant’s philosophy. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  23.  16
    Tradition(s) Ii: Hermeneutics, Ethics, and the Dispensation of the Good.Stephen H. Watson -2001 - Indiana University Press.
    Tradition II Hermeneutics, Ethics, and the Dispensation of the Good Stephen H. Watson Examines concepts oftradition in 20th-century Continental philosophy. InTradition II, Stephen H. Watson engagespost-Kantian Continental philosophy in his continuing investigation into the concept oftradition which he began in his work,Tradition. According to Watson, the problem oftradition became explicit in 20th-century philosophy, and is especially apparent in the work of Heidegger, Gadamer, Husserl, Benjamin, Adorno, Levinas, (...) Kristeva, and Derrida, among others. By formulating a series of dialogues between these philosophers and their predecessors, Watson articulates the issues and concerns surroundingtradition and traditionality. Taking on topics such as the hermeneutics of the self, the rationality oftradition, the pluralistic nature of historical interpretation, and the question of the "other," Watson emphasizes the importance of classical accounts of ethical and political discourse for contemporary philosophy and today’s multicultural world. Watson extends his analysis oftradition to include the problems of meaning and narrative and the nature of the self. He also considers the meaning of the Good and how Good is dispensed in the world. By questioning past philosophical narratives and their influence on modern and postmodern philosophy, Watson brings fresh perspective to the complex meanings oftradition for a pluralistic world. Stephen H. Watson is Professor of Philosophy and Chair of the Philosophy Department at the University of Notre Dame. He is author of Extensions: Essays on Interpretation, Rationality, and the Closure of Modernism andTradition: Refiguring Community, Remembrance, and Virtue in Classical German Thought. Studies in Continental Thought—John Sallis, general editor June 2001 320 pages, 6 1/8 x 9 1/4, index cloth 0-253-33900-6 $35.00 s / £26.50. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24.  32
    Women Philosophers in the Long Nineteenth Century: The GermanTradition ed. by Kristin Gjesdal and Dalia Nassar (review).Alison Stone -2023 -Journal of the History of Philosophy 61 (2):336-337.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Women Philosophers in the Long Nineteenth Century: The GermanTradition ed. by Kristin Gjesdal and Dalia NassarAlison StoneKristin Gjesdal and Dalia Nassar, editors. Women Philosophers in the Long Nineteenth Century: The GermanTradition. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021. Pp. 336. Hardback, $99.00."How plausible, [Dalia Nassar and I] kept asking, is it that women published philosophy in the early modern period and then simply ceased to think (...) and publish philosophy in the nineteenth century?" remarked Kristin Gjesdal recently (interview with Richard Marshall, 3:16am [blog], https://www.3-16am.co.uk/articles/gadamer-herder-and-the-womenphilosophers-of-the-long-nineteen-cent ury?c=end-times-series). Not plausible at all—yet this is what historians of women in philosophy often seem to have assumed, judging by the remarkably small amount of scholarship on nineteenth-century women philosophers compared with those of the early modern period or the twentieth century. Eileen O'Neill, for instance, claims that it was "not a particularly friendly century for women philosophers" (1). In fact, as Gjesdal and Nassar observe, women were "significant contributors" to the "thriving intellectual cultures in German-speaking countries" at this time (1). Gjesdal and Nassar contrast Germanic countries to France and Britain in this regard, yet I would add that nineteenth-century Britain too had a vibrant print and periodical culture that created openings for women philosophers such as Harriet Martineau, Anna Jameson, Frances Power Cobbe, and many others. The broader point remains: the nineteenth century has only seemed empty of women philosophers because we have not yet investigated the women thinkers of this period or challenged the canons and narratives from which they have been excluded.Recognizing German women philosophers is particularly important because the vast majority of scholarship on the nineteenth century focuses on the Germantradition. Consequently, unless we recover the work of German-speaking women, we will never change the narrative about this period. This makes the present anthology invaluable for both teaching and research. Edited by Gjesdal and Nassar, it contains new translations, nearly all by Anna Ezekiel, of texts by historical German-speaking women philosophers.Regarding teaching, many courses onpost-Kantian European philosophy include no women until Beauvoir or Arendt. Such courses typically cover Fichte, Hegel, Marx, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, Husserl, and Heidegger. The editors have clearly designed this volume to enable instructors easily to bring women into such courses, by providing extracts—of suitable lengths for teaching—from women affiliated respectively with German idealism and Romanticism (Germaine de Staël, Karoline von Günderrode, and Bettina von Arnim), Marxism (Clara Zetkin, Rosa Luxemburg), Nietzscheanism (Hedwig Dohm, Lou Salomé), and phenomenology (Edith Stein, Gerda Walther). Some of these women are already well-known as political activists, as with Luxemburg and Zetkin, or under the elastic heading of "writers," as with Staël and von Arnim. But this collection presents these women's writings in a new light, showcasing their philosophical side. After all, we have learned to read Marx and Nietzsche philosophically: why not extend the same courtesy to Staël or Luxemburg?For researchers, this collection will likewise be invaluable.Post-Kantian European philosophy has been slow to respond to the wider questioning and broadening of the traditional philosophical canon. It remains sadly common for narratives of nineteenth-century German philosophy to discuss men only—a position that this book makes untenable. [End Page 336] Hopefully it will galvanize philosophers to integrate these women into the historiography of thepost-Kantiantradition at last.In the introduction, the editors helpfully contextualize the selected writings, arguing that these women's exclusion from academic institutions led them to philosophize in ways that spoke to general audiences, connected with lived experience, and addressed practical and political concerns. In short, these women did a type of philosophy that was not purified but socially engaged, and can be a model for us today. Thereafter the book consists of sections on nine women philosophers, ordered chronologically. Each section begins with an editorial introduction to the philosopher and her interests, ideas, writings, and interlocutors.The writings included from Staël—whose work spans the period from the French Revolution into Romanticism—are "On Women Writers" from... (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  86
    Presence andPost-Modernism.James Mensch -1997 -American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 71 (2):145-156.
    Thepost-modern,post-enlightenment debate on the nature of being begins with Heidegger’s assertion that the “ancient interpretation of the being of beings” is informed by “the determination of the sense of being as ... ‘presence.’”[i] This understanding, which reduces being to temporal presence, is supposed to have set all subsequent philosophical reflection. At its origin is “Aristotle’s essay on time.” In Heidegger’s reading, Aristotle interprets entities with regard to the present, equating their being with temporal presence. He also (...) takes time itself as a present entity--i.e., “as just one being among others.”[ii] In an interpretation that is essentially “oriented to the world,” Aristotle thus collapses being and temporal presence to the point that the countable nows are, in their presence, taken as entities. Aristotle’s essay, Heidegger claims, “has essentially determined every subsequent account of time--Bergson’s included.” Even “theKantian interpretation of time” remains under its sway.[iii] Given this, the “destruction” of thetradition that Heidegger proposes[iv] is a destruction of this account.[v] Only through such a destruction can we uncover what the Aristotelian account conceals. In making time objective, it hides Dasein’s (or human being’s) role in temporalization. The project of Being and Time is to uncover this through “the repeated interpretation of the structures of Dasein ... as modes of temporalization.”[vi]. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  38
    The Religious Significance of Ricoeur’sPost-HegelianKantian Ethics.Gary B. Herbert &Patrick L. Bourgeois -1991 -Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 65:133-144.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  119
    Pierre Bourdieu: From neo-Kantian to Hegelian critical social theory.Paul Redding -2005 -Critical Horizons 6 (1):183-204.
    This paper challenges the commonly made claim that the work of Pierre Bourdieu is fundamentally anti-Hegelian in orientation. In contrast, it argues that the development of Bourdieu's work from its earliest structuralist through its later 'post-structuralist' phase is better described in terms of a shift from a late nineteenth century neo-Kantian to a distinctly Hegelianpost-Kantian outlook. In his break with structuralism, Bourdieu appealed to a bodily based 'logic of practice' to explain the binaristic logic of (...) Lévi-Strauss' structuralist analyses of myth. Effectively working within thetradition of the Durkheimian approach to symbolic classification, Lévi-Strauss had inherited Durkheim's distinctly neo-Kantian understanding of the role of categories in experience and action—an account that conflated two forms of representation—'intuitions' and 'concepts—that Kant himself had held distinct. Bourdieu's appeal to the role of the body's dispositional habitus can be considered as a retrieval of Hegel's earlier quite different reworking of Kant's intuition-concept distinction in terms of distinct 'logics' with different forms of 'negation'. Bourdieu commonly acknowledged the parallels of his analyses of social life to those of Hegel, but opposed Hegelianism because he believed that Hegel had remained entrapped within the dynamics of mythopoeic thought. In contrast, Durkheim and Lévi-Strauss, he claimed, by instituting a science of myth, had broken with it. This criticism of Hegel, however, relies on an understanding of his philosophy that has been rejected by many contemporary Hegel scholars, and without it, the gap separating Hegel and Bourdieu narrows dramatically. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  8
    In apost-Hegelian spirit: philosophical theology as idealistic discontent.Gary J. Dorrien -2020 - Waco, Texas: Baylor University Press.
    Hegel broke open the deadliest assumptions of Western thought by conceiving being as becoming and consciousness as the social-subjective relation of spirit to itself, yet his white Eurocentric conceits were grotesquely inflated even by the standards of his time. With In aPost-Hegelian Spirit, Gary Dorrien emphasizes both sides of this Hegelian legacy, contending that it takes a great deal of digging and refuting to recover the parts of Hegel that still matter for religious thought. By distilling his signature (...) argument about the role ofpost-Kantian idealism in modern Christian thought, Dorrien fashions a liberationist form of religious idealism: apost-Hegelian religious philosophy that is simultaneously both Hegelian as it expounds a fluid, holistic, open, intersubjective, ambiguous, tragic, and reconciliatory idea of revelation andpost-Hegelian, as it rejects the deep-seated flaws in Hegel's thought. Dorrien mines Kant, Schleiermacher, and Hegel as the foundation of his argument about intellectual intuition and the creative power of subjectivity. After analyzing critiques of Hegel by SA, ren Kierkegaard, Karl Marx, Karl Barth, and Emmanuel Levinas, Dorrien contends that though these monumental figures were penetrating in their assessments, they appear one-sided compared to Hegel. In aPost-Hegelian Spirit further engages with the personal idealisttradition founded by Borden Parker Bowne, the processtradition founded by Alfred North Whitehead, and the daring cultural contributions of Paul Tillich, W.E.B. Du Bois, Martin Luther King, Jr., Rosemary Radford Ruether, David Tracy, Peter Hodgson, Edward Farley, Catherine Keller, and Monica Coleman. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  92
    BeyondTradition and Modernity.Robert R. Williams -2006 -The Owl of Minerva 37 (1):29-56.
    Although Hegel has been rediscovered frequently, few have focused on Hegel’s speculative theology. Since Hegel criticizes traditional theology, it is widely assumed that he must be an atheist. But Hegel rejects the alternatives of a fossilized orthodoxy and apost-religious secularity. Hegel’s speculative philosophy has profound significance for Christian theological reconstruction. This essay focuses on Hegel’s philosophy of religion as a philosophical theology in thepost-Kantian,post-Enlightenment context. Hegel rejects philosophies of finitude as nihilistic. Second, it (...) examines how Hegel’s attempt to provide a logical map of world religions demonstrates the impossibility of such a logical mapping. Third, it concludes with an examination of eschatology: Hegel criticizes the dualist eschatology of religious representation because it undermines the actuality of reconciliation. The eschatology of the concept can only be taken up in the context of Hegel’s views concerning tragedy and the death of God. The suffering God excludes any triumphalist realized eschatology or end of history culmination. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  186
    Phantom of consistency: Alain Badiou andKantian transcendental idealism.Adrian Johnston -2008 -Continental Philosophy Review 41 (3):345-366.
    Immanuel Kant is one of Alain Badiou’s principle philosophical enemies. Kant’s critical philosophy is anathema to Badiou not only because of the latter’s openly aired hatred of the motif of finitude so omnipresent inpost-Kantian European intellectual traditions—Badiou blames Kant for inventing this motif—but also because of its idealism. For Badiou-the-materialist, as for any serious philosophical materialist writing in Kant’s wake, transcendental idealism must be dismantled and overcome. In his most recent works, Badiou attempts to invent a non- (...) class='Hi'>Kantian notion of the transcendental, a notion compatible with the basic tenets of materialism. However, from 1988’s Being and Event up through the present, Badiou’s oeuvre contains indications that he hasn’t managed fully to purge the traces ofKantian transcendental idealism that arguably continue to haunt his system—with these traces clustering around a concept Badiou christens “counting-for-one”. The result is that, in the end, Kant’s shadow still falls over Badiouian philosophy—this is despite Badiou’s admirable, sophisticated, and instructive attempts to step out from under it—thus calling into question this philosophy’s self-proclaimed status as materialist through and through. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  31.  65
    The irrational in the rational, or: John McDowell’s dialectic of enlightenment.Tom Whyman -2023 -Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 66 (3):332-354.
    Post-Kantian philosophers typically hold there to be a coincidence between reason and freedom. In this paper, I question their ability to secure this coincidence. I do so in particular by examining the work of John McDowell: probably the leading light of contemporary analyticpost-Kantian philosophy, and certainly someone for whom the coincidence is important. Working through McDowell, I argue that in order to be considered ‘rationally free’ in relation to the external world, the world itself needs (...) to, at at least some level, elude rational understanding. In the conclusion, I claim that this invites greater engagement – particularly bypost-Kantian philosophers working in the analytictradition – with the work of Theodor Adorno. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  20
    José Ortega y Gasset y la generación de 1911. Reflexiones en torno a la filosofía «post-neokantiana».Dorota Leszcyna -2017 -Contrastes: Revista Internacional de Filosofía 20 (1).
    RESUMENEl intento del presente artículo es investigar el lugar de Ortega en el panorama del pensamiento europeo, especialmente alemán, de la primera mitad del siglo XX, utilizando uno de los conceptos fundamentales de su filosofía, es decir, el concepto de la «generación». Por tanto se defiende la tesis de que Ortega puede ser considerado como uno de los representantes de la generaciónpost-neokantiana llamada por él mismo la generación de 1911 y que el pensamiento orteguiano se inscriba en el (...) programa intelectual de filósofos como: Nicolai Hartmann, Heinz Heimsoeth, Karl Jaspers o Martin Heidegger. Todos estos filósofos brotan de la tradición neokantiana y la superan creando una nueva actitud filosófica centrándose en la reflexión ontológica y en el proyecto de superar el idealismo moderno.PALABRAS CLAVESORTEGA, GENERACIÓN, NEOKANTISMO,POST-NEOKANTISMO, ONTOLOGÍA, IDEALISMO ABSTRACTThe aim of this paper is to investigate the site of Ortega in the panorama of European, especially German thought, in the first half of the twentieth century, using one of the fundamental concepts of his philosophy, that is, the concept of «generation». Therefore I will defend the thesis that Ortega can be considered as one of the representatives of thepost-neo-Kantian generation, called by himself the «generation of 1911» and that Ortega’s thought participates in the intellectual program of philosophers such as: Nicolai Hartmann, Heinz Heimsoeth, Karl Jaspers or Martin Heidegger. All these philosophers emerge from the neo-Kantiantradition but it overcomes, creating a new philosophical attitude, focusing on ontological reflection and on the project to overcome modern idealism.KEYWORDSORTEGA, GENERATION, NEO-KANTIANISM,POST-NEO-KANTIANISM, ONTOLOGY, IDEALISM. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  121
    Who’s Who from Kant to Hegel I: In theKantian Wake.Peter Graham Thielke -2010 -Philosophy Compass 5 (5):385-397.
    While almost all of Kant's contemporaries agreed that the Critique of Pure Reason effected a philosophically epochal change, there was far less consensus about what precisely Kant's new critical philosophy had brought about. In large part, this uncertainty was a result of a methodological crisis that Kant's work had sparked: the Critique had shown that traditional dogmatic metaphysics was suspect at best, but what new methods needed to be adopted in the wake of Kant's 'Copernican Revolution'? The Critique stood as (...) the lighting rod at the center of a complicated and especially lively set of debates and disputes that erupted in Germany in the late 1780s and early 1790s: empiricists and rationalists, threatened by the 'all-destroying Kant', leapt to challenge the new critical system; skeptics attacked Kant's claims to have secured a sure footing for empirical knowledge; a few ambitious thinkers sought to complete the critical system by revealing a foundational first principle on which Kant's system could rest. All of these elements conspired to make the early stages inpost-Kantian thought one of the richest, most vibrant – and most fascinating – periods in the history of philosophy. The present essay looks at the various figures of the move from Kant to Fichte, and presents some of the excellent new research on the era that has appeared in the last decade or so. The sequel takes up the period from Fichte to Hegel, with an eye toward understanding howKantian critical philosophy gave way to Hegelian Absolute Idealism. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  45
    Scientific realism in thepost-Kuhnian times.Tian Yu Cao -2018 - In Shyam Wuppuluri & Francisco Antonio Doria,The Map and the Territory: Exploring the Foundations of Science, Thought and Reality. Cham: Springer. pp. 101-123.
    Motivated by the developments in contemporary mathematical physics and the related interpretive and historiographical works on these developments, a structuralist and historically constitutive and constructive approach to scientific realism (SHASR) is proposed to address the challenges Thomas Kuhn raised against scientific realism, and to remove the defects of the currently available dissatisfactory responses the structuralists put forward to the challenges. The paper shows that SHASR productively exploits the insights from both Kuhn’s historicism and his critics’ structuralism, while avoids the traps (...) in both traditions. Then, after a brief comparison between SHASR and the increasingly popular neo-Kantianpost-Kuhnian philosophy of science recommended and defended by Michael Freedman and some others, it concludes with a big picture about the science-world relationship derived from the notion of emergence conceptualized within the framework of SHASR, whose bearings on theKantian question of the phenomenal - noumenal relationship are worth further explorations. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  11
    Hidden Resources: Classical Perspectives on Subjectivity.Dan Zahavi (ed.) -2004 - Imprint Academic.
    Dan Zahavi, the editor of this collection, heads the Center for Subjectivity Research, at the University of Copenhagen. The essays reflect the interests of the Center and seek to address the following issue: To what extent can the current discussion of consciousness in mainstream cognitive science and analytical philosophy of mind profit from insights drawn from the investigations of subjectivity found in theKantian andpost-Kantiantradition as well as in the phenomenological and hermeneuticaltradition. (...) The contributions include some that are philosophical, while others relate to issues in empirical science, such as psychopathology, cognitive neuroscience, and developmental psychology.Contributors include Andrew Brook, John Drummond, Shaun Gallagher, Arne Groen, Josef Parnas, Peter Poellner, Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl, Louis Sass, Dieter Teichert and Dan Zahavi. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  62
    Minding the Gap: Epistemology & Philosophy of Science in the Two Traditions.Christopher Norris -2000 - Univ of Massachusetts Press.
    In this sweeping volume, Christopher Norris challenges the view that there is no room for productive engagement between mainstream analytic philosophers and thinkers in thepost-Kantian continental line of descent. On the contrary, he argues, this view is simply the product of a limiting perspective that accompanied the rise of logical positivism. Norris reveals the various shared concerns that have often been obscured by parochial interests or the desire to stake out separate philosophical territory. He examines the problems (...) that emerged within the analytictradition as a result of its turn against Husserlian phenomenology and its outright rejection of what came to be seen as a merely "psychologistic" approach to issues of meaning, knowledge, and truth. Norris shows how these problems have resurfaced in various forms from the heyday of logical empiricism to the present. He provides critical readings of such philosophers as Willard Quine, Thomas Kuhn, Donald Davidson, Hilary Putnam, Richard Rorty, Michael Dummett, Thomas Nagel, and John McDowell. He also offers a running discussion of Wittgenstein's influence and its harmful effect in promoting a placidly consensus-based theory of knowledge. On the continental side, Norris argues for a reassessment of Husserl's phenomenological project and its potential contribution to present-day Anglo-American debates in epistemology and philosophy of science. He discusses Bachelard, Canguilhem, and the Frenchtradition of rationalisme applique as an alternative to Kuhnian conceptions of scientific paradigm change. This leads him to suggest a non-Wittgensteinian way around the problems that have dogged more traditional theories of knowledge andtruth. In two chapters on the work of Jacques Derrida, Norris explores the "supplementary" logic of deconstruction and compares it with other recent proposals for a nonstandard logic. Here again he stresses the community of interests between the two philosophical cultures and the extent to which continental thinking has engaged certain issues with a rigor largely ignored by Anglophone writers. By bringing a fresh perspective to questions that have often been considered the exclusive preserve of analytic philosophy, Norris offers an overview of current debates that is at once refreshingly open-minded and sure of its own argumentative bearings. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  37.  417
    Dialectics of difference and negation: the responses of Deleuze and Hegel to representation.Henry Somers-Hall -2008 - Dissertation, University of Warwick
    This thesis has the following aims. First, to show that Deleuze can be situated clearly within thepost-Kantiantradition. This is achieved through an analysis of the relations between Kant's transcendental idealism and Deleuze's transcendental empiricism. Second, to explore the criticisms of representational theories of difference which can be found in the work of Deleuze and Hegel. Representational theories are best understood as theories which rely on a logic which is governed by relations between entities which pre-exist (...) those relations. Deleuze argues that these logics presuppose the formal equivalent of a homogeneous space within which these relations can be construed. Hegel similarly understands representation as the utilisation of finite categories which rely on the fixity of the subject of predication. The third aim is to provide a rigorous explication of some of the key themes of Deleuzian ontology, particularly in relation to the problem of representation. This will involve looking at the logic of multiplicities, which attempts to provide a theory of difference that is non-oppositional. This logic will be clarified through a discussion of Deleuze's use of modern geometry, and his analysis of the foundations of the calculus. The fourth aim will be to contrast Deleuze's solution with that of Hegel, particularly with respect to their relationships to Kant and the calculus. This is achieved through the Deleuzian distinction between finite and infinite representation, the latter in Deleuze's view characterising the Hegelian attempt to bring the idea of transition into representation itself. Finally, having shown where Deleuze and Hegel differ in their respective projects, the thesis will explore whether either of these philosophies has the resources to provide a refutation of the other with reference to the dialectic of force and the understanding in the henomenology of Spirit, and the problem of the one and the many. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  57
    Post-Gödelian Ontological Argumentation for God’s Existence.Joshua R. Brotherton -2018 -International Philosophical Quarterly 58 (4):371-387.
    The so-called ontological argument has a complex and controverted history, rising to particular prominence in contemporary analytic philosophy. Against this backdrop I will present a non-analytic interpretation of ontological argumentation for God’s existence by attempting to fuse Anselmian and Gödelian perspectives. I defend ontological argumentation in a number of slightly variant forms as neither a priori nor a posteriori, but ab actu exercito.Kantian and especially Thomistic critiques are confronted in the course of explaining how ontological argumentation may be (...) logically valid without depending on or yielding to subjectivist epistemologies. Hence,post-Gödelian ontological argumentation ought to be acceptable to realists. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  37
    Idealism after existentialism: encounters in philosophy of religion.Nick Trakakis -2023 - New York, NY: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group.
    A century ago the dominant philosophical outlook was not some form of materialism or naturalism, but idealism. However, this way of thinking about reality fell out of favour in the Anglo-American analytictradition as well as the Continental schools of the twentieth century. The aim of this book is to restage and reassess the encounter between idealism and contemporary philosophy. The idealist side will be represented by the great figures of the 19th-centurypost-Kantiantradition in Germany, (...) from Fichte and Schelling to Hegel, followed by the towering Hegelians in Britain led by T.H. Green, F.H. Bradley and Bernard Bosanquet. Their 20th-century adversaries will be represented by the secular existentialists, especially the famous French trio of Sartre, Beauvoir and Camus, who sought to follow Nietzsche in philosophizing in light of the death of God. And the arena of encounter will be the philosophy of religion-more specifically, questions relating to the nature and existence of God, death and the meaning of life, and the problem of evil. The book argues that the existentialist critique of idealism enables an innovative as well as a more critical and adventurous approach that is sorely needed in philosophy of religion today. Idealism after Existentialism will be of interest to scholars and advanced students working in the history of 19th- and 20th-century philosophy and philosophy of religion. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  57
    Liberal naturalism, objectivity and the autonomy of the mental.David Zapero -2019 -Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 62 (5):546-564.
    ABSTRACTThe paper distinguishes between two different ways of cashing out the general insight that often goes by the name of ‘liberal naturalism’. The objective is to show how these two different argumentative strategies undergird two fundamentally different approaches to the project of elucidating the specificity of mental phenomena. On one approach, the central concern of such a project is the ontological status of subjective conscious phenomena; on the other, the central concern is the irreducibility of parochial capacities in the adoption (...) of intentional stances. I begin by tracing out some of the origins of this important divergence and then focus on the motivations of the latter approach. I show that there is a tension between its motivations and the way that it has been used to rehabilitate idealist themes from thepost-Kantiantradition. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  123
    Immanence and Method Bergson's Early Reading of Spinoza.Russell Ford -2004 -Southern Journal of Philosophy 42 (2):171-192.
    With the publication of the notes from Bergson’s early courses it has become possible to investigate thetradition of thinking that Bergson understood himself to be working within. A historical investigation of this understanding is valuable for at least two reasons: first, it allows us to appreciate the decisive interventions that Bergson’s thought makes within thepost-Kantiantradition. Part of Bergson’s popularity was due to his insistence upon ‘beginning anew’ in thinking. However, while there is certainly (...) much that is new in Bergson’s thought, to emphasize this element of novelty at the price of occluding Bergson’s scholarly work on the history of philosophy is to simultaneously deprive Bergson’s own philosophy of the depth and relevance that it gathers through its resonance with other great thinkers and, inversely, to fail to understand the critical force of Bergson’s intellectual creativity. In addition to being valuable as an elaboration of the stakes in a particular moment of the history of philosophy, a historical investigation of Bergson’s reading of Spinoza affords us the opportunity to work out and think through the motivating questions that animate Bergson’s own thought and which become visible in the way that he takes up other philosophical concepts and systems. Clearly, such a historical investigation is unconcerned with the question of whether or not Bergson “understood” Spinoza, or “got him right.” That Kierkegaard “misunderstood” Hegel is hardly a profound or even philosophically interesting statement. However, it becomes constructive when it drives us to ask, for instance, how it is that Kierkegaard misunderstands Hegel. What concerns motivate Kierkegaard to reject Hegel’s system? What are the points of disagreement and, perhaps most importantly, what new concepts, what new directions of thought, do these points allow Kierkegaard to create? This point can be generalized as follows: the historical investigation of a philosopher’s engagement with the philosophicaltradition is productive (i.e. creative rather than reductive) when this engagement is taken up and interpreted as indicative of the new and distinctive concerns that drive the more recent philosopher’s thought – a thought whose distinction at the same time marks the distinctiveness of his or her historical interlocutor. As Deleuze writes of the concept of the subject, “it is never very interesting to criticize a concept: it is better to build the new functions and discover the new fields that make it useless or inadequate.” By extension, an “interesting” reading of Bergson’s interpretation of Spinoza ought not to emphasize the points of agreement and disagreement between them – as though it could be taken for granted that they have the same or equivalent concerns – but would inquire into the direction of Bergson’s thought that makes Spinoza simultaneously one of his closest philosophical allies and, at the same time, a thinker from whom Bergson repeatedly distances himself and critiques in order to elucidate his own thinking. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  38
    Pierre Klossowski’s Hamann.Tom Giesbers -2017 -Idealistic Studies 47 (1-2):141-154.
    This paper elucidates Pierre Klossowski’s relationship to thepost-Kantiantradition, specifically as a part of the shift in twentieth-century French philosophy from a neo-Kantian epistemological approach to the emphasis on the primacy of language in the human subject and his place in society. In response to a variety of events (the reception of Hegelianism through the lenses of Kojève and Wahl, the Marxist critique of capitalism and the rise of European fascism) Klossowski develops a peculiar interest (...) in the works of Johann Georg Hamann, who can be considered to be either the firstpost-Kantian or the direct antecedent ofpost-Kantianism (given the fact that he influenced both Kant and manypost-Kantians). As this paper argues, Klossowski published a collection of texts by Hamann as a direct response to the philosophical deadlock between conceptuality and immediate life that the French reception of Hegel emphasized. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  44
    La réflexion de Poincaré sur l’espace, dans l’histoire de la géométrie.Alain Michel -2004 -Philosophiques 31 (1):89-114.
    Les conceptions de Poincaré en matière de physique mathématique demandent à être mises en relation avec son travail mathématique. Ce qu’on a appelé son « conventionnalisme géométrique » est étroitement lié à ses premiers travaux mathématiques et à son intérêt pour la géométrie de Plücker et la théorie des groupes continus de Lie. Sa conception profonde de l’espace et son insertion dans un environnementpost-kantien concourent à composer les traits d’une doctrine dont on a souvent sous-estimé l’originalité, dans ses (...) différences avec celle de Riemann.It is necessary to link the philosophical conceptions of Poincaré to his mathematical work. What has been named his « geometrical conventionalism » is closely tied to his first mathematical works and to his interest in Plücker’s geometry and in the theory of continuous groups of Lie. His profound conception of space and the immersion in thepost-Kantiantradition are the specific features of a doctrine greatly original, different in many respects from the Riemannian doctrine. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  39
    Hegel, Deleuze, and the Critique of Representation: Dialectics of Negation and Difference.Henry Somers-Hall -2012 - State University of New York Press.
    A critical account of the key connections between twentieth-century French philosopher Gilles Deleuze and nineteenth-century German idealist G. W. F. Hegel. Hegel, Deleuze, and the Critique of Representation provides a critical account of the key connections between twentieth-century French philosopher Gilles Deleuze and nineteenth-century German idealist G. W. F. Hegel. While Hegel has been recognized as one of the key targets of Deleuze’s philosophical writing, Henry Somers-Hall shows how Deleuze’s antipathy to Hegel has its roots in a problem the two (...) thinkers both try to address: getting beyond a philosophy of judgment and the restrictions of Kant’s transcendental idealism. By tracing the development of their attempts to address this problem, Somers-Hall offers an interpretation of the sweep of nineteenth- and twentieth-century philosophy, providing a series of analyses of key moments in the history of thought, including the logics of Aristotle and Russell, Kant’s own philosophy of judgment, and the philosophy of Bergson. He also develops a novel interpretation of Deleuze’s philosophy of difference, and situates his philosophy in relation to the broaderpost-Kantiantradition. In addition to Deleuze’s relation to Hegel, the book makes important contributions to the study of Deleuze’s philosophy of mathematics, as well as to the study of several underappreciated areas of Hegel’s own philosophy. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  45.  26
    The Palgrave Fichte Handbook.Steven Hoeltzel (ed.) -2019 - Palgrave Macmillan.
    This Handbook provides a comprehensive single-volume treatment of Fichte’s philosophy. In addition to offering new researchers an authoritative introduction and orientation to Fichtean thought, the volume also surveys the main scholarly and philosophical controversies regarding Fichtean interpretation, and defends a range of philosophical theses in a way that advances the scholarly discussion. Fichte is the first major philosopher in thepost-Kantiantradition and the first of the great German Idealists, but he was no mere epigone of Kant (...) or precursor to Hegel. His work speaks powerfully and originally to a wide range of issues of enduring concern, and his many innovations importantly anticipate major developments, including absolute idealism, phenomenology, and existentialism. He is therefore not only a path-breaking thinker but also a pivotal figure in Western intellectual history. Wide-ranging, well-organised and timely, this key volume makes Fichte’s work both accessible and relevant. It is essential reading for scholars, graduate researchers and advanced students interested in Fichte, German Idealism, and the history of nineteenth-century philosophy in the West. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  71
    Kant and the ContinentalTradition: Sensibility, Nature, and Religion.Sorin Baiasu &Alberto Vanzo (eds.) -2020 - New York: Routledge.
    Immanuel Kant's work continues to be a main focus of attention in almost all areas of philosophy. The significance of Kant's work for the so-called continental philosophy cannot be exaggerated, although work in this area is relatively scant. The book includes eight chapters, a substantial introduction and a postscript, all newly written by an international cast of well-known authors. Each chapter focuses on particular aspects of a fundamental problem in Kant's andpost-Kantian philosophy, the problem of the relation (...) between the world and transcendence. Chapters fall thematically into three parts: sensibility, nature and religion. Each part starts with a more interpretative chapter focusing on Kant's relevant work, and continues with comparative chapters which stage dialogues between Kant andpost-Kantian philosophers, including Martin Heidegger, Hannah Arendt, Jean-François Lyotard, Luce Irigaray and Jacques Derrida. A special feature of this volume is the engagement of each chapter with the work of the late British philosopher Gary Banham. The Postscript offers a subtle and erudite analysis of his intellectual trajectory, philosophy and mode of working. The volume is dedicated to his memory. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  98
    Fichte’s critique of physicalism – towards an idealist alternative.Plato Tse -2019 -Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 62 (5):527-545.
    ABSTRACTThough the perennial problem of consciousness has outlasted the idealists, the reductivist turn in contemporary naturalistic philosophy of mind and the non-reductivist reactions to it provoke us to re-thinkpost-Kantian idealism. Fichte's Wissenschaftslehre makes for a classical case of non-reductivist approach to mind and his critique of ‘dogmatism’ is all the more relevant in this context. This article contains four sections. The first section is an introduction that explains whypost-Kantian idealism is relevant to contemporary philosophy (...) of mind. The second section pinpoints the placement issue that confronts not only current philosophers but also partially motivated Fichte's own philosophy. The third section is a short but essential remark about the normative and practical valence of ‘knowledge’ and ‘science’ in Fichte's traditional understanding of them. In the fourth section, I provide a reconstructive analysis of Fichte's understanding and critique of physicalism. Fichte's argument can be analyzed into two horns with each targeting reductivism and epiphenomenalism respectively. The final section is a brief but positive exposition on a necessary feature, namely reflexivity, of mind and the first-person perspective. Fichte's appropriation of intellectual intuition exemplifies a non-representationalist picture that connects content transparency with the active nature of mind. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  35
    How and why to express the emotions: A taxonomy of emotional expression with historical illustrations.Christopher Bennett -2021 -Metaphilosophy 52 (5):513-529.
    Recent writing on the expression of emotion has explored the idea that there is a symbolic dimension to many “expressive actions.” This paper aims to situate and better understand the “symbolic expression” account by exploring its position in a framework of views from the history of philosophy regarding emotion, action out of emotion, and their place in the good human life. The paper discusses a number of competing views that can be found in thistradition, ranging from irrationalism, through (...) irenicism, self‐externalization, and cognitivism to the symbolisttradition itself. In looking specifically at the roots of symbolism, the paper departs from the common view that Aristotelianism is the centraltradition, for us, of thinking about philosophy of the emotions. It suggests that we can get a better grip on the source of these ideas by looking rather at how thinkers in thepostKantian and Romantictradition wrestled with the question of the freedom and rationality of behaviour out of emotion. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  36
    Immanence and the Vertigo of Philosophy: From Kant to Deleuze.Christian Kerslake -2009 - Edinburgh University Press.
    One of the terminological constants in the philosophical work of Gilles Deleuze is the word 'immanence', and it has therefore become a foothold for those wishing to understand exactly what 'Deleuzian philosophy' is. Deleuze's philosophy of immanence is held to be fundamentally characterised by its opposition to all philosophies of 'transcendence'. On that basis, it is widely believed that Deleuze's project is premised on a return to a materialist metaphysics. Christian Kerslake argues that such an interpretation is fundamentally misconceived, and (...) has led to misunderstandings of Deleuze's philosophy, which is rather one of the latest heirs to thepost-Kantiantradition of thought about immanence. This will be the first book to assess Deleuze's relationship toKantian epistemology andpost-Kantian philosophy, and will attempt to make Deleuze's philosophy intelligible to students working within thattradition. But it also attempts to reconstruct our image of thepost-Kantiantradition, isolating a lineage that takes shape in the work of Schelling and Wronski, and which is developed in the twentieth century by Bergson, Warrain and Deleuze. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  50.  524
    (1 other version)From Kant to Schelling to Process Metaphysics: On The Way to Ecological Civilization.Arran Gare -2011 -Cosmos and History 7 (2):26-69.
    Thepost-Kantians were inspired by Kant’s Critique of Judgment to forge a new synthesis of natural philosophy, art and history that would overcome the dualisms and gulfs within Kant’s philosophy. Focusing on biology and showing how Schelling reworked and transformed Kant’s insights, it is argued that Schelling was largely successful in laying the foundations for this synthesis, although he was not always consistent in building on these foundations. To appreciate this achievement, it is argued that Schelling should not be (...) interpreted as an idealist but as a process metaphysician; as he claimed, overcoming the oppositions between idealism and realism, spiritualism and materialism. It is also argued that as a process metaphysician, Schelling not merely defended an organic view of nature but developed a theory of emergence and a new conception of life relevant to current theoretical and philosophical biology. This interpretation provides a defense of process metaphysics as the logical successor to Kant’s critical philosophy and thereby as the most defensibletradition of philosophy up to the present. It provides the foundations forpost-reductionist science, reconciling the sciences, the arts and the humanities, and provides the basis for a more satisfactory ethics and political philosophy. Most importantly, it overcomes the nihilism of European civilization, providing the foundations for a global ecological civilization. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
1 — 50 / 943
Export
Limit to items.
Filters





Configure languageshere.Sign in to use this feature.

Viewing options


Open Category Editor
Off-campus access
Using PhilPapers from home?

Create an account to enable off-campus access through your institution's proxy server or OpenAthens.


[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp