Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs
Switch to: Citations

References in:

Epistemic Modals in Context

, &
In Gerhard Preyer & Georg Peter,Contextualism in philosophy: knowledge, meaning, and truth. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 131-168 (2005)

Add references

You mustlogin to add references.
  1. Knowledge and lotteries.John Hawthorne -2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Knowledge and Lotteries is organized around an epistemological puzzle: in many cases, we seem consistently inclined to deny that we know a certain class of propositions, while crediting ourselves with knowledge of propositions that imply them. In its starkest form, the puzzle is this: we do not think we know that a given lottery ticket will be a loser, yet we normally count ourselves as knowing all sorts of ordinary things that entail that its holder will not suddenly acquire a (...) large fortune. After providing a number of specific and general characterizations of the puzzle, Hawthorne carefully examines the competing merits of candidate solutions. In so doing, he explores a number of central questions concerning the nature and importance of knowledge, including the relationship of knowledge to assertion and practical reasoning, the status of epistemic closure principles, the merits of various brands of scepticism, the prospects for a contextualist account of knowledge, and the potential for other sorts of salience-sensitive accounts. Along the way, he offers a careful treatment of pertinent issues at the foundations of semantics. His book will be of interest to anyone working in the field of epistemology, as well as to philosophers of language. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   981 citations  
  • A Natural History of Negation.Laurence R. Horn -1989 - University of Chicago Press.
    This book offers a unique synthesis of past and current work on the structure, meaning, and use of negation and negative expressions, a topic that has engaged thinkers from Aristotle and the Buddha to Freud and Chomsky. Horn's masterful study melds a review of scholarship in philosophy, psychology, and linguistics with original research, providing a full picture of negation in natural language and thought; this new edition adds a comprehensive preface and bibliography, surveying research since the book's original publication.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   389 citations  
  • (1 other version)Assertion.Robert Stalnaker -2013 - In Maite Ezcurdia & Robert J. Stainton,The Semantics-Pragmatics Boundary in Philosophy. Peterborough, CA: Broadview Press. pp. 179.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   627 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The Paradoxes of Time Travel.David Lewis -1976 -American Philosophical Quarterly 13 (2):145-152.
  • Knowledge and Lotteries.John Hawthorne -2005 -Philosophical Quarterly 55 (219):353-356.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   963 citations  
  • (1 other version)Assertion.Robert Stalnaker -1978 -Syntax and Semantics (New York Academic Press) 9:315-332.
  • On Quantifier Domain Restriction.Jason Stanley &Zoltán Gendler Szabó -2000 -Mind and Language 15 (2-3):219--61.
    In this paper, we provide a comprehensive survey of the space of possible analyses of the phenomenon of quantifier domain restriction, together with a set of considerations which militate against all but our own proposal. Among the many accounts we consider and reject are the ‘explicit’ approach to quantifier domain restric‐tion discussed, for example, by Stephen Neale, and the pragmatic approach to quantifier domain restriction proposed by Kent Bach. Our hope is that the exhaustive discussion of this special case of (...) context‐dependence will provide guidelines for how to decide, for an arbitrary case of context‐dependent discourse, whether it should be treated syntactically, semantically, or pragmatically. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   424 citations  
  • (1 other version)Direct Reference, Propositional Attitudes, and Semantic Content.Scott Soames -1987 -Philosophical Topics 15 (1):47-87.
  • (1 other version)Context and logical form.Jason Stanley -2000 -Linguistics and Philosophy 23 (4):391--434.
    In this paper, I defend the thesis that alleffects of extra-linguistic context on thetruth-conditions of an assertion are traceable toelements in the actual syntactic structure of thesentence uttered. In the first section, I develop thethesis in detail, and discuss its implications for therelation between semantics and pragmatics. The nexttwo sections are devoted to apparent counterexamples.In the second section, I argue that there are noconvincing examples of true non-sentential assertions.In the third section, I argue that there are noconvincing examples of what (...) John Perry has called`unarticulated constituents''. I conclude by drawingsome consequences of my arguments for appeals tocontext-dependence in the resolution of problems inepistemology and philosophical logic. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   359 citations  
  • Future contingents and relative truth.John MacFarlane -2003 -Philosophical Quarterly 53 (212):321–336.
    If it is not now determined whether there will be a sea battle tomorrow, can an assertion that there will be one be true? The problem has persisted because there are compelling arguments on both sides. If there are objectively possible futures which would make the prediction true and others which would make it false, symmetry considerations seem to forbid counting it either true or false. Yet if we think about how we would assess the prediction tomorrow, when a sea (...) battle is raging (or not), it seems we must assign the utterance a definite truth-value. I argue that both arguments must be given their due, and that this requires relativizing utterance-truth to a context of assessment. I show how this relativization can be handled in a rigorous formal semantics, and I argue that we can make coherent sense of assertion without assuming that utterances have their truth-values absolutely. (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   308 citations  
  • (1 other version)Context and Logical Form.Jason Stanley -2013 - In Maite Ezcurdia & Robert J. Stainton,The Semantics-Pragmatics Boundary in Philosophy. Peterborough, CA: Broadview Press. pp. 316.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   225 citations  
  • A Natural History of Negation.Laurence R. Horn -1989 -Philosophy and Rhetoric 24 (2):164-168.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   351 citations  
  • Epistemic possibilities.Keith DeRose -1991 -Philosophical Review 100 (4):581-605.
  • (2 other versions)The Paradoxes of Time Travel.David Lewis -2004 - In Tim Crane & Katalin Farkas,Metaphysics: a guide and anthology. New York: Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   227 citations  
  • (1 other version)Direct reference, propositional attitudes, and semantic content.Scott Soames -2009 - InPhilosophical Essays, Volume 2: The Philosophical Significance of Language. Princeton University Press. pp. 33-71.
  • Towards a variable-free semantics.Pauline Jacobson -1999 -Linguistics and Philosophy 22 (2):117-185.
    The Montagovian hypothesis of direct model-theoretic interpretation of syntactic surface structures is supported by an account of the semantics of binding that makes no use of variables, syntactic indices, or assignment functions & shows that the interpretation of a large portion of so-called variable-binding phenomena can dispense with the level of logical form without incurring equivalent complexity elsewhere in the system. Variable-free semantics hypothesizes local interpretation of each surface constituent; binding is formalized as a type-shifting operation on expressions that denote (...) functions, & sentences containing a free pronoun are analyzed as a function from individuals to propositions having a meaning of type (e,t). Standard weak crossover effects & binding patterns in sentences with multiple pronouns are shown to submit to straightforward type-theoretic treatments that do not rely on indexation. The variable-free semantics smoothly implements full surface compositionality & requires less machinery than standard accounts to handle functional questions, their answers, sloppy inferences, & across-the-board binding. 73 References. J. Hitchcock. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • Compositionality and context.Peter Pagin -2005 - In Gerhard Preyer & Georg Peter,Contextualism in philosophy: knowledge, meaning, and truth. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 303-348.
    This paper contains a discussion of how the concept of compositionality is to be extended from context invariant to context dependent meaning, and of how the compositionality of natural language might conflict with context dependence. Several new distinctions are needed, including a distinction between a weaker (e-) and a stronger (ec-) concept of compositionality for context dependent meaning. The relations between the various notions are investigated. A claim by Jerry Fodor that there is a general conflict between context dependence and (...) compositionality is considered. There is in fact a possible conflict betwee ec-compositionality and context dependence, but not of the kind Fodor suggests. It turns on the presence of so-called unarticulated constituents, in John Perry’s sense. Because of this phenomenon, on some semantic accounts there might be a variation in the meaning of a complex expression between contexts without any corresponding variation in any of the syntactic parts of that complex. The conflict can be resolved in several ways. One way is to make the unarticulated context dependence explicit only in the meta-language, which makes it into an unarticulated constituent account. A recent argument by Jason Stanley against such accounts is discussed. According to Stanley, certain readings of English sentences involving binding of contextual variables, are unavailable in these theories. After considering a reply to Stanley by François Recanati, I present an outline of a fully compositional theory, of the unarticulated constituent variety, which does deliver these readings. Concluding remarks on, inter alia, the semantics/pragmatics distinction. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Second-Order Predication and the Metaphysics of Properties.Andy Egan -2004 -Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (1):48-66.
    Problems about the accidental properties of properties motivate us--force us, I think--not to identify properties with the sets of their instances. If we identify them instead with functions from worlds to extensions, we get a theory of properties that is neutral with respect to disputes over counterpart theory, and we avoid a problem for Lewis's theory of events. Similar problems about the temporary properties of properties motivate us--though this time they probably don't force us--to give up this theory as well, (...) and to identify properties with functions from world, time pairs to extensions. Again, the replacement theory is neutral with respect to a metaphysical dispute that the old theory (arguably) forces us to take a stand on--the dispute over whether objects have temporal parts. It also allows us to give a smoother semantics for predication, to better accommodate our intuitions about which objects temporary properties are properties of, and to make temporally self-locating beliefs genuinely self -locating. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Epistemic Containment.Kai von Fintel &Sabine Iatridou -2003 -Linguistic Inquiry 34:173-98.
    This article concerns a new constraint on the interaction of quantifier phrases and epistemic modals. It is argued that QPs cannot bind their traces across an epistemic modal, though it is shown that scoping mechanisms of a differentnature are permitted to cross epistemic modals. The nature and source of this constraint are investigated.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Can Propositions Be Naturalistically Acceptable?Jeffrey C. King -1994 -Midwest Studies in Philosophy 19 (1):53-75.

  • [8]ページ先頭

    ©2009-2025 Movatter.jp