Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs
Switch to: References

Add citations

You mustlogin to add citations.
  1. One, two, three, four, nothing more: An investigation of the conceptual sources of the verbal counting principles.Mathieu Le Corre &Susan Carey -2007 -Cognition 105 (2):395-438.
  • Mathematical symbols as epistemic actions.Johan De Smedt &Helen De Cruz -2013 -Synthese 190 (1):3-19.
    Recent experimental evidence from developmental psychology and cognitive neuroscience indicates that humans are equipped with unlearned elementary mathematical skills. However, formal mathematics has properties that cannot be reduced to these elementary cognitive capacities. The question then arises how human beings cognitively deal with more advanced mathematical ideas. This paper draws on the extended mind thesis to suggest that mathematical symbols enable us to delegate some mathematical operations to the external environment. In this view, mathematical symbols are not only used to (...) express mathematical concepts—they are constitutive of the mathematical concepts themselves. Mathematical symbols are epistemic actions, because they enable us to represent concepts that are literally unthinkable with our bare brains. Using case-studies from the history of mathematics and from educational psychology, we argue for an intimate relationship between mathematical symbols and mathematical cognition. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • The role of language in acquiring object kind concepts in infancy.Fei Xu -2002 -Cognition 85 (3):223-250.
  • Numerals and neural reuse.Max Jones -2020 -Synthese 197 (9):3657-3681.
    Menary OpenMIND, MIND Group, Frankfurt am Main, 2015) has argued that the development of our capacities for mathematical cognition can be explained in terms of enculturation. Our ancient systems for perceptually estimating numerical quantities are augmented and transformed by interacting with a culturally-enriched environment that provides scaffolds for the acquisition of cognitive practices, leading to the development of a discrete number system for representing number precisely. Numerals and the practices associated with numeral systems play a significant role in this process. (...) However, the details of the relationship between the ancient number system and the discrete number system remain unclear. This lack of clarity is exacerbated by the problem of symbolic estrangement and the fact that unique features of how numeral systems represent require our ancient number system to play a dual role. These issues highlight that Dehaene’s From monkey brain to human brain, MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 133–157, 2005) neuronal recycling hypothesis may be insufficient to explain the neural mechanisms underlying the process of enculturation. In order to explain mathematical enculturation, and enculturation more generally, it may be necessary to adopt Anderson’s :245–266, 2010; After phrenology: neural reuse and the interactive brain, MIT Press, Cambridge, 2014) theory of neural reuse. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Compositionality and constituent structure in the analogue mind.Sam Clarke -2023 -Philosophical Perspectives 37 (1):90-118.
    I argue that analogue mental representations possess a canonical decomposition into privileged constituents from which they compose. I motivate this suggestion, and rebut arguments to the contrary, through reflection on the approximate number system, whose representations are widely expected to have an analogue format. I then argue that arguments for the compositionality and constituent structure of these analogue representations generalize to other analogue mental representations posited in the human mind, such as those in early vision and visual imagery.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Making sense of domain specificity.Eric Margolis &Stephen Laurence -2023 -Cognition 240 (C):105583.
    The notion of domain specificity plays a central role in some of the most important debates in cognitive science. Yet, despite the widespread reliance on domain specificity in recent theorizing in cognitive science, this notion remains elusive. Critics have claimed that the notion of domain specificity can't bear the theoretical weight that has been put on it and that it should be abandoned. Even its most steadfast proponents have highlighted puzzles and tensions that arise once one tries to go beyond (...) an initial intuitive sketch of what domain specificity involves. In this paper, we address these concerns head on by developing an account of what it means for a cognitive mechanism to be domain specific that overcomes the obstacles that have made domain specificity seem so problematic. We then apply this understanding of domain specificity to one of the key debates that it has figured prominently in—the rationalism-empiricism debate concerning the origins of cognitive traits—and introduce several related theoretical notions that work alongside domain specificity in helping to clarify what makes a view more (or less) rationalist. This example illustrates how the notion of domain specificity can, and should, continue to play a central role in ongoing debates in cognitive science. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Calibrating the mental number line.Véronique Izard &Stanislas Dehaene -2008 -Cognition 106 (3):1221-1247.
    Human adults are thought to possess two dissociable systems to represent numbers: an approximate quantity system akin to a mental number line, and a verbal system capable of representing numbers exactly. Here, we study the interface between these two systems using an estimation task. Observers were asked to estimate the approximate numerosity of dot arrays. We show that, in the absence of calibration, estimates are largely inaccurate: responses increase monotonically with numerosity, but underestimate the actual numerosity. However, insertion of a (...) few inducer trials, in which participants are explicitly (and sometimes misleadingly) told that a given display contains 30 dots, is sufficient to calibrate their estimates on the whole range of stimuli. Based on these empirical results, we develop a model of the mapping between the numerical symbols and the representations of numerosity on the number line. (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • From numerical concepts to concepts of number.Lance J. Rips,Amber Bloomfield &Jennifer Asmuth -2008 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (6):623-642.
    Many experiments with infants suggest that they possess quantitative abilities, and many experimentalists believe that these abilities set the stage for later mathematics: natural numbers and arithmetic. However, the connection between these early and later skills is far from obvious. We evaluate two possible routes to mathematics and argue that neither is sufficient: (1) We first sketch what we think is the most likely model for infant abilities in this domain, and we examine proposals for extrapolating the natural number concept (...) from these beginnings. Proposals for arriving at natural number by (empirical) induction presuppose the mathematical concepts they seek to explain. Moreover, standard experimental tests for children's understanding of number terms do not necessarily tap these concepts. (2) True concepts of number do appear, however, when children are able to understand generalizations over all numbers; for example, the principle of additive commutativity (a+b=b+a). Theories of how children learn such principles usually rely on a process of mapping from physical object groupings. But both experimental results and theoretical considerations imply that direct mapping is insufficient for acquiring these principles. We suggest instead that children may arrive at natural numbers and arithmetic in a more top-down way, by constructing mathematical schemas. (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Six does not just mean a lot: preschoolers see number words as specific.B. Sarnecka -2004 -Cognition 92 (3):329-352.
  • Improving arithmetic performance with number sense training: An investigation of underlying mechanism.Joonkoo Park &Elizabeth M. Brannon -2014 -Cognition 133 (1):188-200.
  • Number and natural language.Stephen Laurence &Eric Margolis -2005 - In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Laurence & Stephen P. Stich,The Innate Mind: Structure and Contents. New York, US: Oxford University Press on Demand. pp. 1--216.
    One of the most important abilities we have as humans is the ability to think about number. In this chapter, we examine the question of whether there is an essential connection between language and number. We provide a careful examination of two prominent theories according to which concepts of the positive integers are dependent on language. The first of these claims that language creates the positive integers on the basis of an innate capacity to represent real numbers. The second claims (...) that language’s function is to integrate contents from modules that humans share with other animals. We argue that neither model is successful. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Thinking through language.Paul Bloom &Frank C. Keil -2001 -Mind and Language 16 (4):351–367.
    What would it be like to have never learned English, but instead only to know Hopi, Mandarin Chinese, or American Sign Language? Would that change the way you think? Imagine entirely losing your language, as the result of stroke or trauma. You are aphasic, unable to speak or listen, read or write. What would your thoughts now be like? As the most extreme case, imagine having been raised without any language at all, as a wild child. What—if anything—would it be (...) like to be such a person? Could you be smart; could you reminisce about the past, plan the future? (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Number nativism.Sam Clarke -2025 -Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 110 (1):226-252.
    Number Nativism is the view that humans innately represent precise natural numbers. Despite a long and venerable history, it is often considered hopelessly out of touch with the empirical record. I argue that this is a mistake. After clarifying Number Nativism and distancing it from related conjectures, I distinguish three arguments which have been seen to refute the view. I argue that, while popular, two of these arguments miss the mark, and fail to place pressure on Number Nativism. Meanwhile, a (...) third argument is best construed as a challenge: rather than refuting Number Nativism, it challenges its proponents to provide positive evidence for their thesis and show that this can be squared with apparent counterevidence. In response, I introduce psycholinguistic work on The Tolerance Principle (not yet considered in this context), propose that it is hard to make sense of without positing precise and innate representations of natural numbers, and argue that there is no obvious reason why these innate representations couldn’t serve as a basis for mature numeric conception. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The semantics and acquisition of number words: integrating linguistic and developmental perspectives.Julien Musolino -2004 -Cognition 93 (1):1-41.
    This article brings together two independent lines of research on numerally quantified expressions, e.g. two girls. One stems from work in linguistic theory and asks what truth conditional contributions such expressions make to the utterances in which they are used--in other words, what do numerals mean? The other comes from the study of language development and asks when and how children learn the meaning of such expressions. My goal is to show that when integrated, these two perspectives can both constrain (...) and enrich each other in ways hitherto not considered. Specifically, work in linguistic theory suggests that in addition to their 'exactly n' interpretation, numerally quantified NPs such as two hoops can also receive an 'at least n' and an 'at most n' interpretation, e.g. you need to put two hoops on the pole to win (i.e. at least two hoops) and you can miss two shots and still win (i.e. at most two shots). I demonstrate here through the results of three sets of experiments that by the age of 5 children have implicit knowledge of the fact that expressions like two N can be interpreted as 'at least two N' and 'at most two N' while they do not yet know the meaning of corresponding expressions such as at least/most two N which convey these senses explicitly. I show that these results have important implications for theories of the semantics of numerals and that they raise new questions for developmental accounts of the number vocabulary. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Language and the development of spatial reasoning.Anna Shusterman &E. S. Spelke -2005 - In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Laurence & Stephen P. Stich,The Innate Mind: Structure and Contents. New York, US: Oxford University Press on Demand. pp. 89--106.
    This chapter argues that human and animal minds indeed depend on a collection of domain-specific, task-specific, and encapsulated cognitive systems: on a set of cognitive ‘modules’ in Fodor's sense. It also argues that human and animal minds are endowed with domain-general, central systems that orchestrate the information delivered by core knowledge systems. The chapter begins by reviewing the literature on spatial reorientation in animals and in young children, arguing that spatial reorientation bears the hallmarks of core knowledge and of modularity. (...) It then considers studies of older children and adults, arguing that human spatial representations change qualitatively over development and show capacities not found in any other species. Finally, it presents two new experiments that investigate the role of emerging spatial language in uniquely human navigation performance. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Towards a pluralist theory of singular thought.Michele Palmira -2018 -Synthese 195 (9):3947-3974.
    This paper investigates the question of how to correctly capture the scope of singular thinking. The first part of the paper identifies a scope problem for the dominant view of singular thought maintaining that, in order for a thinker to have a singular thought about an object o, the thinker has to bear a special epistemic relation to o. The scope problem has it is that this view cannot make sense of the singularity of our thoughts about objects to which (...) we do not or cannot bear any special epistemic relation. The paper focuses on a specific instance of the scope problem by addressing the case of thoughts about the natural numbers. Various possible solutions to the scope problem within the dominant framework are assessed and rejected. The second part of the paper develops a new theory of singular thought which hinges on the contention that the constraints that need to be met in order to think singularly vary depending on the kind of object we are thinking about. This idea is developed in detail by discussing the difference between the somewhat standard case of thoughts about spatio-temporal medium-sized inanimate objects and the case of thoughts about the natural numbers. It is contended that this new Pluralist theory of singular thought can successfully solve the scope problem. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The role of language in mathematical development: Evidence from children with specific language impairments.Chris Donlan,Richard Cowan,Elizabeth J. Newton &Delyth Lloyd -2007 -Cognition 103 (1):23-33.
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Number concepts for the concept empiricist.Max Jones -2016 -Philosophical Psychology 29 (3):334-348.
    Dove and Machery both argue that recent findings about the nature of numerical representation present problems for Concept Empiricism. I shall argue that, whilst this evidence does challenge certain versions of CE, such as Prinz, it needn’t be seen as problematic to the general CE approach. Recent research can arguably be seen to support a CE account of number concepts. Neurological and behavioral evidence suggests that systems involved in the perception of numerical properties are also implicated in numerical cognition. Furthermore, (...) the discovery of associations between spatial and numerical representations also lends independent support to a CE approach. Although these findings support CE in general, certain versions of the theory may need revising in order to accommodate them. In particular, it may be necessary to either jettison Prinz's Modal Specificity Hypothesis or to revise one’s method for individuating modal representational formats. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Power of 2: How an Apparently Irregular Numeration System Facilitates Mental Arithmetic.Andrea Bender &Sieghard Beller -2017 -Cognitive Science 41 (1):158-187.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Thought, language, and the argument from explicitness.Agustín Vicente &Fernando Martínez-Manrique -2008 -Metaphilosophy 39 (3):381–401.
    This article deals with the relationship between language and thought, focusing on the question of whether language can be a vehicle of thought, as, for example, Peter Carruthers has claimed. We develop and examine a powerful argument—the "argument from explicitness"—against this cognitive role of language. The premises of the argument are just two: (1) the vehicle of thought has to be explicit, and (2) natural languages are not explicit. We explain what these simple premises mean and why we should believe (...) they are true. Finally, we argue that even though the argument from explicitness shows that natural language cannot be a vehicle of thought, there is a cognitive function for language. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Cognitive effects of language on human navigation.Elizabeth S. Spelke Anna Shusterman, Sang Ah Lee -2011 -Cognition 120 (2):186.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Rapid parallel semantic processing of numbers without awareness.Filip Van Opstal,Floris P. de Lange &Stanislas Dehaene -2011 -Cognition 120 (1):136-147.
  • Semantic underdetermination and the cognitive uses of language.Agustín Vicente &Fernando Martínez-Manrique -2005 -Mind and Language 20 (5):537–558.
    According to the thesis of semantic underdetermination, most sentences of a natural language lack a definite semantic interpretation. This thesis supports an argument against the use of natural language as an instrument of thought, based on the premise that cognition requires a semantically precise and compositional instrument. In this paper we examine several ways to construe this argument, as well as possible ways out for the cognitive view of natural language in the introspectivist version defended by Carruthers. Finally, we sketch (...) a view of the role of language in thought as a specialized tool, showing how it avoids the consequences of semantic underdetermination. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Distinctively human thinking: Modular precursors and components.Peter Carruthers -2005 - In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Laurence & Stephen P. Stich,The Innate Mind: Structure and Contents. New York, US: Oxford University Press on Demand. pp. 69--88.
    This chapter addresses the main challenge facing massively modular theories of the architecture of the human mind. This is to account for the distinctively flexible, non-domain-specific character of much human thinking. It shows how the appearance of a modular language faculty within an evolving modular architecture might have led to these distinctive features of human thinking with only minor further additions and non-domain-specific adaptations.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Combination Across Domains: An MEG Investigation into the Relationship between Mathematical, Pictorial, and Linguistic Processing.Douglas K. Bemis &Liina Pylkkänen -2012 -Frontiers in Psychology 3.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The relation between language and arithmetic in bilinguals: insights from different stages of language acquisition.Amandine Van Rinsveld,Martin Brunner,Karin Landerl,Christine Schiltz &Sonja Ugen -2015 -Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Learning phonetic categories by tracking movements.Bruno Gauthier,Rushen Shi &Yi Xu -2007 -Cognition 103 (1):80-106.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Does the number sense represent number?Sam Clarke &Jacob Beck -2020 - In Blair Armstrong, Stephanie Denison, Michael Mack & Yang Xu,Proceedings of the 42nd Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society.
    On a now orthodox view, humans and many other animals are endowed with a “number sense”, or approximate number system (ANS), that represents number. Recently, this orthodox view has been subject to numerous critiques, with critics maintaining either that numerical content is absent altogether, or else that some primitive analog of number (‘numerosity’) is represented as opposed to number itself. We distinguish three arguments for these claims – the arguments from congruency, confounds, and imprecision – and show that none succeed. (...) We then highlight positive reasons for thinking that the ANS genuinely represents numbers. The upshot is that proponents of the orthodox view should not feel troubled by recent critiques of their position. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Spatial Ability Explains the Male Advantage in Approximate Arithmetic.Wei Wei,Chuansheng Chen &Xinlin Zhou -2016 -Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Number word structure in first and second language influences arithmetic skills.Anat Prior,Michal Katz,Islam Mahajna &Orly Rubinsten -2015 -Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Spatial complexity of character-based writing systems and arithmetic in primary school: a longitudinal study.Maja Rodic,Tatiana Tikhomirova,Tatiana Kolienko,Sergey Malykh,Olga Bogdanova,Dina Y. Zueva,Elena I. Gynku,Sirui Wan,Xinlin Zhou &Yulia Kovas -2015 -Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download(9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Don't throw the baby out with the math water: Why discounting the developmental foundations of early numeracy is premature and unnecessary.Kevin Muldoon,Charlie Lewis &Norman Freeman -2008 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (6):663-664.
    We see no grounds for insisting that, because the concept natural number is abstract, its foundations must be innate. It is possible to specify domain general learning processes that feed into more abstract concepts of numerical infinity. By neglecting the messiness of children's slow acquisition of arithmetical concepts, Rips et al. present an idealized, unnecessarily insular, view of number development.
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Mechanistic Study of the Association Between Symbolic Approximate Arithmetic Performance and Basic Number Magnitude Processing Based on Task Difficulty.Wei Wei,Wanying Deng,Chen Chen,Jie He,Jike Qin &Yulia Kovas -2018 -Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How the Language of Instruction Influences Mathematical Thinking Development in the First Years of Bilingual Schoolers.Vicente Bermejo,Pilar Ester &Isabel Morales -2021 -Frontiers in Psychology 12:533141.
    The present research study focuses on how the language of instruction has an impact on the mathematical thinking development as a consequence of using a language of instruction different from the students’ mother tongue. In CLIL (Content and Language Integrated Learning) academic content and a foreign language are leant at the same time, a methodology that is widely used in the schools in the present times. It is, therefore, our main aim to study if the language of instruction in second (...) language immersion programs influences the development of the first formal mathematical concepts. More specifically, if the learning of mathematical concepts in the early ages develops in a similar way if it is taught in the students’ mother tongue and is not influenced by the language used for teaching. Or else, if it can influence the development of the first skills only in the students’ general performance or in certain areas. The results of both the analysis of variance and multiple regression confirm how influencing the language of instruction is when mathematical thinking is developed teaching formal contents in a non-coincidence language. The second language is affecting the resolution of daily life problems, being more competent those students in 1st grades whose language of instruction matched with their mother tongue. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hablar para pensar: sobre el uso del lenguaje en el pensamiento.Fernando Martínez Manrique &Agustín Vicente -2008 -Análisis Filosófico 28 (1):91-112.
    En este artículo examinamos la última propuesta de Carruthers acerca del papel del lenguaje en cuanto emisor global de pensamientos en una arquitectura masivamente modular, centrándonos en dos aspectos: el habla interna como integrador intermodular y su función para explicar la creatividad de la cognición humana. En primer lugar argumentamos que el lenguaje no es suficiente para la integración intermodular, a partir de lo que llamamos el "problema de la audiencia": las oraciones compuestas por el módulo lingüístico, que incorporan información (...) de distintos dominios, son ininteligibles para cada módulo central, que es de dominio específico. Como alternativa, consideramos la posibilidad de que exista integración sin que sea llevada a cabo por ningún módulo en concreto. Finalmente sostenemos que la propuesta de Carruthers para el pensamiento creativo no respeta la fenomenología ni la ambigüedad del lenguaje. Defendemos que un sistema relacionado con la "lectura de mentes", cuya función es crucial para la comunicación lingüística, debe tener un papel mucho más importante. This paper examines Carruthers's latest proposal on the role of language as a global broadcaster of thoughts in a massively modular architecture. We focus on two aspects: inner speech as an intermodular integrator, and its function to explain creativity in human cognition. First, we argue that language is not sufficient for intermodular integration from what we call "the audience problem": sentences composed by the linguistic module, combining information from different domains, would be unintelligible to each central module, which is domain-specific. As an alternative, we consider the possibility that there is integration not carried out by a specific module. Finally, we claim that Carruthers's proposal for creative thinking respects neither the phenomenology nor the ambiguity of language. We contend that a mindreading system, which has a crucial function in linguistic communication, must have a much more important role to play. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Language as a Necessary Condition for Complex Mental Content: A Review of the Discussion on Spatial and Mathematical Thinking. [REVIEW]Arkadiusz Gut &Robert Mirski -2018 -Roczniki Filozoficzne 66 (3):33-56.
    In this article we review the discussion over the thesis that language serves as an integrator of contents coming from different cognitive modules. After presenting the theoretical considerations, we examine two strands of empirical research that tested the hypothesis — spatial cognition and mathematical cognition. The idea shared by both of them is that each is composed of two separate modules processing information of a specific kind. For spatial thinking these are geometric information about the location of the object and (...) the information about the object’s properties such as color or size. For mathematical thinking, they are the absolute representation of small numbers and the approximate representation of numerosities. Language is said to integrate the two kinds of information within each of these domains, which the reviewed data demonstrates. In the final part of the paper, we offer some comments on the theoretical side of the discussion. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  

  • [8]ページ先頭

    ©2009-2025 Movatter.jp