Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs
Switch to: References

Add citations

You mustlogin to add citations.
  1. Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness-potential). The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act.Benjamin Libet,Curtis A. Gleason,Elwood W. Wright &Dennis K. Pearl -1983 -Brain 106 (3):623--664.
  • Measurement of sensory intensity.Richard M. Warren -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):175-189.
    The measurement of sensory intensity has had a long history, attracting the attention of investigators from many disciplines including physiology, psychology, physics, mathematics, philosophy, and even chemistry. While there has been a continuing doubt by some that sensation has the properties necessary for measurement, experiments designed to obtain estimates of sensory intensity have found that a general rule applies: Equal stimulus ratios produce equal sensory ratios. Theories concerning the basis for this simple psychophysical rule are discussed, with emphasis given to (...) the physical correlate theory, which considers judgments of subjective magnitudes to be based upon estimates of physical dimensions that vary regularly with changes in degree of stimulation. For the most thoroughly investigated sensory scales, brightness and loudness, the physical correlate is considered to be distance. Our “tacit knowledge” of the sensory effects of changing distance plays an essential role in matching motor activities to environmental conditions and in ensuring accurate perceptual evaluations through brightness and loudness constancies. In psychophysical experiments, subjects apparently use this same tacit knowledge when required to estimate relative subjective magnitudes. The evidence related to the physical correlate theory is summarized, and it is concluded that, while under appropriate conditions we demonstrate considerable skill in evaluating environmental relationships, we are quite unable to estimate the neurophysiological nature or quantity of sensory response. A psychophysics devoted to studying conditions required for accuracy and conditions producing errors in the perception of environmental relationships would seem to be more valuable than one devoted to subjective magnitudes. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   167 citations  
  • Reconciling Fechner and Stevens?Donald Laming -1991 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):188-191.
  • Psychophysical law: Taming the cognitive and chaotic aspects.Lester E. Krueger -1991 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):193-199.
  • Psychophysical scaling: Judgments of attributes or objects?Gregory R. Lockhead -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):543-558.
    Psychophysical scaling models of the form R = f, with R the response and I some intensity of an attribute, all assume that people judge the amounts of an attribute. With simple biases excepted, most also assume that judgments are independent of space, time, and features of the situation other than the one being judged. Many data support these ideas: Magnitude estimations of brightness increase with luminance. Nevertheless, I argue that the general model is wrong. The stabilized retinal image literature (...) shows that nothing is seen if light does not change over time. The classification literature shows that dimensions often combine to produce emergent properties that cannot be described by the elements in the stimulus. These and other effects cannot be adjusted for by simply adding variables to the general model because some factors do not combine linearly. The proposed alternative is that people initially judge the entire stimulus – the object in terms of its environment. This agrees with the constancy literature that shows that objects and their attributes are identified through their relations to other aspects of the scene. That the environment determines judgments is masked in scaling studies where the standard procedure is to hold context constant. In a typical brightness study the essential stimulus might be the intensity of the light or a difference between the light and the background. The two are perfectly confounded. This issue is examined in the case of audition. Judgments of the loudness of a tone depend on how much that tone differs from the previous tone in both pitch and loudness. To judge loudness people first seem to process the stimulus object in terms of differences between it and other aspects in the situation; only then do they assess the feature of interest. Psychophysical judgments will therefore be better interpreted by theories of attention that are based in biology or psychology than those that are based in classical physics. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Psychophysics and ecometrics.William H. Warren &Robert E. Shaw -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):209-210.
  • Methodological suggestions from a comparative psychology of knowledge processes.Donald T. Campbell -1959 -Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 2 (1-4):152 – 182.
    Introductory Abstract Philosophers of science, in the course of making a sharp distinction between the tasks of the philosopher and those of the scientist, have pointed to the possibility of an empirical science of induction. A comparative psychology of knowledge processes is offered as one aspect of this potential enterprise. From fragments of such a psychology, methodological suggestions are drawn relevant to several chronic problems in the social sciences, including the publication of negative results from novel explorations, the operational diagnosis (...) of dispositions, the status of aggregates of persons as social entities, and the validation of psychological tests. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Neural and behavioral assessments of sensory quantity.Gerald S. Wasserman -1991 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):192-193.
  • Schooling and the new psychophysics.E. C. Poulton -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):201-203.
  • Sensory scaling: A paradigm whose time has past.Michel Treisman -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):206-207.
  • Dead men tell odd simple tales!Robert A. M. Gregson -1991 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):187-188.
  • Cooperation, psychological game theory, and limitations of rationality in social interaction.Andrew M. Colman -2003 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (2):139-153.
    Rational choice theory enjoys unprecedented popularity and influence in the behavioral and social sciences, but it generates intractable problems when applied to socially interactive decisions. In individual decisions, instrumental rationality is defined in terms of expected utility maximization. This becomes problematic in interactive decisions, when individuals have only partial control over the outcomes, because expected utility maximization is undefined in the absence of assumptions about how the other participants will behave. Game theory therefore incorporates not only rationality but also common (...) knowledge assumptions, enabling players to anticipate their co-players' strategies. Under these assumptions, disparate anomalies emerge. Instrumental rationality, conventionally interpreted, fails to explain intuitively obvious features of human interaction, yields predictions starkly at variance with experimental findings, and breaks down completely in certain cases. In particular, focal point selection in pure coordination games is inexplicable, though it is easily achieved in practice; the intuitively compelling payoff-dominance principle lacks rational justification; rationality in social dilemmas is self-defeating; a key solution concept for cooperative coalition games is frequently inapplicable; and rational choice in certain sequential games generates contradictions. In experiments, human players behave more cooperatively and receive higher payoffs than strict rationality would permit. Orthodox conceptions of rationality are evidently internally deficient and inadequate for explaining human interaction. Psychological game theory, based on nonstandard assumptions, is required to solve these problems, and some suggestions along these lines have already been put forward. Key Words: backward induction; Centipede game; common knowledge; cooperation; epistemic reasoning; game theory; payoff dominance; pure coordination game; rational choice theory; social dilemma. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Ceteris paribus laws.J. van Brakel -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):584-585.
  • Will the real stimulus please step forward?Lester E. Krueger -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):570-572.
  • Accounting for an old inconsistency in the psychophysics of Plateau and Delboeuf.Marc Brysbaert -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):562-563.
  • Can brightness be related to luminance by a meaningful function?Ehtibar N. Dzhafarov -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):565-566.
  • Attributes or objects: A paradigm shift in psychophysics.John S. Monahan -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):577-577.
  • The evident object of inquiry.Keith K. Niall -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):578-578.
  • Perception, apperception and psychophysics.Daniel Algom -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):558-559.
  • Psychophysical scaling: Context and illusion.Stanley Coren -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):563-564.
  • When learning to classify by relations is easier than by features.Bradley C. Love &Marc T. Tomlinson -2010 -Thinking and Reasoning 16 (4):372-401.
  • Psychophysical scaling within an information processing approach?Claude Bonnet -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):560-561.
  • Prospect relativity: how choice options influence decision under risk.Neil Stewart,Nick Chater,Henry P. Stott &Stian Reimers -2003 -Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 132 (1):23.
  • Selecting one attribute for judgment is not an act of stupidity.Robert Teghtsoonian -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):580-581.
  • Do we scale “objects” or isolated sensory dimensions?Michel Treisman -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):581-584.
  • Relation of sensory scales to physical scales.Richard M. Warren -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):586-587.
  • Integration psychophysics is not traditional psychophysics.Norman H. Anderson -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):559-560.
  • Lockhead's view of scaling: Something's fishy here.Stanley J. Bolanowski -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):560-560.
  • Psychophysical scaling: To describe relations or to uncover a law?Gunnar Borg -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):561-562.
  • Psychophysical invariance, perceptual invariance and the physicalistic trap.Hannes Eisler -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):566-567.
  • The complexity and importance of the psychophysical scaling of sensory attributes.George A. Gescheider -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):567-567.
  • Two categories of contextual variable in perception.Donald Laming -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):572-573.
  • Warren's physical correlate theory: Correlation does not imply causation.Donald D. Dorfman -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):192-193.
    Warren's major contention is that judgments of subjective magnitude are not possible, and therefore subjects base such judgments upon physical correlates of the dimension in question. It would appear that Warren's theory will almost surely fail as a comprehensive model, even though it does provide a heuristic account of judgments of loudness and brightness. In order for the theory to succeed, Warren must specify a physical correlate for judgments ofeverysubjective attribute that has yielded orderly data with Stevens's scaling procedures.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Sensory coding: The search for invariants.R. J. W. Mansfield -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):198-199.
  • Distance - a physical correlate of brightness and loudness scaling?Erich Mittenecker -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):200-201.
  • Objections to physical correlate theory, with emphasis on loudness.Bertram Scharf &Rhona Hellman -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):203-204.
  • Subjective averaging of length with serial presentation.David J. Weiss &Norman H. Anderson -1969 -Journal of Experimental Psychology 82 (1p1):52.
  • Cognitive algebra and sensation measurement.Norman H. Anderson -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):189-190.
  • Sensations, correlates and judgments: Why physics?Hannes Eisler -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):193-194.
  • In defense of a sensory process theory of psychophysical scaling.George A. Gescheider -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):194-194.
  • On relating physiology to sensation.Donald C. Hood &Marcia A. Finkelstein -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):195-195.
  • Bridging psychology and game theory yields interdependence theory.Paul A. M. Van Lange &Marcello Gallucci -2003 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (2):177-178.
    This commentary focuses on the parts of psychological game theory dealing with preference, as illustrated by team reasoning, and supports the conclusion that these theoretical notions do not contribute above and beyond existing theory in understanding social interaction. In particular, psychology and games are already bridged by a comprehensive, formal, and inherently psychological theory, interdependence theory (Kelley & Thibaut 1978; Kelley et al. 2003), which has been demonstrated to account for a wide variety of social interaction phenomena.
    Direct download(8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Psychophysical theory: On the avoidance of contradiction.John C. Baird -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):190-190.
  • Multisource Assessment for Development Purposes: Revisiting the Methodology of Data Analysis.Joan Manuel Batista-Foguet,Willem Saris,Richard E. Boyatzis,Ricard Serlavós &Ferran Velasco Moreno -2019 -Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Limitations of the physical correlate theory of psychophysical judgment.Michael H. Birnbaum -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):190-191.
  • The determinants of perceived brightness are complicated, but not hopelessly so.Thomas R. Corwin -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):564-565.
  • Direct judgments: Sensation or stimulus correlate?Dwight W. Curtis -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):191-192.
  • Scales falling from the eyes?Richard L. Gregory -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):567-568.
  • Walking in a psychophysical dustbowl creates a dustcloud.Robert A. M. Gregson -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):568-569.
  • A dialogue on loudness.Geoffrey J. Iverson -1981 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):195-196.

  • [8]ページ先頭

    ©2009-2025 Movatter.jp