Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs
Switch to: References

Add citations

You mustlogin to add citations.
  1. Perceptual symbol systems.Lawrence W. Barsalou -1999 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (4):577-660.
    Prior to the twentieth century, theories of knowledge were inherently perceptual. Since then, developments in logic, statis- tics, and programming languages have inspired amodal theories that rest on principles fundamentally different from those underlying perception. In addition, perceptual approaches have become widely viewed as untenable because they are assumed to implement record- ing systems, not conceptual systems. A perceptual theory of knowledge is developed here in the context of current cognitive science and neuroscience. During perceptual experience, association areas in the (...) brain capture bottom-up patterns of activation in sensory-motor areas. Later, in a top-down manner, association areas partially reactivate sensory-motor areas to implement perceptual symbols. The stor- age and reactivation of perceptual symbols operates at the level of perceptual components – not at the level of holistic perceptual expe- riences. Through the use of selective attention, schematic representations of perceptual components are extracted from experience and stored in memory (e.g., individual memories of green, purr, hot). As memories of the same component become organized around a com- mon frame, they implement a simulator that produces limitless simulations of the component (e.g., simulations of purr). Not only do such simulators develop for aspects of sensory experience, they also develop for aspects of proprioception (e.g., lift, run) and introspec- tion (e.g., compare, memory, happy, hungry). Once established, these simulators implement a basic conceptual system that represents types, supports categorization, and produces categorical inferences. These simulators further support productivity, propositions, and ab- stract concepts, thereby implementing a fully functional conceptual system. Productivity results from integrating simulators combinato- rially and recursively to produce complex simulations. Propositions result from binding simulators to perceived individuals to represent type-token relations. Abstract concepts are grounded in complex simulations of combined physical and introspective events. Thus, a per- ceptual theory of knowledge can implement a fully functional conceptual system while avoiding problems associated with amodal sym- bol systems. Implications for cognition, neuroscience, evolution, development, and artificial intelligence are explored. (shrink)
    Direct download(10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   820 citations  
  • Natural language and natural selection.Steven Pinker &Paul Bloom -1990 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):707-27.
    Many people have argued that the evolution of the human language faculty cannot be explained by Darwinian natural selection. Chomsky and Gould have suggested that language may have evolved as the by-product of selection for other abilities or as a consequence of as-yet unknown laws of growth and form. Others have argued that a biological specialization for grammar is incompatible with every tenet of Darwinian theory – that it shows no genetic variation, could not exist in any intermediate forms, confers (...) no selective advantage, and would require more evolutionary time and genomic space than is available. We examine these arguments and show that they depend on inaccurate assumptions about biology or language or both. Evolutionary theory offers clear criteria for when a trait should be attributed to natural selection: complex design for some function, and the absence of alternative processes capable of explaining such complexity. Human language meets these criteria: Grammar is a complex mechanism tailored to the transmission of propositional structures through a serial interface. Autonomous and arbitrary grammatical phenomena have been offered as counterexamples to the position that language is an adaptation, but this reasoning is unsound: Communication protocols depend on arbitrary conventions that are adaptive as long as they are shared. Consequently, language acquisition in the child should systematically differ from language evolution in the species, and attempts to analogize them are misleading. Reviewing other arguments and data, we conclude that there is every reason to believe that a specialization for grammar evolved by a conventional neo-Darwinian process. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   615 citations  
  • Building machines that learn and think like people.Brenden M. Lake,Tomer D. Ullman,Joshua B. Tenenbaum &Samuel J. Gershman -2017 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 40.
    Recent progress in artificial intelligence has renewed interest in building systems that learn and think like people. Many advances have come from using deep neural networks trained end-to-end in tasks such as object recognition, video games, and board games, achieving performance that equals or even beats that of humans in some respects. Despite their biological inspiration and performance achievements, these systems differ from human intelligence in crucial ways. We review progress in cognitive science suggesting that truly human-like learning and thinking (...) machines will have to reach beyond current engineering trends in both what they learn and how they learn it. Specifically, we argue that these machines should build causal models of the world that support explanation and understanding, rather than merely solving pattern recognition problems; ground learning in intuitive theories of physics and psychology to support and enrich the knowledge that is learned; and harness compositionality and learning-to-learn to rapidly acquire and generalize knowledge to new tasks and situations. We suggest concrete challenges and promising routes toward these goals that can combine the strengths of recent neural network advances with more structured cognitive models. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   115 citations  
  • Are humans good intuitive statisticians after all? Rethinking some conclusions from the literature on judgment under uncertainty.L. Cosmides -1996 -Cognition 58 (1):1-73.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   145 citations  
  • A phone in a basket looks like a knife in a cup: Role-filler independence in visual processing.Alon Hafri,Michael Bonner,Barbara Landau &Chaz Firestone -2024 -Open Mind.
    When a piece of fruit is in a bowl, and the bowl is on a table, we appreciate not only the individual objects and their features, but also the relations containment and support, which abstract away from the particular objects involved. Independent representation of roles (e.g., containers vs. supporters) and “fillers” of those roles (e.g., bowls vs. cups, tables vs. chairs) is a core principle of language and higherlevel reasoning. But does such role-filler independence also arise in automatic visual processing? (...) Here, we show that it does, by exploring a surprising error that such independence can produce. In four experiments, participants saw a stream of images containing different objects arranged in forcedynamic relations — e.g., a phone contained in a basket, a marker resting on a garbage can, or a knife sitting in a cup. Participants had to respond to a single target image (e.g., a phone in a basket) within a stream of distractors presented under time constraints. Surprisingly, even though participants completed this task quickly and accurately, they false-alarmed more often to images matching the target’s relational category than to those that did not — even when those images involved completely different objects. In other words, participants searching for a phone in a basket were more likely to mistakenly respond to a knife in a cup than to a marker on a garbage can. Follow-up experiments ruled out strategic responses and also controlled for various confounding image features. We suggest that visual processing represents relations abstractly, in ways that separate roles from fillers. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What good is five percent of a language competence?A. Charles Catania -1990 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):729-731.
  • The view of language.Michael Studdert-Kennedy -1990 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):758-759.
  • Dynamic attending and responses to time.Mari Riess Jones &Marilyn Boltz -1989 -Psychological Review 96 (3):459-491.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Perceptual-cognitive universals as reflections of the world.Roger N. Shepard -2001 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (4):581-601.
    The universality, invariance, and elegance of principles governing the universe may be reflected in principles of the minds that have evolved in that universe – provided that the mental principles are formulated with respect to the abstract spaces appropriate for the representation of biologically significant objects and their properties. (1) Positions and motions of objects conserve their shapes in the geometrically fullest and simplest way when represented as points and connecting geodesic paths in the six-dimensional manifold jointly determined by the (...) Euclidean group of three-dimensional space and the symmetry group of each object. (2) Colors of objects attain constancy when represented as points in a three-dimensional vector space in which each variation in natural illumination is canceled by application of its inverse from the three-dimensional linear group of terrestrial transformations of the invariant solar source. (3) Kinds of objects support optimal generalization and categorization when represented, in an evolutionarily-shaped space of possible objects, as connected regions with associated weights determined by Bayesian revision of maximum-entropy priors. Key Words: apparent motion; Bayesian inference; cognition; color constancy; generalization; mental rotation; perception; psychological laws; psychological space; universal laws. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Mental imagery.Nigel J. T. Thomas -2001 -Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Mental imagery (varieties of which are sometimes colloquially refered to as “visualizing,” “seeing in the mind's eye,” “hearing in the head,” “imagining the feel of,” etc.) is quasi-perceptual experience; it resembles perceptual experience, but occurs in the absence of the appropriate external stimuli. It is also generally understood to bear intentionality (i.e., mental images are always images of something or other), and thereby to function as a form of mental representation. Traditionally, visual mental imagery, the most discussed variety, was thought (...) to be caused by the presence of picturelike representations (mental images) in the mind, soul, or brain, but this is no longer universally accepted. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Scrutinizing visual images: The role of gaze in mental imagery and memory.Bruno Laeng,Ilona M. Bloem,Stefania D’Ascenzo &Luca Tommasi -2014 -Cognition 131 (2):263-283.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Constraints on Constraints: Surveying the Epigenetic Landscape.Frank C. Keil -1990 -Cognitive Science 14 (1):135-168.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Attention and the evolution of intentional communication.Ingar Brinck -2000 -Pragmatics and Cognition 9 (2):259-277.
    Intentional communication is perceptually based and about attentional objects. Three attention mechanisms are distinguished: scanning, attention attraction, and attention-focusing. Attention-focusing directs the subject towards attentional objects. Attention-focusing is goal-governed (controlled by stimulus) or goal-intended (under the control of the subject). Attentional objects are perceptually categorised functional entities that emerge in the interaction between subjects and environment. Joint attention allows for focusing on the same attentional object simultaneously (mutual object-focused attention), provided that the subjects have focused on each other beforehand (subject-subject (...) attention). It results in intentional communication if the subjects attend to each other as subjects (i) capable of attending, and (ii) attending in a goal-intended way. Intentional communication is fundamentally imperative and adapted to action. (shrink)
    Direct download(9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Problems for the Purported Cognitive Penetration of Perceptual Color Experience and Macpherson’s Proposed Mechanism.Steven Gross,Thitaporn Chaisilprungraung,Elizabeth Kaplan,Jorge Aurelio Menendez &Jonathan Flombaum -2014 -Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication.
    Fiona Macpherson (2012) argues that various experimental results provide strong evidence in favor of the cognitive penetration of perceptual color experience. Moreover, she proposes a mechanism for how such cognitive penetration occurs. We argue, first, that the results on which Macpherson relies do not provide strong grounds for her claim of cognitive penetrability; and, second, that, if the results do reflect cognitive penetrability, then time-course considerations raise worries for her proposed mechanism. We base our arguments in part on several of (...) our own experiments, reported herein. (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Moving words: dynamic representations in language comprehension*1.R. Zwaan -2004 -Cognitive Science 28 (4):611-619.
    Eighty‐two participants listened to sentences and then judged whether two sequentially presented visual objects were the same. On critical trials, participants heard a sentence describe the motion of a ball toward or away from the observer (e.g., “The pitcher hurled the softball to you”). Seven hundred and fifty milliseconds after the offset of the sentence, a picture of an object was presented for 500 ms, followed by another picture. On critical trials, the two pictures depicted the kind of ball mentioned (...) in the sentence. The second picture was displayed 175 ms after the first. Crucially, it was either slightly larger or smaller than the first picture, thus suggesting movement of the ball toward or away from the observer. Participants responded more quickly when the implied movement of the balls matched the movement described in the sentence. This result provides support for the viewthat language comprehension involves dynamic perceptual simulations. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Do readers mentally represent characters' emotional states?Morton Ann Gernsbacher,H. Hill Goldsmith &Rachel R. W. Robertson -1992 -Cognition and Emotion 6 (2):89-111.
  • Welcome to functionalism.Elizabeth Bates &Brian MacWhinney -1990 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):727-728.
  • Perceiving expressions of emotion: What evidence could bear on questions about perceptual experience of mental states?Stephen A. Butterfill -2015 -Consciousness and Cognition 36:438-451.
  • An implicit measure of undetected change.Ian Thornton &Diego Fernandez-Duque -2000 -Spatial Vision 14 (1):21-44.
    b>—Several paradigms (e.g. change blindness, inattentional blindness, transsaccadic integra- tion) indicate that observers are often very poor at reporting changes to their visual environment. Such evidence has been used to suggest that the spatio-temporal coherence needed to represent change can only occur in the presence of focused attention. However, those studies almost always rely on explicit reports. It remains a possibility that the visual system can implicitly detect change, but that in the absence of focused attention, the change does not (...) reach awareness and consequently is not reported. To test this possibility, we used a simple change detection paradigm coupled with a speeded orien- tation discrimination task. Even when observers reported being unaware of a change in an item’s orientation, its nal orientation effectively biased their response in the orientation discrimination task. Both in aware and unaware trials, errors were most frequent when the changed item and the probe had incongruent orientations. These results demonstrate that the _nature _of the change can be represented in the absence of awareness. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • From embodied to extended cognition.John A. Teske -2013 -Zygon 48 (3):759-787.
    Embodied cognitive science holds that cognitive processes are deeply and inescapably rooted in our bodily interactions with the world. Our finite, contingent, and mortal embodiment may be not only supportive, but in some cases even constitutive of emotions, thoughts, and experiences. My discussion here will work outward from the neuroanatomy and neurophysiology of the brain to a nervous system which extends to the boundaries of the body. It will extend to nonneural aspects of embodiment and even beyond the boundaries of (...) the body to prosthetics of various kinds, including symbioses with a broad array of cultural artifacts, our symbolic niche, and our relationships with other embodied human beings. While cognition may not always be situated, its origins are embedded in temporally and spatially limited activities. Cognitive work also can be off-loaded to the body and to the environment in service of action, tool use, group cognition, and social coordination. This can blur the boundaries between brain areas, brain and body, and body and environment, transforming our understanding of mind and personhood to provide a different grounding for faith traditions in general, and of the historically dualist Christian tradition in particular. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Codes and their vicissitudes.Bernhard Hommel,Jochen Müsseler,Gisa Aschersleben &Wolfgang Prinz -2001 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (5):910-926.
    First, we discuss issues raised with respect to the Theory of Event Coding (TEC)'s scope, that is, its limitations and possible extensions. Then, we address the issue of specificity, that is, the widespread concern that TEC is too unspecified and, therefore, too vague in a number of important respects. Finally, we elaborate on our views about TEC's relations to other important frameworks and approaches in the field like stages models, ecological approaches, and the two-visual-pathways model. Footnotes1 We acknowledge the precedence (...) of both Freud¹s Instincts and Their Vicissitudes (1915) and Neisser¹s Stimulus Information and Its Vicissitudes (a term Neisser borrowed from Freud for his monograph “Cognitive psychology,” 1967). (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Temporal cognition and the phenomenology of time: A multiplicative function for apparent duration.Joseph Glicksohn -2001 -Consciousness and Cognition 10 (1):1-25.
    The literature on time perception is discussed. This is done with reference both to the ''cognitive-timer'' model for time estimation and to the subjective experience of apparent duration. Three assumptions underlying the model are scrutinized. I stress the strong interplay among attention, arousal, and time perception, which is at the base of the cognitive-timer model. It is suggested that a multiplicative function of two key components (the number of subjective time units and their size) should predict apparent duration. Implications for (...) other cognitive domains are drawn, and in particular an analogy is suggested between apparent duration and apparent movement. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Emotion identification across adulthood using the Dynamic FACES database of emotional expressions in younger, middle aged, and older adults.Catherine A. C. Holland,Natalie C. Ebner,Tian Lin &Gregory R. Samanez-Larkin -2018 -Cognition and Emotion 33 (2):245-257.
    ABSTRACTFacial stimuli are widely used in behavioural and brain science research to investigate emotional facial processing. However, some studies have demonstrated that dynamic expressions elicit stronger emotional responses compared to static images. To address the need for more ecologically valid and powerful facial emotional stimuli, we created Dynamic FACES, a database of morphed videos from younger, middle-aged, and older adults displaying naturalistic emotional facial expressions. To assess adult age differences in emotion identification of dynamic stimuli and to provide normative ratings (...) for this modified set of stimuli, healthy adults categorised for each video the emotional expression displayed, rated the expression distinctiveness, estimated the age of the face model, and rated the naturalness of the expression. We found few age differences in emotion identification when using dynamic stimuli. On... (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Does representational momentum reflect a distortion of the length or the endpoint of a trajectory?Timothy L. Hubbard &Michael A. Motes -2002 -Cognition 82 (3):B89-B99.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Depicting Motion in a Static Image: Philosophy, Psychology and the Perception of Pictures.Luca Marchetti -2022 -British Journal of Aesthetics 62 (3):353-371.
    This paper focuses on whether static images can depict motion. It is natural to say that pictures depicting objects caught in the middle of a dynamic action—such as Henri Cartier-Bresson’s (1932) Behind the Gare St. Lazare—are pictures of movement, but, given that pictures themselves do not move, can we make sense of such an idea? Drawing on results from experimental psychology and cognitive sciences, I show that we can. Psychological studies on implicit motion and representational momentum indicate that motion is (...) really perceived in some static images: our visual system is built in order to detect motion, even where it is only implied, and to anticipate the probable outcomes of others’ actions—even when the ‘others’ are only the subject matters of pictures’. I argue that, consequently, a range of popular depiction theories—perceptualist theories of depiction—can accommodate depicted motion. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On time, memory and dynamic form.Stephen E. Robbins -2004 -Consciousness and Cognition 13 (4):762-788.
    A common approach to explaining the perception of form is through the use of static features. The weakness of this approach points naturally to dynamic definitions of form. Considering dynamical form, however, leads inevitably to the need to explain how events are perceived as time-extended—a problem with primacy over that even of qualia. Optic flow models, energy models, models reliant on a rigidity constraint are examined. The reliance of these models on the instantaneous specification of form at an instant, t, (...) or across a series of such instants forces the consideration of the primary memory supporting both the perception of time-extended events and the time-extension of consciousness. This cannot be reduced to an integration over space and time. The difficulty of defining the basis for this memory is highlighted in considerations of dynamic form in relation to scales of time. Ultimately, the possibility is raised that psychology must follow physics in a more profound approach to time and motion. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Humans Anticipate the Goal of other People’s Point-Light Actions.Claudia Elsner,Terje Falck-Ytter &Gustaf Gredebäck -2012 -Frontiers in Psychology 3.
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Particulars.Johanna Seibt -2010 - In Roberto Poli & Johanna Seibt,Theory and Applications of Ontology: Philosophical Perspectives. Springer Verlag. pp. 23--55.
    According to the standard view of particularity, an entity is a particular just in case it necessarily has a unique spatial location at any time of its existence. That the basic entities of the world we speak about in common sense and science are particular entities in this sense is the thesis of “foundational particularism,” a theoretical intuition that has guided Western ontological research from its beginnings to the present day. The main aim of this paper is to review the (...) notion of particularity and its role in ontology. I proceed in four steps. First, I offer a brief reconstruction of the tasks of ontology as “theory of categorial inference in L”. An ontological theory states which (combinations of) entity types or categories make true L-sentences true; the features of the stipulated categories explain why L-speakers are entitled to draw certain material inferences from the classificatory expressions of L. Second, I draw attention to the fact that since Aristotle this theoretical program typically has been implemented with peculiar restrictions prescribing certain combinations of category features, e.g., the combination of particularity, concreteness, individuality, and subjecthood. I briefly sketch how these restrictions of the “substance paradigm” or “myth of substance” are reinforced by the standard readings of predicate-logical constants, viz. the existential quantifier and the identity sign. Third, I argue that in the context of the substance paradigm foundational particularism is incoherent. I discuss the current standard conceptions of particulars as developed in the debate about individuation (bare particulars, nude particulars, tropes) and show that their main difficulties derive from the traditional restriction that particulars are so also logical subjects and/or individuals. Fourth, to show that the traditional linkages of category features are not conceptual necessities, I sketch the outlines of an ontology (General Process Theory) based on non-particular individuals. For ontologists in computer science working with description logic this monocategoreal ontology based on more or less generic ‘dynamics’ may hold special interest. As General Process Theory documents, ontologists may well abandon the notion of particularity: in common sense and science we do reason about items that have a unique spatial location at any time, but the uniqueness of their location can be taken to be a contingent affair. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Further Correspondences and Similarities of Shamanism and Cognitive Science: Mental Representation, Implicit Processing, and Cognitive Structures.Timothy L. Hubbard -2003 -Anthropology of Consciousness 14 (1):40-74.
    Properties of mental representation are related to findings in cognitive science and ideas in shamanism. A selective review of research in cognitive science suggests visual images and spatial memory preserve important functional information regarding physical principles and the behavior of objects in the natural world, and notions of second‐order isomorphism and the perceptual cycle developed to account for such findings are related to shamanic experience. Possible roles of implicit processes in shamanic cognition, and the idea that shamanic experience may involve (...) normally unconscious information becoming temporarily available to consciousness, are considered. The existence of a cognitive module dedicated to processing information relevant to social knowledge and social interaction is consistent with cognitive science and with shamanism, and may help account for the extension of intentionality and meaning that characterize shamanic practice. Overall, findings from cognitive science and ideas from shamanism exhibit a number of correspondences and similarities regarding basic properties of cognition, and this suggests that shamanic and nonshamanic cognition may not be fundamentally different. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Interactive knowing: The metaphysics of intentionality.Mark H. Bickhard -2010 - In Roberto Poli & Johanna Seibt,Theory and Applications of Ontology: Philosophical Perspectives. Springer Verlag. pp. 207--229.
  • Ontology and Methodology in Analytic Philosophy.John Symons -2010 - In Roberto Poli & Johanna Seibt,Theory and Applications of Ontology: Philosophical Perspectives. Springer Verlag. pp. 349--394.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The sound of motion in spoken language: Visual information conveyed by acoustic properties of speech.Hadas Shintel &Howard C. Nusbaum -2007 -Cognition 105 (3):681-690.
  • A dynamic approach to recognition memory.Gregory E. Cox &Richard M. Shiffrin -2017 -Psychological Review 124 (6):795-860.
    No categories
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Walk this way: Approaching bodies can influence the processing of faces.Karin S. Pilz,Quoc C. Vuong,Heinrich H. Bülthoff &Ian M. Thornton -2011 -Cognition 118 (1):17-31.
    No categories
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Effects of Badminton Expertise on Representational Momentum: A Combination of Cross-Sectional and Longitudinal Studies.Hua Jin,Pin Wang,Zhuo Fang,Xin Di,Zhuo’er Ye,Guiping Xu,Huiyan Lin,Yongmin Cheng,Yongjie Li,Yong Xu &Hengyi Rao -2017 -Frontiers in Psychology 8.
  • What's in a name for memory errors? Implications and ethical issues arising from the use of the term "false memory" for errors in memory for details.Anne P. DePrince,Carolyn B. Allard,Hannah Oh &Jennifer J. Freyd -2004 -Ethics and Behavior 14 (3):201 – 233.
    The term "false memories" has been used to refer to suggestibility experiments in which whole events are apparently confabulated and in media accounts of contested memories of childhood abuse. Since 1992 psychologists have increasingly used the term "false memory" when discussing memory errors for details, such as specific words within word lists. Use of the term to refer to errors in details is a shift in language away from other terms used historically (e.g., "memory intrusions"). We empirically examine this shift (...) in language and discuss implications of the new use of the term "false memories." Use of the term presents serious ethical challenges to the data-interpretation process by encouraging over-generalization and misapplication of research findings on word memory to social issues. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Analogical reminding and the storage of experience: the paradox of Hofstadter-Sander.Stephen E. Robbins -2017 -Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 16 (3):355-385.
    In their exhaustive study of the cognitive operation of analogy, Hofstadter and Sander arrive at a paradox: the creative and inexhaustible production of analogies in our thought must derive from a “reminding” operation based upon the availability of the detailed totality of our experience. Yet the authors see no way that our experience can be stored in the brain in such detail nor do they see how such detail could be accessed or retrieved such that the innumerable analogical remindings we (...) experience can occur. Analogy creation, then, should not be possible. The intent here is to sharpen and deepen our understanding of the paradox, emphasizing its criticality. It will be shown that the retrieval problem has its origins in the failure of memory theory to recognize the actual dynamic structure of events. This structure is comprised of invariance laws as per J. J. Gibson, and this event “invariance structure” is exactly what supports Hofstadter and Sander’s missing mechanism for analogical reminding. Yet these structures of invariants, existing only over optical flows, auditory flows, haptic flows, etc., are equally difficult to imagine being stored in a static memory, and thus only exacerbate the problem of the storage of experience in the brain. A possible route to the solution of this dilemma, based in the radical model of Bergson, is also sketched. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The evolution of the language faculty: A paradox and its solution.Dan Sperber -1990 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):756-758.
  • Anatomizing the rhinoceros.Elliott Sober -1990 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):764-765.
  • A patterned process approach to brain, consciousness, and behavior.José-Luis Díaz -1997 -Philosophical Psychology 10 (2):179-195.
    The architecture of brain, consciousness, and behavioral processes is shown to be formally similar in that all three may be conceived and depicted as Petri net patterned processes structured by a series of elements occurring or becoming active in stochastic succession, in parallel, with different rhythms of temporal iteration, and with a distinct qualitative manifestation in the spatiotemporal domain. A patterned process theory is derived from the isomorphic features of the models and contrasted with connectionist, dynamic system notions. This empirically (...) derived formulation is considered to be optimally compatible with the dual aspect theory in that the foundation of the diverse aspects would be a highly structured and dynamic process, the psychophysical neutral “ground” of mind and matter posed (but not properly determined) by dual aspect and neutral monist theories. It is methodologically sound to approach each one of these processes with specific tools and to establish concurrences in real time between them at the organismic level of analysis. Such intra‐level and inter‐perspective correlations could eventually constitute psychophysical bridge‐laws. A mature psychology of consciousness is necessary to situate and verify the bridges required by a genuine mind‐body science. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Representational momentum for the human body: Awkwardness matters, experience does not.Margaret Wilson,Jessy Lancaster &Karen Emmorey -2010 -Cognition 116 (2):242-250.
  • The ontology of perception.Liliana Albertazzi -2010 - In Roberto Poli & Johanna Seibt,Theory and Applications of Ontology: Philosophical Perspectives. Springer Verlag. pp. 177--206.
  • The embodied dynamics of perceptual causality: a slippery slope?Michel-Ange Amorim,Isabelle A. Siegler,Robin Baurès &Armando M. Oliveira -2015 -Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The role of logic and ontology in language and reasoning.John F. Sowa -2010 - In Roberto Poli & Johanna Seibt,Theory and Applications of Ontology: Philosophical Perspectives. Springer Verlag. pp. 231--263.
  • What would a theory of language evolution have to look like?Ray Jackendoff -1990 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):737-738.
  • Adaptive complexity in sound patterns.Björn Lindblom -1990 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):743-744.
  • Arbitrariness no argument against adaption.Mark Ridley -1990 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):756-756.
  • In defense of exaptation.Wendy Wilkins &Jennie Dumford -1990 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):763-764.
  • Hermeneutic Ontology.Daniel O. Dahlstrom -2010 - In Roberto Poli & Johanna Seibt,Theory and Applications of Ontology: Philosophical Perspectives. Springer Verlag. pp. 395--415.
  • The ontology of mereological systems: A logical approach.Heinrich Herre -2010 - In Roberto Poli & Johanna Seibt,Theory and Applications of Ontology: Philosophical Perspectives. Springer Verlag. pp. 57--82.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  

  • [8]ページ先頭

    ©2009-2025 Movatter.jp