Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs
Switch to: References

Add citations

You mustlogin to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)The philosophy of computer science.Raymond Turner -2013 -Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • On the philosophical relevance of Gödel's incompleteness theorems.Panu Raatikainen -2005 -Revue Internationale de Philosophie 59 (4):513-534.
  • How subtle is Gödel's theorem? More on Roger Penrose.Martin Davis -1993 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):611-612.
  • Provability logic.Rineke Verbrugge -2008 -Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    -/- Provability logic is a modal logic that is used to investigate what arithmetical theories can express in a restricted language about their provability predicates. The logic has been inspired by developments in meta-mathematics such as Gödel’s incompleteness theorems of 1931 and Löb’s theorem of 1953. As a modal logic, provability logic has been studied since the early seventies, and has had important applications in the foundations of mathematics. -/- From a philosophical point of view, provability logic is interesting because (...) the concept of provability in a fixed theory of arithmetic has a unique and non-problematic meaning, other than concepts like necessity and knowledge studied in modal and epistemic logic. Furthermore, provability logic provides tools to study the notion of self-reference. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Remarks on the Gödelian Anti-Mechanist Arguments.Panu Raatikainen -2020 -Studia Semiotyczne 34 (1):267–278.
    Certain selected issues around the Gödelian anti-mechanist arguments which have received less attention are discussed.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Problematic Nature of Gödel’s Disjunctions and Lucas-Penrose’s Theses.Arnon Avron -2020 -Studia Semiotyczne 34 (1):83-108.
    We show that the name “Lucas-Penrose thesis” encompasses several different theses. All these theses refer to extremely vague concepts, and so are either practically meaningless, or obviously false. The arguments for the various theses, in turn, are based on confusions with regard to the meaning of these vague notions, and on unjustified hidden assumptions concerning them. All these observations are true also for all interesting versions of the much weaker thesis known as “Gö- del disjunction”. Our main conclusions are that (...) pure mathematical theorems cannot decide alone any question which is not purely mathematical, and that an argument that cannot be fully formalized cannot be taken as a mathematical proof. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Mechanical intelligence and Godelian Arguments.Vincenzo Fano -2013 -Epistemologia 36 (2):207-232.
  • A Theorem about Computationalism and “Absolute” Truth.Arthur Charlesworth -2016 -Minds and Machines 26 (3):205-226.
    This article focuses on issues related to improving an argument about minds and machines given by Kurt Gödel in 1951, in a prominent lecture. Roughly, Gödel’s argument supported the conjecture that either the human mind is not algorithmic, or there is a particular arithmetical truth impossible for the human mind to master, or both. A well-known weakness in his argument is crucial reliance on the assumption that, if the deductive capability of the human mind is equivalent to that of a (...) formal system, then that system must be consistent. Such a consistency assumption is a strong infallibility assumption about human reasoning, since a formal system having even the slightest inconsistency allows deduction of all statements expressible within the formal system, including all falsehoods expressible within the system. We investigate how that weakness and some of the other problematic aspects of Gödel’s argument can be eliminated or reduced. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Quantum theory and consciousness.David L. Wilson -1993 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):615-616.
  • (1 other version)Mechanical intelligence and Godelian Arguments.Vincenzo Fano -2014 -Epistemologia 2:207-232.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mind the truth: Penrose's new step in the Gödelian argument.Salvatore Guccione -1993 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):612-613.
  • An emperor still without mind.Roger Penrose -1993 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):616-622.
  • The incompleteness of quantum physics.Euan J. Squires -1993 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):613-614.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognitive mapping and algorithmic complexity: Is there a role for quantum processes in the evolution of human consciousness?Ron Wallace -1993 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):614-615.
  • Turing Machines and Semantic Symbol Processing: Why Real Computers Don’t Mind Chinese Emperors.Richard Yee -1993 -Lyceum 5 (1):37-59.
    Philosophical questions about minds and computation need to focus squarely on the mathematical theory of Turing machines (TM's). Surrogate TM's such as computers or formal systems lack abilities that make Turing machines promising candidates for possessors of minds. Computers are only universal Turing machines (UTM's)—a conspicuous but unrepresentative subclass of TM. Formal systems are only static TM's, which do not receive inputs from external sources. The theory of TM computation clearly exposes the failings of two prominent critiques, Searle's Chinese room (...) (1980) and arguments from Gödel's Incompleteness theorems (e.g., Lucas, 1961; Penrose, 1989), both of which fall short of addressing the complete TM model. Both UTM-computers and formal systems provide an unsound basis for debate. In particular, their special natures easily foster the misconception that computation entails intrinsically meaningless symbol manipulation. This common view is incorrect with respect to full-fledged TM's, which can process inputs non-formally, i.e., in a subjective and dynamically evolving fashion. To avoid a distorted understanding of the theory of computation, philosophical judgments and discussions should be grounded firmly upon the complete Turing machine model, the proper model for real computers. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the necessary philosophical premises of the Goedelian arguments.Fano Vincenzo &Graziani Pierluigi -unknown
    Lucas-Penrose type arguments have been the focus of many papers in the literature. In the present paper we attempt to evaluate the consequences of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems for the philosophy of the mind. We argue that the best answer to this question was given by Gödel already in 1951 when he realized that either our intellectual capability is not representable by a Turing Machine, or we can never know with mathematical certainty what such a machine is. But his considerations became (...) known only in recent times when many scholars were already aware of Benacerraf’s and Chihara’s analyses on the consequences of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems for the philosophy of the mind. Benacerraf and Chihara, in fact, discussing Lucas’ paper, arrived at the same conclusions as Gödel in the sixties, but in a more formal way. After Penrose’s provocative arguments, Shapiro again shed light on the question. In our paper, after a broad and simple presentation of the contributions to the debate made by different authors, we show how to present Gödel’s argument in a rigorous way, highlighting the necessary philosophical premises of Gödel’s argument and more in general of Gödelian arguments. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  

  • [8]ページ先頭

    ©2009-2025 Movatter.jp