Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs
Switch to: References

Add citations

You mustlogin to add citations.
  1. Towards a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness: Basic evidence and a workspace framework.Stanislas Dehaene &Lionel Naccache -2001 -Cognition 79 (1):1-37.
    This introductory chapter attempts to clarify the philosophical, empirical, and theoretical bases on which a cognitive neuroscience approach to consciousness can be founded. We isolate three major empirical observations that any theory of consciousness should incorporate, namely (1) a considerable amount of processing is possible without consciousness, (2) attention is a prerequisite of consciousness, and (3) consciousness is required for some specific cognitive tasks, including those that require durable information maintenance, novel combinations of operations, or the spontaneous generation of intentional (...) behavior. We then propose a theoretical framework that synthesizes those facts: the hypothesis of a global neuronal workspace. This framework postulates that, at any given time, many modular cerebral networks are active in parallel and process information in an unconscious manner. An information becomes conscious, however, if the neural population that represents it is mobilized by top-down attentional amplification into a brain-scale state of coherent activity that involves many neurons distributed throughout the brain. The long-distance connectivity of these `workspace neurons' can, when they are active for a minimal duration, make the information available to a variety of processes including perceptual categorization, long-term memorization, evaluation, and intentional action. We postulate that this global availability of information through the workspace is what we subjectively experience as a conscious state. A complete theory of consciousness should explain why some cognitive and cerebral representations can be permanently or temporarily inaccessible to consciousness, what is the range of possible conscious contents, how they map onto specific cerebral circuits, and whether a generic neuronal mechanism underlies all of them. We confront the workspace model with those issues and identify novel experimental predictions. Neurophysiological, anatomical, and brain-imaging data strongly argue for a major role of prefrontal cortex, anterior cingulate, and the areas that connect to them, in creating the postulated brain-scale workspace. (shrink)
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   485 citations  
  • Border Disputes: Recent Debates along the Perception–Cognition Border.Sam Clarke &Jacob Beck -2023 -Philosophy Compass 18 (8):e12936.
    The distinction between perception and cognition frames countless debates in philosophy and cognitive science. But what, if anything, does this distinction actually amount to? In this introductory article, we summarize recent work on this question. We first briefly consider the possibility that a perception-cognition border should be eliminated from our scientific ontology, and then introduce and critically examine five positive approaches to marking a perception–cognition border, framed in terms of phenomenology, revisability, modularity, format, and stimulus-dependence.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Evolution, selection, and cognition: From learning to parameter setting in biology and in the study of language.Massimo Piattelli-Palmarini -1989 -Cognition 31 (1):1-44.
    Most biologists and some cognitive scientists have independently reached the conclusion that there is no such thing as learning in the traditional “instructive‘ sense. This is, admittedly, a somewhat extreme thesis, but I defend it herein the light of data and theories jointly extracted from biology, especially from evolutionary theory and immunology, and from modern generative grammar. I also point out that the general demise of learning is uncontroversial in the biological sciences, while a similar consensus has not yet been (...) reached in psychology and in linguistics at large. Since many arguments presently offered in defense of learning and in defense of “general intelligence‘ are often based on a distorted picture of human biological evolution, I devote some sections of this paper to a critique of “adaptationism,‘ providing also a sketch of a better evolutionary theory. Moreover, since certain standard arguments presented today as “knock-down‘ in psychology, in linguistics and in artificial intelligence are a perfect replica of those once voiced by biologists in favor of instruction and against selection, I capitalize on these errors of the past to draw some lessons for the present and for the future. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   241 citations  
  • The cognitive functions of language.Peter Carruthers -2002 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (6):657-674.
    This paper explores a variety of different versions of the thesis that natural language is involved in human thinking. It distinguishes amongst strong and weak forms of this thesis, dismissing some as implausibly strong and others as uninterestingly weak. Strong forms dismissed include the view that language is conceptually necessary for thought (endorsed by many philosophers) and the view that language is _de facto_ the medium of all human conceptual thinking (endorsed by many philosophers and social scientists). Weak forms include (...) the view that language is necessary for the acquisition of many human concepts, and the view that language can serve to scaffold human thought processes. The paper also discusses the thesis that language may be the medium of _conscious_ propositional thinking, but argues that this cannot be its most fundamental cognitive role. The idea is then proposed that natural language is the medium for non-domain-specific thinking, serving to integrate the outputs of a variety of domain-specific conceptual faculties (or central-cognitive ‘quasi-modules’). Recent experimental evidence in support of this idea is reviewed, and the implications of the idea are discussed, especially for our conception of the architecture of human cognition. Finally, some further kinds of evidence which might serve to corroborate or refute the hypothesis are mentioned. The overall goal of the paper is to review a wide variety of accounts of the cognitive function of natural language, integrating a number of different kinds of evidence and theoretical consideration in order to propose and elaborate the most plausible candidate. (shrink)
    Direct download(11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   159 citations  
  • Initial knowledge: six suggestions.Elizabeth Spelke -1994 -Cognition 50 (1-3):431-445.
    Although debates continue, studies of cognition in infancy suggest that knowledge begins to emerge early in life and constitutes part of humans' innate endowment. Early-developing knowledge appears to be both domain-specific and task-specific, it appears to capture fundamental constraints on ecologically important classes of entities in the child's environment, and it appears to remain central to the commonsense knowledge systems of adults.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   149 citations  
  • A neuronal model of a global workspace in effortful cognitive tasks.Stanislas Dehaene,Michel Kerszberg &Jean-Pierre Changeux -2001 -Pnas 95 (24):14529-14534.
  • Spatial memory: how egocentric and allocentric combine.Neil Burgess -2006 -Trends in Cognitive Sciences 10 (12):551-557.
  • Modularity and development: the case of spatial reorientation.Linda Hermer &Elizabeth Spelke -1996 -Cognition 61 (3):195-232.
  • Challenges for identifying the neural mechanisms that support spatial navigation: the impact of spatial scale.Thomas Wolbers &Jan M. Wiener -2014 -Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8.
  • Beyond natural geometry: on the nature of proto-geometry.José Ferreirós &Manuel J. García-Pérez -2020 -Philosophical Psychology 33 (2):181-205.
    ABSTRACTWe discuss the thesis of universality of geometric notions and offer critical reflections on the concept of “natural geometry” employed by Spelke and others. Promoting interdisciplinary wor...
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Why we can’t say what animals think.Jacob Beck -2013 -Philosophical Psychology 26 (4):520–546.
    Realists about animal cognition confront a puzzle. If animals have real, contentful cognitive states, why can’t anyone say precisely what the contents of those states are? I consider several possible resolutions to this puzzle that are open to realists, and argue that the best of these is likely to appeal to differences in the format of animal cognition and human language.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Language and number: a bilingual training study.Elizabeth S. Spelke -2001 -Cognition 78 (1):45-88.
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Beyond Core Knowledge: Natural Geometry.Elizabeth Spelke,Sang Ah Lee &Véronique Izard -2010 -Cognitive Science 34 (5):863-884.
    For many centuries, philosophers and scientists have pondered the origins and nature of human intuitions about the properties of points, lines, and figures on the Euclidean plane, with most hypothesizing that a system of Euclidean concepts either is innate or is assembled by general learning processes. Recent research from cognitive and developmental psychology, cognitive anthropology, animal cognition, and cognitive neuroscience suggests a different view. Knowledge of geometry may be founded on at least two distinct, evolutionarily ancient, core cognitive systems for (...) representing the shapes of large-scale, navigable surface layouts and of small-scale, movable forms and objects. Each of these systems applies to some but not all perceptible arrays and captures some but not all of the three fundamental Euclidean relationships of distance (or length), angle, and direction (or sense). Like natural number (Carey, 2009), Euclidean geometry may be constructed through the productive combination of representations from these core systems, through the use of uniquely human symbolic systems. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • (1 other version)Contemporary debates in philosophy of science.Christopher Hitchcock (ed.) -2004 - Malden, MA: Blackwell.
    Showcasing original arguments for well-defined positions, as well as clear and concise statements of sophisticated philosophical views, this volume is an ...
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Real space and represented space: Cross-cultural perspectives.J. B. Deregowski -1989 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):51-74.
  • The distinction between object recognition and picture recognition.Hadyn D. Ellis -1989 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):81-82.
  • Navigation as a source of geometric knowledge: Young children’s use of length, angle, distance, and direction in a reorientation task.Sang Ah Lee,Valeria A. Sovrano &Elizabeth S. Spelke -2012 -Cognition 123 (1):144-161.
  • Orientational manoeuvres in the dark: dissociating allocentric and egocentric influences on spatial memory.N. Burgess,H. Spiers &E. PalEologou -2004 -Cognition 94 (2):149-166.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Précis ofWhat Babies Know.Elizabeth S. Spelke -2024 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 47:e120.
    Where does human knowledge begin? Research on human infants, children, adults, and nonhuman animals, using diverse methods from the cognitive, brain, and computational sciences, provides evidence for six early emerging, domain-specific systems of core knowledge. These automatic, unconscious systems are situated between perceptual systems and systems of explicit concepts and beliefs. They emerge early in infancy, guide children's learning, and function throughout life.
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Alternative representations of time, number, and rate.Russell M. Church &Hilary A. Broadbent -1990 -Cognition 37 (1-2):55-81.
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Simple heuristics meet massive modularity.Peter Carruthers -2005 - In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Laurence & Stephen P. Stich,The Innate Mind: Structure and Contents. New York, US: Oxford University Press on Demand.
    This chapter investigates the extent to which claims of massive modular organization of the mind (espoused by some members of the evolutionary psychology research program) are consistent with the main elements of the simple heuristics research program. A number of potential sources of conflict between the two programs are investigated and defused. However, the simple heuristics program turns out to undermine one of the main arguments offered in support of massive modularity, at least as the latter is generally understood by (...) philosophers. So one result of the argument will be to force us to re-examine the way in which the notion of modularity in cognitive science should best be characterized, if the thesis of massive modularity isn’t to be abandoned altogether. What is at stake in this discussion, is whether there is a well-motivated notion of ‘module’ such that we have good reason to think that the human mind must be massively modular in its organization. I shall be arguing (in the end) that there is. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Rhesus monkeys use geometric and nongeometric information during a reorientation task.S. Gouteux,C. Thinus-Blanc &J. Vauclair -2001 -Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 130 (3):505.
  • Memory and content.Gottfried Vosgerau -2010 -Consciousness and Cognition 19 (3):838-846.
  • Cognitive Artifacts for Geometric Reasoning.Mateusz Hohol &Marcin Miłkowski -2019 -Foundations of Science 24 (4):657-680.
    In this paper, we focus on the development of geometric cognition. We argue that to understand how geometric cognition has been constituted, one must appreciate not only individual cognitive factors, such as phylogenetically ancient and ontogenetically early core cognitive systems, but also the social history of the spread and use of cognitive artifacts. In particular, we show that the development of Greek mathematics, enshrined in Euclid’s Elements, was driven by the use of two tightly intertwined cognitive artifacts: the use of (...) lettered diagrams; and the creation of linguistic formulae. Together, these artifacts formed the professional language of geometry. In this respect, the case of Greek geometry clearly shows that explanations of geometric reasoning have to go beyond the confines of methodological individualism to account for how the distributed practice of artifact use has stabilized over time. This practice, as we suggest, has also contributed heavily to the understanding of what mathematical proof is; classically, it has been assumed that proofs are not merely deductively correct but also remain invariant over various individuals sharing the same cognitive practice. Cognitive artifacts in Greek geometry constrained the repertoire of admissible inferential operations, which made these proofs inter-subjectively testable and compelling. By focusing on the cognitive operations on artifacts, we also stress that mental mechanisms that contribute to these operations are still poorly understood, in contrast to those mechanisms which drive symbolic logical inference. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Representations in animal cognition: An introduction.C. R. Gallistel -1990 -Cognition 37 (1-2):1-22.
  • Language and the development of spatial reasoning.Anna Shusterman &E. S. Spelke -2005 - In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Laurence & Stephen P. Stich,The Innate Mind: Structure and Contents. New York, US: Oxford University Press on Demand. pp. 89--106.
    This chapter argues that human and animal minds indeed depend on a collection of domain-specific, task-specific, and encapsulated cognitive systems: on a set of cognitive ‘modules’ in Fodor's sense. It also argues that human and animal minds are endowed with domain-general, central systems that orchestrate the information delivered by core knowledge systems. The chapter begins by reviewing the literature on spatial reorientation in animals and in young children, arguing that spatial reorientation bears the hallmarks of core knowledge and of modularity. (...) It then considers studies of older children and adults, arguing that human spatial representations change qualitatively over development and show capacities not found in any other species. Finally, it presents two new experiments that investigate the role of emerging spatial language in uniquely human navigation performance. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Spatial Concepts and Rodent Maze Studies.Jordan Dopkins -forthcoming -Philosophical Psychology.
    Researchers working on rodent in maze studies claim that organisms use distal (far) and proximal (near) visual cues differently. I characterize the dominant working definitions researchers use for distal and proximal cues, where distal cues sit beyond an experimental apparatus (like a maze) and proximal cues sit within. Then, I present a problem: the relevant experimental apparatuses are confined to labs and cannot be used to study real-life navigation behaviors like long-distance migration. It follows that the working definitions do not (...) identify difference makers beyond those settings and do not allow for claims about distal and proximal cues to play explanatory or predictive roles for real-life navigation. Despite this, I argue that researchers should continue to treat these as working definitions for concepts that work more generally in natural environments. This calls for some conceptual engineering however, since the more generally useful concepts of “proximal” and “distal” are not well-defined. To remedy this, I present more general, ecologically valid definitions in terms of neural information about visual cues. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Five Reasons to Doubt the Existence of a Geometric Module.Alexandra D. Twyman &Nora S. Newcombe -2010 -Cognitive Science 34 (7):1315-1356.
    It is frequently claimed that the human mind is organized in a modular fashion, a hypothesis linked historically, though not inevitably, to the claim that many aspects of the human mind are innately specified. A specific instance of this line of thought is the proposal of an innately specified geometric module for human reorientation. From a massive modularity position, the reorientation module would be one of a large number that organized the mind. From the core knowledge position, the reorientation module (...) is one of five innate and encapsulated modules that can later be supplemented by use of human language. In this paper, we marshall five lines of evidence that cast doubt on the geometric module hypothesis, unfolded in a series of reasons: (1) Language does not play a necessary role in the integration of feature and geometric cues, although it can be helpful. (2) A model of reorientation requires flexibility to explain variable phenomena. (3) Experience matters over short and long periods. (4) Features are used for true reorientation. (5) The nature of geometric information is not as yet clearly specified. In the final section, we review recent theoretical approaches to the known reorientation phenomena. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Modularity and spatial reorientation in a simple mind: encoding of geometric and nongeometric properties of a spatial environment by fish.Valeria Anna Sovrano,Angelo Bisazza &Giorgio Vallortigara -2002 -Cognition 85 (2):B51-B59.
  • Meaning, Concepts, and the Lexicon.Michael Glanzberg -2011 -Croatian Journal of Philosophy 11 (1):1-29.
    This paper explores how words relate to concepts. It argues that in many cases, words get their meanings in part by associating with concepts, but only in conjunction with substantial input from language. Language packages concepts in grammatically determined ways. This structures the meanings of words, and determines which sorts of concepts map to words. The results are linguistically modulated meanings, and the extralinguistic concepts associated with words are often not what intuitively would be expected. The paper concludes by discussing (...) implications of this thesis for the relation of word to sentence meaning, and for issues of linguistic determinism. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Children's use of geometry and landmarks to reorient in an open space.Stéphane Gouteux &Elizabeth S. Spelke -2001 -Cognition 81 (2):119-148.
    No categories
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Schematic representations of local environmental space guide goal-directed navigation.Steven A. Marchette,Jack Ryan &Russell A. Epstein -2017 -Cognition 158 (C):68-80.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • In defense of language-independent flexibility, or: What rodents and humans can do without language.Alexandre Duval -2025 -Mind and Language 40 (1):93-119.
    There are two main approaches within classical cognitive science to explaining how humans can entertain mental states that integrate contents across domains. The language-based framework states that this ability arises from higher cognitive domain-specific systems that combine their outputs through the language faculty, whereas the language-independent framework holds that it comes from non-language-involving connections between such systems. This article turns on its head the most influential empirical argument for the language-based framework, an argument that originates from research on spatial reorientation. (...) I make the case that neuroscientific findings about spatial reorientation in rodents and humans bolster the language-independent framework instead. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The representation selection problem: Why we should favor the geometric-module framework of spatial reorientation over the view-matching framework.Alexandre Duval -2019 -Cognition 192 (C):103985.
    Many species rely on the three-dimensional surface layout of an environment to find a desired goal following disorientation. They generally do so to the exclusion of other important spatial cues. Two influential frameworks for explaining that phenomenon are provided by geometric-module theories and view-matching theories of reorientation respectively. The former posit a module that operates only on representations of the global geo- metry of three-dimensional surfaces to guide behavior. The latter place snapshots, stored representations of the subject’s two-dimensional retinal stimulation (...) at specific locations, at the heart of their accounts. In this paper, I take a fresh look at the debate between them. I begin by making a case that the empirical evidence we currently have does not clearly favor one framework over the other, and that the debate has reached something of an impasse. Then, I present a new explanatory problem—the representation selection problem—that offers the pro- spect of breaking the impasse by introducing a new type of explanatory consideration that both frameworks must address. The representation selection problem requires explaining how subjects can reliably select the relevant representation with which they initiate the reorientation process. I argue that the view-matching framework does not have the resources to address this problem, while a certain type of theory within the geometric-module framework can provide a natural response to it. In showing this, I develop a new geometric-module theory. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Working Memory in Wayfinding—A Dual Task Experiment in a Virtual City.Tobias Meilinger,Markus Knauff &Heinrich H. Bülthoff -2008 -Cognitive Science 32 (4):755-770.
    This study examines the working memory systems involved in human wayfinding. In the learning phase, 24 participants learned two routes in a novel photorealistic virtual environment displayed on a 220° screen while they were disrupted by a visual, a spatial, a verbal, or—in a control group—no secondary task. In the following wayfinding phase, the participants had to find and to “virtually walk” the two routes again. During this wayfinding phase, a number of dependent measures were recorded. This research shows that (...) encoding wayfinding knowledge interfered with the verbal and with the spatial secondary task. These interferences were even stronger than the interference of wayfinding knowledge with the visual secondary task. These findings are consistent with a dual‐coding approach of wayfinding knowledge. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Geometric determinants of human spatial memory.Tom Hartley,Iris Trinkler &Neil Burgess -2004 -Cognition 94 (1):39-75.
  • The shape of human navigation: How environmental geometry is used in maintenance of spatial orientation.Jonathan W. Kelly,Timothy P. McNamara,Bobby Bodenheimer,Thomas H. Carr &John J. Rieser -2008 -Cognition 109 (2):281-286.
    No categories
    Direct download(11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • A viewpoint-independent process for spatial reorientation.Marko Nardini,Rhiannon L. Thomas,Victoria C. P. Knowland,Oliver J. Braddick &Janette Atkinson -2009 -Cognition 112 (2):241-248.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Consciousness, art, and the brain: Lessons from Marcel Proust.Russell Epstein -2004 -Consciousness and Cognition 13 (2):213-40.
    In his novel Remembrance of Things Past, Marcel Proust argues that conventional descriptions of the phenomenology of consciousness are incomplete because they focus too much on the highly-salient sensory information that dominates each moment of awareness and ignore the network of associations that lies in the background. In this paper, I explicate Proust’s theory of conscious experience and show how it leads him directly to a theory of aesthetic perception. Proust’s division of awareness into two components roughly corresponds to William (...) James’ division of the stream of thought into a “nucleus” and “fringe.” Proust argues that the function of art is to evoke the underlying associative network indirectly in the mind of the observer by using carefully chosen sensory surfaces to control the stream of thought. I propose a possible neural basis for this Proustian/Jamesian phenomenology, and argue that the general principles of Proustian aesthetics can be applied to all forms of art. I conclude that a scientific theory of art should follow in a straightforward manner from a scientific theory of consciousness. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Children reorient using the left/right sense of coloured landmarks at 18–24 months.Marko Nardini,Janette Atkinson &Neil Burgess -2008 -Cognition 106 (1):519-527.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Wherein is Human Cognition Systematic?Antoni Gomila,David Travieso &Lorena Lobo -2012 -Minds and Machines 22 (2):101-115.
    The “systematicity argument” has been used to argue for a classical cognitive architecture (Fodor in The Language of Thought. Harvester Press, London, 1975, Why there still has to be a language of thought? In Psychosemantics, appendix. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 135–154, 1987; Fodor and Pylyshyn in Cognition 28:3–71, 1988; Aizawa in The systematicity arguments. Kluwer Academic Press, Dordrecht, 2003). From the premises that cognition is systematic and that the best/only explanation of systematicity is compositional structure, it concludes that cognition is (...) to be explained in terms of symbols (in a language of thought) and formal rules. The debate, with connectionism, has mostly centered on the second premise-whether an explanation of systematicity requires compositional structure, which neural networks do not to exhibit (for example, Hadley and Hayward, in Minds and Machines, 7:1–37). In this paper, I will take issue with the first premise. Several arguments will be deployed that show that cognition is not systematic in general; that, in fact, systematicity seems to be related to language. I will argue that it is just verbal minds that are systematic, and they are so because of the structuring role of language in cognition. A dual-process theory of cognition will be defended as the best explanation of the facts. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Distinctively human thinking: Modular precursors and components.Peter Carruthers -2005 - In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Laurence & Stephen P. Stich,The Innate Mind: Structure and Contents. New York, US: Oxford University Press on Demand. pp. 69--88.
    This chapter addresses the main challenge facing massively modular theories of the architecture of the human mind. This is to account for the distinctively flexible, non-domain-specific character of much human thinking. It shows how the appearance of a modular language faculty within an evolving modular architecture might have led to these distinctive features of human thinking with only minor further additions and non-domain-specific adaptations.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • What are modules and what is their role in development?Stephen Andrew Butterfill -2007 -Mind and Language 22 (4):450–473.
    Modules are widely held to play a central role in explaining mental development and in accounts of the mind generally. But there is much disagreement about what modules are, which shows that we do not adequately understand modularity. This paper outlines a Fodoresque approach to understanding one type of modularity. It suggests that we can distinguish modular from nonmodular cognition by reference to the kinds of process involved, and that modular cognition differs from nonmodular forms of cognition in being a (...) special kind of computational process. The paper concludes by considering implications for the role of modules in explaining mental development. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Is there a geometric module for spatial orientation? Insights from a rodent navigation model.Denis Sheynikhovich,Ricardo Chavarriaga,Thomas Strösslin,Angelo Arleo &Wulfram Gerstner -2009 -Psychological Review 116 (3):540-566.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Contracted time and expanded space: The impact of circumnavigation on judgements of space and time.Iva K. Brunec,Amir-Homayoun Javadi,Fiona E. L. Zisch &Hugo J. Spiers -2017 -Cognition 166 (C):425-432.
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Spatial cognition and the avian hippocampus: Research in domestic chicks.Anastasia Morandi-Raikova &Uwe Mayer -2022 -Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    In this review, we discuss the functional equivalence of the avian and mammalian hippocampus, based mostly on our own research in domestic chicks, which provide an important developmental model. In birds, like in mammals, the hippocampus plays a central role in processing spatial information. However, the structure of this homolog area shows remarkable differences between birds and mammals. To understand the evolutionary origin of the neural mechanisms for spatial navigation, it is important to test how far theories developed for the (...) mammalian hippocampus can also be applied to the avian hippocampal formation. To address this issue, we present a brief overview of studies carried out in domestic chicks, investigating the direct involvement of chicks’ hippocampus homolog in spatial navigation. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The hippocampus is not a geometric module: processing environment geometry during reorientation.Jennifer E. Sutton &Nora S. Newcombe -2014 -Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8.
  • Constructions and Grammatical Explanation: Comments on Goldberg.David Adger -2013 -Mind and Language 28 (4):466-478.
  • Animals' use of landmarks and metric information to reorient: effects of the size of the experimental space.Valeria Anna Sovrano,Angelo Bisazza &Giorgio Vallortigara -2005 -Cognition 97 (2):121-133.
  • How do young children determine location? Evidence from disorientation tasks.Stella F. Lourenco &Janellen Huttenlocher -2006 -Cognition 100 (3):511-529.

  • [8]ページ先頭

    ©2009-2025 Movatter.jp