Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs
Switch to: References

Add citations

You mustlogin to add citations.
  1. Ways of coloring: Comparative color vision as a case study for cognitive science.Evan Thompson,Adrian Palacios &Francisco J. Varela -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):1-26.
  • A dynamical systems perspective on agent-environment interaction.Randall D. Beer -1995 -Artificial Intelligence 72 (1-2):173-215.
  • Implications of Action-Oriented Paradigm Shifts in Cognitive Science.Peter F. Dominey,Tony J. Prescott,Jeannette Bohg,Andreas K. Engel,Shaun Gallagher,Tobias Heed,Matej Hoffmann,Gunther Knoblich,Wolfgang Prinz &Andrew Schwartz -2016 - In Andreas K. Engel, Karl J. Friston & Danica Kragic,The Pragmatic Turn: Toward Action-Oriented Views in Cognitive Science. MIT Press. pp. 333-356.
    An action-oriented perspective changes the role of an individual from a passive observer to an actively engaged agent interacting in a closed loop with the world as well as with others. Cognition exists to serve action within a landscape that contains both. This chapter surveys this landscape and addresses the status of the pragmatic turn. Its potential influence on science and the study of cognition are considered (including perception, social cognition, social interaction, sensorimotor entrainment, and language acquisition) and its impact (...) on how neuroscience is studied is also investigated (with the notion that brains do not passively build models, but instead support the guidance of action). A review of its implications in robotics and engineering includes a discussion of the application of enactive control principles to couple action and perception in robotics as well as the conceptualization of system design in a more holistic, less modular manner. Practical applications that can impact the human condition are reviewed (e.g., educational applications, treatment possibilities for developmental and psychopathological disorders, the development of neural prostheses). All of this foreshadows the potential societal implications of the pragmatic turn. The chapter concludes that an action-oriented approach emphasizes a continuum of interaction between technical aspects of cognitive systems and robotics, biology, psychology, the social sciences, and the humanities, where the individual is part of a grounded cultural system. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Enactivist vision.Jerome A. Feldman -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):35-36.
  • Conclusions from color vision of insects.Werner Backhaus &Randolf Menzel -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):28-30.
  • Color vision: Content versus experience.Mohan Matthen -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):46-47.
  • Objectivism-subjectivim: A false dilemma?Joseph Levine -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):42-43.
  • Nonreductionism, content and evolutionary explanation.Justin Broackes -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):31-32.
  • Language as a dynamical system.Jeffrey L. Elman -1995 - In Tim van Gelder & Robert Port,Mind As Motion: Explorations in the Dynamics of Cognition. MIT Press. pp. 195--223.
  • Doing without representations which specify what to do.Fred A. Keijzer -1998 -Philosophical Psychology 11 (3):269-302.
    A discussion is going on in cognitive science about the use of representations to explain how intelligent behavior is generated. In the traditional view, an organism is thought to incorporate representations. These provide an internal model that is used by the organism to instruct the motor apparatus so that the adaptive and anticipatory characteristics of behavior come about. So-called interactionists claim that this representational specification of behavior raises more problems than it solves. In their view, the notion of internal representational (...) models is to be dispensed with. Instead, behavior is to be explained as the intricate interaction between an embodied organism and the specific make up of an environment. The problem with a non-representational interactive account is that it has severe difficulties with anticipatory, future oriented behavior. The present paper extends the interactionist conceptual framework by drawing on ideas derived from the study of morphogenesis. This extended interactionist framework is based on an analysis of anticipatory behavior as a process which involves multiple spatio-temporal scales of neural, bodily and environmental dynamics. This extended conceptual framework provides the outlines for an explanation of anticipatory behavior without involving a representational specification of future goal states. (shrink)
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Artificial life: organization, adaptation and complexity from the bottom up.Mark A. Bedau -2003 -Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7 (11):505-512.
  • An Embodied Approach to Understanding: Making Sense of the World Through Simulated Bodily Activity.Firat Soylu -2016 -Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • From Alan Turing to modern AI: practical solutions and an implicit epistemic stance.George F. Luger &Chayan Chakrabarti -2017 -AI and Society 32 (3):321-338.
    It has been just over 100 years since the birth of Alan Turing and more than 65 years since he published in Mind his seminal paper, Computing Machinery and Intelligence. In the Mind paper, Turing asked a number of questions, including whether computers could ever be said to have the power of “thinking”. Turing also set up a number of criteria—including his imitation game—under which a human could judge whether a computer could be said to be “intelligent”. Turing’s paper, as (...) well as his important mathematical and computational insights of the 1930s and 1940s led to his popular acclaim as the “Father of Artificial Intelligence”. In the years since his paper was published, however, no computational system has fully satisfied Turing’s challenge. In this paper we focus on a different question, ignored in, but inspired by Turing’s work: How might the Artificial Intelligence practitioner implement “intelligence” on a computational device? Over the past 60 years, although the AI community has not produced a general-purpose computational intelligence, it has constructed a large number of important artifacts, as well as taken several philosophical stances able to shed light on the nature and implementation of intelligence. This paper contends that the construction of any human artifact includes an implicit epistemic stance. In AI this stance is found in commitments to particular knowledge representations and search strategies that lead to a product’s successes as well as its limitations. Finally, we suggest that computational and human intelligence are two different natural kinds, in the philosophical sense, and elaborate on this point in the conclusion. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Language and Reality.Menno Lievers -2021 - InSecond Thoughts. Tilburg, Netherlands: pp. 261-277.
    An introduction to philosophy of language since Frege, focusing on the 20th century.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • For a contextualist and content-related understanding of the difference between human and artificial intelligence.Veronica Cibotaru -2024 -Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences (5):1053-1071.
    The development of artificial intelligence necessarily implies the anthropological question of the difference between human and artificial intelligence for two reasons: on the one hand artificial intelligence tends to be conceived on the model of human intelligence, on the other hand, a large part of types of artificial intelligence are designed in order to exhibit at least some features of what is conceived as being human intelligence. In this article I address this anthropological question in two parts. First I bring (...) into review and classify some of the main answers that have been proposed until now to this question. I argue that these variety of answers can be broadly classified in three categories, namely a (1) behaviorist, (2) a representational, and (3) a holistic understanding of human intelligence. In a second moment I propose an alternative way of understanding the difference between human and artificial intelligence, which is not essentialist but contextualist and content-related. Contrary to possible answers that I analyse in the first section, this alternative model does not aim at grasping the essence of human intelligence, which could or could not be reproduced in principle by artificial intelligence. It situates rather the fundamental differences between human and artificial intelligence in the context of human existence and the conceptual content of human intelligence, following the phenomenological description of one of its most fundamental features, namely its life-world. Grounding on this approach, it is possible to argue that human and artificial intelligence could be distinct, even if one could prove that they are eidetically, i.e. by their essence, identical. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Building brains for bodies.Rodney A. Brooks &Lynn Andrea Stein -1994 -Autonomous Robotics 1 (1):7-25.
    We describe a project to capitalize on newly available levels of computational resources in order to understand human cognition. We are building an integrated physical system including vision, sound input and output, and dextrous manipulation, all controlled by a continuously operating large scale parallel MIMD computer. The resulting system will learn to "think" by building on its bodily experiences to accomplish progressively more abstract tasks. Past experience suggests that in attempting to build such an integrated system we will have to (...) fundamentally change the way artificial intelligence, cognitive science, linguistics, and philosophy think about the organization of intelligence. We expect to be able to better reconcile the theories that will be developed with current work in neuroscience. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Hitting the nail on the head.Daniel C. Dennett -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):35-35.
    No categories
    Direct download(6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On possible perceptual worlds and how they shape their environments.Rainer J. Mausfeld,Reinhard M. Niederée &K. Dieter Heyer -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):47-48.
  • The ethnocentricity of colour.J. van Brakel -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):53-54.
  • On the ways to color.Evan Thompson,Adrian Palacios &Francisco J. Varela -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):56-74.
  • Comparative color vision and the objectivity of color.David Hilbert -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):38-39.
  • Robots as Powerful Allies for the Study of Embodied Cognition from the Bottom Up.Matej Hoffmann &Rolf Pfeifer -2018 - In Albert Newen, Leon De Bruin & Shaun Gallagher,The Oxford Handbook of 4E Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    A large body of compelling evidence has been accumulated demonstrating that embodiment – the agent’s physical setup, including its shape, materials, sensors and actuators – is constitutive for any form of cognition and as a consequence, models of cognition need to be embodied. In contrast to methods from empirical sciences to study cognition, robots can be freely manipulated and virtually all key variables of their embodiment and control programs can be systematically varied. As such, they provide an extremely powerful tool (...) of investigation. We present a robotic bottom-up or developmental approach, focusing on three stages: (a) low-level behaviors like walking and reflexes, (b) learning regularities in sensorimotor spaces, and (c) human-like cognition. We also show that robotic based research is not only a productive path to deepening our understanding of cognition, but that robots can strongly benefit from human-like cognition in order to become more autonomous, robust, resilient, and safe. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • More than mere coloring: The art of spectral vision.Kathleen A. Akins &John Lamping -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):26-27.
  • A limited objectivism defended.Edward Wilson Averill -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):27-28.
  • Problems with explaining the perceptual environment.Aaron Ben-Ze'ev -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):30-31.
  • Fast, Cheap & Out of Control.Rodney A. Brooks -1999 - Sony Pictures Classics Weta-Tv.
    Complex systems and complex missions take years of planning and force launches to become incredibly expensive. The longer the planning and the more expensive the mission, the more catastrophic if it fails. The solution has always been to plan better, add redundancy, test thoroughly and use high quality components. Based on our experience in building ground based mobile robots (legged and wheeled) we argue here for cheap, fast missions using large numbers of mass produced simple autonomous robots that are small (...) b y today's standards (1 to 2 Kg). We argue that the time between mission conception and implementation can be radically reduced, that launch mass can be slashed, that totally autonomous robots can be more reliable than ground controlled robots, and that large numbers of robots can change the tradeoff between reliability of individual components and overall mission success. Lastly, we suggest that within a few years it will be possible at modest cost to invade a planet with millions of tiny robots. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reductionism and subjectivism defined and defended.Austen Clark -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):32-33.
  • Color is as color does.James L. Dannemiller -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):33-34.
  • What is a colour space?Jules Davidoff -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):34-35.
  • Psychophysical modeling: The link between objectivism and subjectivism.Marcia A. Finkelstein -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):36-37.
  • Multivariant color vision.Peter Gouras -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):37-37.
  • Color for pigeons and philosophers.C. L. Hardin -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):37-38.
  • The view of a computational animal.Anya Hurlbert -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):39-40.
  • Data and interpretation in comparative color vision.Gerald H. Jacobs -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):40-41.
  • Color enactivism: A return to Kant?Paul R. Kinnear -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):41-41.
  • Ethological and ecological aspects of color vision.Sergei L. Kondrashev -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):42-42.
  • Ontogeny and ontology: Ontophyletics and enactive focal vision.Barry Lia -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):43-44.
  • Herbert L. roitbiat and Jean-Arcady Meyer, eds., Comparative approaches to cognitive science.Lewis A. Loren -2000 -Minds and Machines 10 (3):401-409.
  • In search of common features of animals' color vision systems and the constraints of environment.Erhard Maier &Dietrich Burkhardt -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):44-45.
  • A mathematical framework for biological color vision.Laurence T. Maloney -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):45-46.
  • Colors really are only in the head.James A. McGilvray -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):48-49.
  • On perceived colors.Christa Neumeyer -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):49-49.
  • Areas of ignorance and confusion in color science.Adam Reeves -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):49-50.
  • What in the world determines the structure of color space?Roger N. Shepard -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):50-51.
  • Ecological subjectivism?Christine A. Skarda -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):51-52.
  • Confusing structure and function.Kenneth M. Steele -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):52-53.
  • Wavelength processing and colour experience.Petra Stoerig &Alan Cowey -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):53-53.
  • Ways of coloring the ecological approach.Johan Wagemans &Charles M. M. de Weert -1992 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):54-56.
  • Emergent functionality among intelligent systems: Cooperation within and without minds. [REVIEW]Cristiano Castelfranchi &Rosaria Conte -1992 -AI and Society 6 (1):78-87.
    In this paper, the current AI view that emergent functionalities apply only to the study of subcognitive agents is questioned; a hypercognitive view of autonomous agents as proposed in some AI subareas is also rejected. As an alternative view, a unified theory of social interaction is proposed which allows for the consideration of both cognitive and extracognitive social relations. A notion of functional effect is proposed, and the application of a formal model of cooperation is illustrated. Functional cooperation shows the (...) role of extracognitive phenomena in the interaction of intelligent agents, thus representing a typical example of emergent functionality. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  

  • [8]ページ先頭

    ©2009-2025 Movatter.jp