Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


PhilPapersPhilPeoplePhilArchivePhilEventsPhilJobs
Switch to: References

Add citations

You mustlogin to add citations.
  1. Reintroducing group selection to the human behavioral sciences.David Sloan Wilson &Elliott Sober -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):585-608.
    In both biology and the human sciences, social groups are sometimes treated as adaptive units whose organization cannot be reduced to individual interactions. This group-level view is opposed by a more individualistic one that treats social organization as a byproduct of self-interest. According to biologists, group-level adaptations can evolve only by a process of natural selection at the group level. Most biologists rejected group selection as an important evolutionary force during the 1960s and 1970s but a positive literature began to (...) grow during the 1970s and is rapidly expanding today. We review this recent literature and its implications for human evolutionary biology. We show that the rejection of group selection was based on a misplaced emphasis on genes as “replicators” which is in fact irrelevant to the question of whether groups can be like individuals in their functional organization. The fundamental question is whether social groups and other higher-level entities can be “vehicles” of selection. When this elementary fact is recognized, group selection emerges as an important force in nature and what seem to be competing theories, such as kin selection and reciprocity, reappear as special cases of group selection. The result is a unified theory of natural selection that operates on a nested hierarchy of units.The vehicle-based theory makes it clear that group selection is an important force to consider in human evolution. Humans can facultatively span the full range from self-interested individuals to “organs” of group-level “organisms.” Human behavior not only reflects the balance between levels of selection but it can also alter the balance through the construction of social structures that have the effect of reducing fitness differences within groups, concentrating natural selection (and functional organization) at the group level. These social structures and the cognitive abilities that produce them allow group selection to be important even among large groups of unrelated individuals. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   139 citations  
  • How did morality evolve?William Irons -1991 -Zygon 26 (1):49-89.
    This paper presents and criticizes. Alexander's evolutionary theory of morality (1987). Earlier research, on which Alexander's theory is based, is also reviewed. The propensity to create moral systems evolved because it allowed ancestral humans to limit conflict within cooperating groups and thus form larger groups, which were advantageous because of intense between-group competition. Alexander sees moral codes as contractual, and the primary criticism of his theory is that moral codes are not completely contractual but also coercive. Ways of evaluating Alexander's (...) theory as well as modified versions of it are discussed. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • Evolutionary theories of morality and the manipulative use of signals.Lee Cronk1 -1994 -Zygon 29 (1):81-101.
    Several attempts have recently been made to explain moral systems and moral sentiments in light of evolutionary biological theory. It may be helpful to modify and extend this project with the help of a theory of communication developed by ethologists. The core of this approach is the idea that signals are best seen as attempts to manipulate others rather than as attempts to inform them. This addition helps to clarify some problematic areas in the evolutionary study of morals, and it (...) generates new, testable predictions about moral statements. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Burying the vehicle.Richard Dawkins -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):616-617.
  • The Rediscovery of Common Sense Philosophy.Stephen Boulter -2007 - Basingstoke, England: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    This book is a defence of the philosophy of common sense in the spirit of Thomas Reid and G.E. Moore, drawing on the work of Aristotle, evolutionary biology and psychology, and historical studies on the origins of early modern philosophy. It defines and explores common sense beliefs, and defends them from challenges from prominent philosophers.
    No categories
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Why is group selection such a problem?Randolph M. Nesse -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):633-634.
  • Adaptation and natural selection: A new look at some old ideas.Jeffry A. Simpson -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):634-636.
  • Group evolutionary strategies: Dimensions and mechanisms.Kevin MacDonald -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):629-630.
  • Beyond shared fate: Group-selected mechanisms for cooperation and competition in fuzzy, fluid vehicles.Geoffrey F. Miller -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):630-631.
  • Hominids, coalitions, and weapons: Not vehicles.Jim Moore -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):632-632.
  • Replicators and vehicles? Or developmental systems?P. E. Griffiths &R. D. Gray -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):623-624.
  • Evolutionary Ethics and Mate Selection.Harriet Muus -manuscript
    Moral philosophers argue that mechanisms such as reciprocal altruism and indirect reciprocity can result in the evolution of shared interests and a ‘moral sense’ in humans. This article discusses the need to broaden that view when considering the consequences of genetic conflict, in particular, the conflict associated with mate selection. An alternative application of evolutionary arguments to morality has been suggested by biologists such as Richard Alexander, who argue that ethical, moral and legal questions arise purely out of conflicts of (...) interest, and that moral systems (consisting of societal rules or laws) exist to ameliorate those conflicts. Following Alexander, a novel societal rule is proposed that could lessen the negative consequences to men of reproductive conflicts with women. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Limits of Our Explanation: A Case Study in Myxococcus xanthus Cooperation.Saira Khan -2025 -Biological Theory 20 (1):25-40.
    In this article, I demonstrate two ways in which our major theories of the evolution of cooperation may fail to capture particular social phenomena. The first shortcoming of our current major theories stems from the possibility of mischaracterizing the cooperative problem in game theory. The second shortcoming of our current major theories is the insensitivity of these explanatory models to ecological and genomic context. As a case study to illustrate these points, I will use the cooperative interaction of a species (...) of myxobacteria called Myxococcus xanthus. M. xanthus cooperate in many areas of their life cycle—in quorum sensing, social motility, fruiting body formation, and predation. I focus in particular on predation as we have not yet discovered an adequate explanation of how they sustain cooperative predation in the face of developmental cheats. In explaining why we have not, I draw generalizable conclusions that shed light on our use of simplified models to explain real-world behaviors in a variety of organisms. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • En busca del origen evolutivo de la moralidad: el cerebro social y la empatía.Augusto Montiel-Castro &Jorge Martínez-Contreras -2012 -Signos Filosóficos 14 (28):31-56.
    La evidencia comparativa reciente sugiere que algunas especies no humanas sienten empatía hacia otros congéneres, la cual es una capacidad necesaria para la presencia y evolución de la moralidad. Por otro lado, la Hipótesis del Cerebro Social plantea relaciones entre la evolución de la neocorteza cerebral en primates y el tamaño de sus grupos sociales. Este artículo vincula estas ideas al señalar que: (i) la empatía y la moralidad son subproductos de la expansión de la neocorteza cerebral, y (ii) la (...) función de tales capacidades es facilitar la cooperación entre individuos, aumentando su cohesión social. Recent comparative evidence suggests that some nonhuman species feel empathy towards fellow group members and empathy is a necessary capacity for the presence and evolution of morality. On the other hand, the Social Brain Hypothesis suggests relationships between the evolution of brain's neocortex in primates and the size of their social groups. This paper links these ideas by suggesting that (i) empathy and morality are by-products of the expansión of brain's neocortex, and that (ii) the function of such capacities is to facilitate cooperation between individuals, increasing their social cohesion. (shrink)
    Direct download(5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Taking vechicles seriously.David L. Hull -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):627-628.
  • E pluribus unum?Daniel C. Dennett -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):617-618.
    W&S correctly ask if groups can be like individuals in the harmony and cooperation of their parts, but in their answer, they ignore the importance of the difference between genetically related and unrelated components, and also misconstrue the import of the Hutterites.
    No categories
    Direct download(7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the evolution of morality and religion: A response to Lee Cronk.Roy A. Rappaport -1994 -Zygon 29 (3):331-349.
    Issue is taken with Dawkins and Krebs's (1978) conception of communication as being by nature manipulative and with Cronk's proposals concerning the evolution of morality, both of which are grounded in evolutionary biology. An alternative view, which recognizes that which humanity has in common with other species but which emphasizes humanity's distinctiveness, is offered to account for religion and morality.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ambivalently held group-optimizing predispositions.Donald T. Campbell &John B. Gatewood -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):614-614.
  • Group selection's new clothes.Lee Cronk -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):615-616.
  • Some philosophical implications of the rehabilitation of group selection.John Dupré -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):619-620.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Group selection: The theory replaces the bogey man.David Sloan Wilson &Elliott Sober -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):639-654.
    In both biology and the human sciences, social groups are sometimes treated as adaptive units whose organization cannot be reduced to individual interactions. This group-level view is opposed by a more individualistic one that treats social organization as a byproduct of self-interest. According to biologists, group-level adaptations can evolve only by a process of natural selection at the group level. Most biologists rejected group selection as an important evolutionary force during the 1960s and 1970s but a positive literature began to (...) grow during the 1970s and is rapidly expanding today. We review this recent literature and its implications for human evolutionary biology. We show that the rejection of group selection was based on a misplaced emphasis on genes as "replicators" which is in fact irrelevant to the question of whether groups can be like individuals in their functional organization. The fundamental question is whether social groups and other higher-level entities can be "vehicles" of selection. When this elementary fact is recognized, group selection emerges as an important force in nature and what seem to be competing theories, such as kin selection and reciprocity, reappear as special cases of group selection. The result is a unified theory of natural selection that operates on a nested hierarchy of units. The vehicle-based theory makes it clear that group selection is an important force to consider in human evolution. Humans can facultatively span the full range from self-interested individuals to "organs" of group-level "organisms." Human behavior not only reflects the balance between levels of selection but it can also alter the balance through the construction of social structures that have the effect of reducing fitness differences within groups, concentrating natural selection (and functional organization) at the group level. These social structures and the cognitive abilities that produce them allow group selection to be important even among large groups of unrelated individuals. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Driving both ways: Wilson & Sober's conflicting criteria for the identification of groups as vehicles of selection.John Alroy &Alexander Levine -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):608-610.
    No categories
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Seeing the light: What does biology tell us about human social behavior?C. Daniel Batson -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):610-611.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Metaphors and mechanisms in vehicle-based selection theory.Michael Bradie -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):612-612.
  • The consequences of group selection in a domain without genetic input: Culture.C. Loring Brace -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):611-612.
  • Group selection and the group mind in science.Gordon M. Burghardt -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):613-613.
  • On "huxleys evolution and ethics in sociobiological perspective" by George C. Williams.Ralph Wendell Burhoe -1988 -Zygon 23 (4):417-430.
    I concur with Williams that improving human ethics requires full consideration of the biogenetic facts; but I argue that the understanding of biogenetic facts, and of ethics also, can be improved by a fuller view of nature's mechanism for selecting what is fit, a view recently generated by physical scientists. For me ethics necessarily must fit the evolved genotype, but ethics does not emerge until the rise of cultural evolution, where nature selects a culturetype symbiotic with the genotype. I outline (...) my integrated dynamics of the relation of culturetypes to genotypes and to the laws governing physical systems. The biologist's finding that a living organism is of transient significance compared with its lines of heritage and their consequences, I argue, is constructively important for ethical and theological understanding. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Unnecessary competition requirement makes group selection harder to demonstrate.F. T. Cloak -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):614-615.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In praise of replicators.James F. Crow -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):616-616.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Subtle ways of shifting the balance in favor of between-group selection.Lee Alan Dugatkin -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):618-619.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Group selection and “genuine” altruism.Robert H. Frank -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):620-621.
  • Me, you, and us: Distinguishing “egoism,” “altruism,” and “groupism”.Margaret Gilbert -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):621-622.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Contextual analysis and group selection.Charles J. Goodnight -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):622-622.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Putting the cart back behind the horse: Group selection does not require that groups be “organisms”.Todd A. Grantham -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):622-623.
  • Reconstructing the real unit of selection.Adolf Heschl -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):624-625.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Empirically equivalent theories.Harmon R. Holcomb -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):625-626.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Groups as vehicles and replicators: The problem of group-level adaptation.Kent E. Holsinger -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):626-627.
  • Different vehicles for group selection in humans.Michael E. Hyland -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):628-628.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evolving Autonomy.Thomas Johnson -2024 - Dissertation, University of Melbourne
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evolving Autonomy: The Mutual Selection of Social Values.Thomas Johnson -2024 - Dissertation, University of Melbourne
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Limits of Our Explanation: A Case Study inMyxococcus xanthus Cooperation.Saira Khan -2024 -Biological Theory 20 (1):25-40.
    In this article, I demonstrate two ways in which our major theories of the evolution of cooperation may fail to capture particular social phenomena. The first shortcoming of our current major theories stems from the possibility of mischaracterizing the cooperative problem in game theory. The second shortcoming of our current major theories is the insensitivity of these explanatory models to ecological and genomic context. As a case study to illustrate these points, I will use the cooperative interaction of a species (...) of myxobacteria called _Myxococcus xanthus. M. xanthus_ cooperate in many areas of their life cycle—in quorum sensing, social motility, fruiting body formation, and predation. I focus in particular on predation as we have not yet discovered an adequate explanation of how they sustain cooperative predation in the face of developmental cheats. In explaining why we have not, I draw generalizable conclusions that shed light on our use of simplified models to explain real-world behaviors in a variety of organisms. (shrink)
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rx: Distinguish group selection from group adaptation.Elisabeth A. Lloyd -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):628-629.
    I admire Wilson & Sober's (W & S's) aim, to alert social scientists that group selection has risen from the ashqs, and to explicate its relevance to the behavioral sciences. Group selection has beenwidely misunderstood; furthermore, both authors have been instrumental in illuminating conceptual problems surrounding higher-level selection. Still, I find that this target article muddies the waters, primarily through its shifting and confused definition of a "vehicle" of selection. The fundamental problem is an ambiguity in the definition of "adaptation." (...) On the one hand, any evolutionary change that results from a selection process could be called an adaptation, by definition; I call this the "weak" view of adaptation. A "strong" view of adaptation, on the other hand, includes some notion of design - the evolution of a specific complex trait understood, in an engineering sense, to provide a mechanism favoring its owner's success in contributing to the evolutionary lineage. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nongenetic and non-Darwinian evolution.Anatol Rapoport -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):634-634.
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Semantics, theory, and methodological individualism in the group-selection controversy.Eric Alden Smith -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):636-637.
  • Vehicles all the way down?Nicholas S. Thompson -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):638-638.
  • When to bear false witness: An evolutionary approach to the social context of honesty and deceit among commercial fishers.Craig T. Palmer -1993 -Zygon 28 (4):455-468.
    Abstract.This paper uses an evolutionary perspective to identify variables influencing compliance with moral codes about honest communication. Data on over one thousand radio conversations among lobster fishers in two harbors in Maine are compared in regard to the sharing of information. The sharing of accurate information is found to be significantly more frequent in the harbor that is more integrated by reciprocally altruistic relationships. This is consistent with the view that moral systems are systems of indirect reciprocity, but it also (...) suggests that humans have evolved to base their compliance with moral codes on cues from their social environment. (shrink)
    Direct download(2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Methodological problems in evolutionary biology. XII. against evolutionary ethics.Wim J. van der Steen -1999 -Acta Biotheoretica 47 (1):41-57.
    Evolutionary ethics has recently become popular again. Some of its representatives elaborate new attempts to derive ethics from evolutionary biology. The attempts, like previous ones, fail because they commit the naturalistic fallacy. Premises from evolutionary biology together with normative premises also do not justify ethical principles. Other representatives argue that evolutionary considerations imply that ethics cannot be justified at all. Their arguments presuppose an unacceptable form of foundationalism. In principle, evolutionary biology might explain some aspects of morality, but in practice (...) explanations are hard to come by. All this does not imply that evolutionary theory is irrelevant in normative settings. To the contrary, it may help us devise guidelines in environmental policy and health care policy. It is to be hoped that evolutionary ethicists will divert their research efforts to the elaboration of such guidelines. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The maintenance of behavioral diversity in human societies.Christopher Wills -1994 -Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):638-639.
    Direct download(3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moral darwinism: Ethical evidence for the descent of man. [REVIEW]Robert T. Pennock -1995 -Biology and Philosophy 10 (3):287-307.
    Could an ethical theory ever play a substantial evidential role in a scientific argument for an empirical hypothesis? InThe Descent of Man, Darwin includes an extended discussion of the nature of human morality, and the ethical theory which he sketches is not simply developed as an interesting ramification of his theory of evolution, but is used as a key part of his evidence for human descent from animal ancestors. Darwin must rebut the argument that, because of our moral nature, humans (...) are essentially different in kind from other animals and so had to have had a different origin. I trace his causal story of how the moral sense could develop out of social instincts by evolutionary mechanisms of group selection, and show that the form of Utilitarianism he proposes involves a radical reduction of the standard of value to the concept of biological fitness. I argue that this causal analysis, although a weakness from a normative standpoint, is a strength when judged for its intended purpose as part of an evidential argument to confirm the hypothesis of human descent. (shrink)
    Direct download(4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  

  • [8]ページ先頭

    ©2009-2025 Movatter.jp