Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


nLab over category

Skip the Navigation Links |Home Page |All Pages |Latest Revisions |Discuss this page |
Contents

Context

Category theory

Contents

Definition

Theslice category orover categoryC/c\mathbf{C}/c of acategoryC\mathbf{C} over an objectcCc \in \mathbf{C} has

C/c={XgXffc} C/c = \left\lbrace \array{ X &&\stackrel{g}{\to}&& X' \\ & {}_f \searrow && \swarrow_{f'} \\ && c } \right\rbrace

The slice category is a special case of acomma category.

There is aforgetful functorUc:C/cCU_c: \mathbf{C}/c \to \mathbf{C} which maps an objectf:Xcf:X \to c to its domainXX and a morphismg:XXC/cg: X \to X' \in \mathbf{C}/c (fromf:Xcf:X \to c tof:Xcf': X' \to c such thatfg=ff' \circ g = f) to the morphismg:XXg: X \to X'.

Thedual notion is anunder category.

Examples

Properties

Comonadicity

IfCC admits binary coproducts with the fixed objectcc, then the forgetful functorC/cCC/c \to C iscomonadic. Seecoreader comonad for more details.

Relation to codomain fibration

The assignment of overcategoriesC/cC/c to objectscCc \in C extends to afunctor

C/():CCat C/(-) : C \to Cat

Under theGrothendieck construction this functor corresponds to thecodomain fibration

cod:[I,C]C cod : [I,C] \to C

from thearrow category ofCC. (Note that unlessCC haspullbacks, this functor is not actually afibration, though it is always an opfibration.)

Slicing of adjoint functors

Proposition

(sliced adjoints)
Let

be a pair ofadjoint functors (adjoint ∞-functors), where thecategory (∞-category)𝒞\mathcal{C} has allpullbacks (homotopy pullbacks).

Then:

  1. For everyobjectb𝒞b \in \mathcal{C} there is induced a pair ofadjoint functors between theslice categories (slice ∞-categories) of the form

    where:

  2. For everyobjectb𝒟b \in \mathcal{D} there is induced a pair ofadjoint functors between theslice categories of the form

    where:

The first statement appears, in the generality of(∞,1)-category theory, asHTT, prop. 5.2.5.1. For discussion inmodel category theory see atsliced Quillen adjunctions.
Proof

(in1-category theory)

Recall that (this Prop.) the hom-isomorphism that defines an adjunction of functors (this Def.) is equivalently given in terms ofcomposition with

as follows:

Using this, consider the following transformations of morphisms in slice categories, for thefirst case:

(1a)

(2a)

(2b)

(1b)

Here:

Hence:

  • starting with a morphism as in (1a) and transforming it to(2)(2) and then to (1b) is the identity operation;

  • starting with a morphism as in (2b) and transforming it to (1) and then to (2a) is the identity operation.

In conclusion, the transformations (1)\leftrightarrow (2) consitute ahom-isomorphism that witnesses an adjunction of the first claimed form(1).


Thesecond case follows analogously, but a little more directly since no pullback is involved:

(1a)

(2)

(1b)

In conclusion, the transformations (1)\leftrightarrow (2) consitute ahom-isomorphism that witnesses an adjunction of the second claimed form(2).

Remark

(left adjoint of sliced adjunction forms adjuncts)
The sliced adjunction (Prop.) in the second form(2) is such that the slicedleft adjoint sends slicing morphismτ\tau to theiradjunctsτ˜\widetilde{\tau}, in that (again bythis Prop.):

The two adjunctions in admit the following joint generalisation, which is provenHTT, lem. 5.2.5.2. (Note that the statement there is even more general and here we only use the case whereK=Δ0K = \Delta^0.)

Proposition

(sliced adjoints)
Let

be a pair ofadjoint ∞-functors, where the∞-category𝒞\mathcal{C} has allhomotopy pullbacks. Suppose further we are given objectsc𝒞c \in \mathcal{C} andd𝒟d \in \mathcal{D} together with a morphismα:cR(d)\alpha: c \to R(d) and its adjunctβ:L(c)d\beta:L(c) \to d.

Then there is an induced a pair ofadjoint ∞-functors between theslice ∞-categories of the form

where:

Presheaves on over-categories and over-categories of presheaves

Seeslice of presheaves is presheaves on slice.

LetCC be acategory,cc anobject ofCC and letC/cC/c be theover category ofCC overcc. WritePSh(C/c)=[(C/c)op,Set]PSh(C/c) = [(C/c)^{op}, Set] for thecategory of presheaves onC/cC/c and writePSh(C)/Y(c)PSh(C)/Y(c) for theover category ofpresheaves onCC over the presheafY(c)Y(c), whereY:CPSh(c)Y : C \to PSh(c) is theYoneda embedding.

Proposition

There is anequivalence of categories

e:PSh(C/c)PSh(C)/Y(c). e : PSh(C/c) \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} PSh(C)/Y(c) \,.
Proof

The functoree takesFPSh(C/c)F \in PSh(C/c) to the presheafF:dfC(d,c)F(f)F' : d \mapsto \sqcup_{f \in C(d,c)} F(f) which is equipped with the natural transformationη:FY(c)\eta : F' \to Y(c) with component mapηd:fC(d,c)F(f)C(d,c)\eta_d: \sqcup_{f \in C(d,c)} F(f) \to C(d,c).

A weak inverse ofee is given by the functor

e¯:PSh(C)/Y(c)PSh(C/c) \bar e : PSh(C)/Y(c) \to PSh(C/c)

which sendsη:FY(C)) \eta : F' \to Y(C)) toFPSh(C/c)F \in PSh(C/c) given by

F:(f:dc)F(d)|c, F : (f : d \to c) \mapsto F'(d)|_c \,,

whereF(d)|cF'(d)|_c is thepullback

F(d)|cF(d)ηdptfC(d,c). \array{ F'(d)|_c &\to& F'(d) \\ \downarrow && \downarrow^{\eta_d} \\ pt &\stackrel{f}{\to}& C(d,c) } \,.
Example

Suppose the presheafFPSh(C/c)F \in PSh(C/c) does not actually depend on the morphisms toCC, i.e. suppose that it factors through the forgetful functor from theover category toCC:

F:(C/c)opCopSet. F : (C/c)^{op} \to C^{op} \to Set \,.

ThenF(d)=fC(d,c)F(f)=fC(d,c)F(d)C(d,c)×F(d) F'(d) = \sqcup_{f \in C(d,c)} F(f) = \sqcup_{f \in C(d,c)} F(d) \simeq C(d,c) \times F(d) and henceF=Y(c)×FF ' = Y(c) \times F with respect to theclosed monoidal structure on presheaves.

See alsofunctors and comma categories.

For the analogous statement in(∞,1)-category theory see at(∞,1)-category of (∞,1)-presheaves – Interaction with overcategories?.

Limits and colimits

Proposition

Acolimit in anover category is computed as a colimit in the underlying category.

Precisely: let𝒞\mathcal{C} be acategory,t𝒞t \in \mathcal{C} anobject, and𝒞/t\mathcal{C}/t the correspondingovercategory, andp:𝒞/t𝒞p \colon \mathcal{C}/t \to \mathcal{C} the obvious projection.

LetF:D𝒞/tF \colon D \to \mathcal{C}/t be anyfunctor. Then, if it exists, thecolimit ofpFp \circ F in𝒞\mathcal{C} is the image underpp of the colimit overFF:

p(limF)lim(pF) p \big( \underset{\longrightarrow}{\lim} F \big) \;\simeq\; \underset{\longrightarrow}{\lim} (p \circ F)

andlimF\underset{\longrightarrow}{\lim} F is uniquely characterized bylim(pF)\underset{\longrightarrow}{\lim} (p \circ F) this way.

This statement, and its proof, is theformal dual to the corresponding statement forundercategories, seethere.

Proposition

For𝒞\mathcal{C} acategory,X:𝒟𝒞X \;\colon\; \mathcal{D} \longrightarrow \mathcal{C} adiagram,𝒞/X\mathcal{C}_{/X} thecomma category (the over-category if𝒟\mathcal{D} is the point) andF:K𝒞/XF \;\colon\; K \to \mathcal{C}_{/X} adiagram in thecomma category, then thelimitlimF\underset{\leftarrow}{\lim} F in𝒞/X\mathcal{C}_{/X} coincides with the limitlimF/X\underset{\leftarrow}{\lim} F/X in𝒞\mathcal{C}.

For a proof see at(∞,1)-limithere.

Initial and terminal objects

As a special case of the above discussion of limits and colimits in a slice𝒞/X\mathcal{C}_{/X} we obtain the following statement, which of course is also immediately checked explicitly.

Corollary

Related concepts

References

Formalization incubical Agda:

Last revised on September 11, 2024 at 13:05:52. See thehistory of this page for a list of all contributions to it.

EditDiscussPrevious revisionChanges from previous revisionHistory (51 revisions)CitePrintSource

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp