Theslice category orover category of acategory over an object has
objects that are all arrows such that, and
morphisms from to such that.
The slice category is a special case of acomma category.
There is aforgetful functor which maps an object to its domain and a morphism (from to such that) to the morphism.
Thedual notion is anunder category.
If is aposet and, then the slice category is thedown set of elements with.
If is aterminal object in, then is isomorphic to.
For atopological space then thecategory of covering spaces over is afull subcategory of the slice category of thecategory of topological spaces.
Thefundamental theorem of topos theory states that the slice category over any object in a topos is itself a topos.
For amonoidal category the slice category over anymonoid object is monoidal.
For instance, theslice topos of a giventopos over anymonoid object is canonically amonoidal topos (see the Examplethere).
If admits binary coproducts with the fixed object, then the forgetful functor iscomonadic. Seecoreader comonad for more details.
The assignment of overcategories to objects extends to afunctor
Under theGrothendieck construction this functor corresponds to thecodomain fibration
from thearrow category of. (Note that unless haspullbacks, this functor is not actually afibration, though it is always an opfibration.)
(sliced adjoints)
Let
be a pair ofadjoint functors (adjoint ∞-functors), where thecategory (∞-category) has allpullbacks (homotopy pullbacks).
Then:
For everyobject there is induced a pair ofadjoint functors between theslice categories (slice ∞-categories) of the form
where:
For everyobject there is induced a pair ofadjoint functors between theslice categories of the form
where:
is the evident induced functor (applying to the entire trianglediagrams in which represent the morphisms in);
is thecomposite
of
the evident functor induced by;
thecomposition with the-counit at (i.e. the leftbase change along).
Recall that (this Prop.) the hom-isomorphism that defines an adjunction of functors (this Def.) is equivalently given in terms ofcomposition with
as follows:
Using this, consider the following transformations of morphisms in slice categories, for thefirst case:
(1a)
(2a)
(2b)
(1b)
Here:
(1a) and (1b) are equivalent expressions of the same morphism in, by (at the top of the diagrams) the above expression ofadjuncts between and and (at the bottom) by thetriangle identity.
(2a) and (2b) are equivalent expression of the same morphism in, by theuniversal property of thepullback.
Hence:
starting with a morphism as in (1a) and transforming it to and then to (1b) is the identity operation;
starting with a morphism as in (2b) and transforming it to (1) and then to (2a) is the identity operation.
In conclusion, the transformations (1) (2) consitute ahom-isomorphism that witnesses an adjunction of the first claimed form(1).
Thesecond case follows analogously, but a little more directly since no pullback is involved:
(1a)
(2)
(1b)
In conclusion, the transformations (1) (2) consitute ahom-isomorphism that witnesses an adjunction of the second claimed form(2).
(left adjoint of sliced adjunction forms adjuncts)
The sliced adjunction (Prop.) in the second form(2) is such that the slicedleft adjoint sends slicing morphism to theiradjuncts, in that (again bythis Prop.):
The two adjunctions in admit the following joint generalisation, which is provenHTT, lem. 5.2.5.2. (Note that the statement there is even more general and here we only use the case where.)
(sliced adjoints)
Let
be a pair ofadjoint ∞-functors, where the∞-category has allhomotopy pullbacks. Suppose further we are given objects and together with a morphism and its adjunct.
Then there is an induced a pair ofadjoint ∞-functors between theslice ∞-categories of the form
where:
is thecomposite
of
the evident functor induced by;
thecomposition with (i.e. the leftbase change along).
is thecomposite
of
the evident functor induced by;
thehomotopy along (i.e. thebase change along).
Seeslice of presheaves is presheaves on slice.
Let be acategory, anobject of and let be theover category of over. Write for thecategory of presheaves on and write for theover category ofpresheaves on over the presheaf, where is theYoneda embedding.
There is anequivalence of categories
The functor takes to the presheaf which is equipped with the natural transformation with component map.
A weak inverse of is given by the functor
which sends to given by
where is thepullback
Suppose the presheaf does not actually depend on the morphisms to, i.e. suppose that it factors through the forgetful functor from theover category to:
Then and hence with respect to theclosed monoidal structure on presheaves.
See alsofunctors and comma categories.
For the analogous statement in(∞,1)-category theory see at(∞,1)-category of (∞,1)-presheaves – Interaction with overcategories?.
Acolimit in anover category is computed as a colimit in the underlying category.
Precisely: let be acategory, anobject, and the correspondingovercategory, and the obvious projection.
Let be anyfunctor. Then, if it exists, thecolimit of in is the image under of the colimit over:
and is uniquely characterized by this way.
This statement, and its proof, is theformal dual to the corresponding statement forundercategories, seethere.
For acategory, adiagram, thecomma category (the over-category if is the point) and adiagram in thecomma category, then thelimit in coincides with the limit in.
For a proof see at(∞,1)-limithere.
As a special case of the above discussion of limits and colimits in a slice we obtain the following statement, which of course is also immediately checked explicitly.
If has an initial object, then has aninitial object, given by.
Theterminal object of is.
over-category
Formalization incubical Agda:
Last revised on September 11, 2024 at 13:05:52. See thehistory of this page for a list of all contributions to it.