Part of the book series:Elections, Voting, Technology ((EVT))
1387Accesses
1Citation
Abstract
This chapter explores the connection between compulsory voting in Australia and public reason, i.e. the view that political rules are legitimate only if they are justified by appealing to reasons that all citizens can accept at some level of idealization. While constitutional democracies such as the US assign a significant role to institutions like the Supreme Court in the process of public reasoning, parliamentary supremacy regimes rely instead more extensively on democracy and majorities. In a polity like Australia, which presents many features typical of a parliamentary supremacy regime, compulsory voting can play a key role in guaranteeing public reason, by forcing public officials to take into account a broad variety of perspectives, interests and demands, and therefore refrain from appealing to sectarian non-public reasons when justifying political rules.
This is a preview of subscription content,log in via an institution to check access.
Access this chapter
Subscribe and save
- Get 10 units per month
- Download Article/Chapter or eBook
- 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
- Cancel anytime
Buy Now
- Chapter
- JPY 3498
- Price includes VAT (Japan)
- eBook
- JPY 14871
- Price includes VAT (Japan)
- Softcover Book
- JPY 18589
- Price includes VAT (Japan)
- Hardcover Book
- JPY 18589
- Price includes VAT (Japan)
Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout
Purchases are for personal use only
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
- 1.
See also later in this chapter the example of the ‘Lemon Test’ in the US, which constitutes a de facto legal enforcement of public reason.
- 2.
The priority assigned to democracy and majorities reflects a broader feature of Australia’s political culture, which is often associated with Benthamite utilitarianism (Collins1985; Brett2019). The latter prioritizes the maximization of happiness across society over the protection of individual natural rights (to life, liberty and property) that is central to Lockean liberalism and to the US political culture.
- 3.
Likewise, constitutional democracy regimes may not fully match the Rawlsian ideal. To that extent, compulsory voting may also play a role in such regimes, by providing an additional contribution (e.g. alongside a constitutional court) to the monitoring of public reasoning and the exclusion of non-public reasons from the justification of political rules. Ultimately, indirect public reason should be understood as a systemic process to which different institutions can make a contribution. The type and degree of contribution that each institution makes may vary depending on the type of political regime considered.
- 4.
This point should be qualified. The effectiveness of compulsory voting in guaranteeing that all voices are heard also strongly depends on other factors such as the electoral system. A proportional representation system, for example, may be more conducive than a majoritarian one to an equal consideration of all voices. In a majoritarian system the presence of safe vs. swinging seats may imply that not all voices are given equal consideration, even in the presence of compulsory voting. Furthermore, majoritarian systems normally encourage the formation of ‘big tent’ or ‘catch-all’ parties within which certain interests and voices may be assigned more prominence than others. Proportional representation favours instead the formation of a multi-party system in which different citizens and social groups are more likely to find (or be able to create) parties that closely reflect their interests and demands (see Bonotti2017, Chapter 7).
- 5.
It is worth noting, once again, that compulsory voting is not a perfect solution. For example, it may not be sufficient to resolve the problem of persistent minority groups to whom no politician or public official bothers to offer justifications. Such groups may need, for example, special representation rights (e.g. Kymlicka1995) in order to be heard and taken into account in the design and implementation of political rules.
- 6.
For some criticisms of the fairness argument, see Brennan and Hill (2014, p. 192).
- 7.
Sometimes this process may be more indirect, i.e. politicians may be responsive to their constituents’ reasons, which may be non-public and based on their partial interests (rather than being interpretations of shared basic political values). It will be politicians’ task to translate these non-public reasons into public ones, more specifically into specific interpretations of shared basic political values, and to challenge the alternative interpretations provided by their political opponents.
Bibliography
Badano, G., & Bonotti, M. (2020). Rescuing public reason liberalism’s accessibility requirement.Law and Philosophy,39(1), 35–65.
Beitz, C. (1989).Political equality: An essay on democratic theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Blackshield, T., & Williams, G. (2010).Australian constitutional law and theory (5th ed.). Annandale, NSW: Federation Press.
Brennan, J., & Hill, L. (2014).Compulsory voting: For and against. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Bonotti, M. (2015). Political liberalism, free speech and public reason.European Journal of Political Theory,14(2), 180–208.
Bonotti, M. (2017).Partisanship and political liberalism in diverse societies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Brett, J. (2019).From secret ballot of democracy sausage: How Australia got compulsory Voting. Melbourne: Text Publishing.
Brown, A. (2015).Hate speech law: A philosophical examination. New York and Abingdon, Oxon: Routledge.
Christiano, T. (1996).The rule of the many: Fundamental issues in democratic theory. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Collins, H. (1985). Political ideology in Australia: The distinctiveness of a Benthamite society.Daedalus,114(1), 147–169.
Dahl, R. A. (1989).Democracy and its critics. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Fowler, A. (2013). Electoral and policy consequences of voter turnout: Evidence from compulsory voting in Australia.Quarterly Journal of Political Science,8(2), 159–182.
Gaus, G. (2010).The order of public reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gaus, G., & Vallier, K. (2009). The roles of religious conviction in a publicly justified polity.Philosophy and Social Criticism,35(1–2), 51–76.
Goldsworthy, J. (2001).The sovereignty of parliament: History and philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Griffin, J. D., & Newman, B. (2005). Are voters better represented?The Journal of Politics,67(4), 1206–1227.
Habermas, J. (2006). Religion in the public sphere.European Journal of Philosophy, 14(1), 1–25.
Hart, H. L. A. (1955). Are there any natural rights?Philosophical Review,64(2), 175–191.
Hill, L. (2006). Low voter turnout in the United States: Is compulsory voting a viable solution?Journal of Theoretical Politics,18(2), 207–32.
Hill, L. (2010). On the justifiability of compulsory voting: Reply to Lever.British Journal of Political Science,40(4), 917–923.
Hill, L. (2017). Compulsory voting and the promotion of human rights in Australia.Australian Journal of Human Rights,23(2), 188–202.
Keane, P. A. (2008, June 12).In celebration of the constitution. An address to the National Archives Commission, Brisbane.http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/QldJSchol/2008/64.pdf. Accessed 21 July 2020.
Klosko, G. (2004).The principle of fairness and political obligation (2nd ed.). Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Kymlicka, W. (1995).Multicultural citizenship: A liberal theory of minority rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Laborde, C. (2017).Liberalism’s religion. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Lemon v. Kurtzman, 403 U.S. 602 (1971).
Lever, A. (2010). Compulsory voting: A critical perspective.British Journal of Political Science,40(4), 897–915.
Lever, A., & Volacu, A. (2018). Should voting be compulsory? Democracy and the ethics of voting. In A. Lever & A. Poama (Eds.),Routledge handbook of ethics and public policy (pp. 242–254). New York: Routledge.
Lijphart, A. (1997). Unequal participation: Democracy’s unresolved dilemma.American Political Science Review,91(1), 1–14.
McGraw, B. T. (2010).Faith in politics: Religion and liberal democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Patapan, H. (2000).Judging democracy: The new politics of the High Court of Australia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Peters, Y., & Ensink, S. J. (2015). Differential responsiveness in Europe: The effects of preference difference and electoral participation.West European Politics,38(3), 577–600.
Quong, J. (2011).Liberalism without perfection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Quong, J. (2018). Public reason. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.),The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2018 ed.).https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/public-reason/. Accessed 21 July 2020.
Rawls, J. (1999).A theory of justice (Revised ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rawls, J. (2005).Political liberalism (Expanded ed.). New York: Columbia University Press.
Umbers, L. (2018). Compulsory voting: A defence.British Journal of Political Science. First View.https://doi.org/10.1017/S0007123418000303.
Vallier, K. (2014).Liberal politics and public faith. New York: Routledge.
Wolterstorff, N. (1997). The role of religion in decision and discussion of political issues. In R. Audi & N. Wolterstorff (Eds.),Religion in the public square (pp. 67–120). London: Rowman & Littlefield.
Acknowledgements
This work was supported in part by the grant ‘Civic Virtue in Public Life: Understanding and Countering Incivility in Liberal Democracies’, funded as part of the Self, Virtue and Public Life Project, a three-year research initiative based at the Institute for the Study of Human Flourishing at the University of Oklahoma, funded with generous support from the Templeton Religion Trust. I would also like to thank Valeria Ottonelli, Federico Zuolo, and the audience at the POLIETHICS—Seminario genovese di Etica e Politica, 14 February 2020, for helpful feedback on an earlier draft of this chapter.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Politics and International Relations, Monash University, Clayton, VIC, Australia
Matteo Bonotti
- Matteo Bonotti
Search author on:PubMed Google Scholar
Corresponding author
Correspondence toMatteo Bonotti.
Editor information
Editors and Affiliations
Politics and International Relations, Monash University, Clayton, VIC, Australia
Matteo Bonotti
Politics and International Relations, Monash University, Clayton, VIC, Australia
Paul Strangio
Rights and permissions
Copyright information
© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.
About this chapter
Cite this chapter
Bonotti, M. (2021). Public Reason, Compulsory Voting and Australian Democracy. In: Bonotti, M., Strangio, P. (eds) A Century of Compulsory Voting in Australia. Elections, Voting, Technology. Palgrave Macmillan, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-33-4025-1_10
Download citation
Published:
Publisher Name:Palgrave Macmillan, Singapore
Print ISBN:978-981-33-4024-4
Online ISBN:978-981-33-4025-1
eBook Packages:Political Science and International StudiesPolitical Science and International Studies (R0)
Share this chapter
Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:
Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.
Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative