Part of the book series:History of Mechanism and Machine Science ((HMMS,volume 27))
1418Accesses
2Citations
Abstract
In this paper we try to distinguish two different styles of experimental practice—roughly speaking the Galilean and the Newtonian. They differ in the way they intertwine mathematics and experimentation. We offer a theoretical reconstruction of the transition from the Galilean to the Newtonian experimental practice. It seems that this transition was brought about by gradual changes of the conceptual framework for the representation of motion. The aim of the paper is to argue that in many of these changes Cartesian physics played an important role.
This is a preview of subscription content,log in via an institution to check access.
Access this chapter
Subscribe and save
- Get 10 units per month
- Download Article/Chapter or eBook
- 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
- Cancel anytime
Buy Now
- Chapter
- JPY 3498
- Price includes VAT (Japan)
- eBook
- JPY 17159
- Price includes VAT (Japan)
- Softcover Book
- JPY 21449
- Price includes VAT (Japan)
- Hardcover Book
- JPY 21449
- Price includes VAT (Japan)
Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout
Purchases are for personal use only
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
- 1.
Even though air pressure (which we will discuss below) is not directly accessible to ordinary experience, there is nevertheless a directly observable phenomenon—the strange behavior of the water pumps that refuse to pump water from depths greater than a certain limit—that is accessible to ordinary experience.
- 2.
Geometrical transition means that the basic representation of motion isgeometrical (as opposed to adynamic one): it describes motion as a change ofposition in space rather than as a change of state. Further,geometrical transition represents motion astransition, which means that the focus of attention is on the starting point and the terminal point of motion, while the process of motion itself does not enter the representation. (This does not mean that the change ofstate or theprocess of change is not thought about, but only that they are not included into the representation of motion. Thus even though Aristotle understands change as a becoming, in the definitions of (violent) motions these aspects do not enter.).
- 3.
Geometrical flow means that the representation of motion is stillgeometrical, it concerns a change of position in space and not a change of state. Nevertheless, it is aflow. It represents motion as a continuous passing along a trajectory (as opposed to atransition from the starting position to the terminal one).
- 4.
It seems that theextended body of Cartesian physics is closer to thecosa of theCossists than to the Aristotelianpragmata. An extended body enters into mechanical interactions with other bodies just like acosa enters into algebraic relations with other quantities. Furthermore, an extended body has only mechanical properties just like acosa has purely algebraic ones.
References
De Caro M (1993) Galileo’s mathematical platonism. In: Czermak (ed) Philosophie der Mathematik. Holder–Pichler–Tempsky, Wien, pp 13–22
Drake S (1973) Galileo’s experimental confirmation of horizontal inertia. Isis 64:291–305
Gabbey A (1980) Force and inertia in the seventeenth century: Descartes and Newton. In: Gaukroger S (ed) Descartes: philosophy, mathematics and physics. The Harvester Press, Sussex, pp 230–320
Galilei G (1610) The starry messenger. In: Drake S (ed) Discoveries and opinions of Galileo (1957). Doubleday, New York, pp 21–58
Galilei G (1623) The Assayer. In: Drake S (ed) Discoveries and opinions of Galileo (1957). Doubleday, New York, pp 229–280
Garber D (1992) Descartes’ metaphysical physics. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Gaukroger S (1980) Descartes’ project for a mathematical physics. In: Gaukroger S (ed) Descartes, philosophy, mathematics and physics (1980) The Harvester Press, Sussex, pp 97–140
Hakfoort C (1992) Newtons Optik, Wandel im spektrum der Wissenschaft. In: Fauvel J (ed) Newtons werk. Die Begründung der modernen Naturwissenschaft (1993) Birkhäuser, Basel, pp 109–133
Hill DK (1988) Dissecting trajectories: Galileo’s early experiments on projectile motion and the law of fall. Isis 79:646–668
Kvasz L (2002) Galilean physics in light of Husserlian phenomenology. Philosophia Naturalis 39:209–233
Kvasz L (2003) The mathematisation of nature and Cartesian physics. Philosophia Naturalis 40:157–182
Kvasz L (2005) The mathematisation of nature and Newtonian physics. Philosophia Naturalis 42:183–211
Nagel E (1961) The structure of science. Hackett Publishing Company, New York
Naylor RH (1990) Galileo’s method of analysis and synthesis. Isis 81:695–707
Ronchi V (1967) The influence of the early development of optics on science and philosophy. In: McMullin E (ed) Galileo, man of science. (1967) Basic Books, New York, pp 195–206
Shea W (1998) Galileo’s Copernicanism: the science and the rhetoric. In: Machamer P (ed) The Cambridge companion to Galileo. (1998) Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 211–243
Swerdlow N (1998) Galileo’s discoveries with the telescope and their evidence for the Copernican theory. In: Machamer P (ed) The Cambridge companion to Galileo. (1998) Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 244–270
Wallace WA (1984) Galileo and his sources: the heritage of the Collegio Romano in Galileo’s science. Princeton University Press, Princeton
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Gábor Boros for his support and encouragement. The paper was written in the framework of theJan Evangelista Purkyně Fellowship at the Institute of Philosophy of the Academy of Sciences of Czech Republic in Prague.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Institute of Philosophy, Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic, Prague, Czech Republic
Ladislav Kvasz
- Ladislav Kvasz
Search author on:PubMed Google Scholar
Corresponding author
Correspondence toLadislav Kvasz.
Editor information
Editors and Affiliations
Department of Physics, Lille 1 University Science and Technology, Villeneuve d’Ascq, France
Raffaele Pisano
Rights and permissions
Copyright information
© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht
About this chapter
Cite this chapter
Kvasz, L. (2015). Mathematical Language as a Bridge Between Conceptualization of Motion and Experimental Practice. In: Pisano, R. (eds) A Bridge between Conceptual Frameworks. History of Mechanism and Machine Science, vol 27. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9645-3_13
Download citation
Published:
Publisher Name:Springer, Dordrecht
Print ISBN:978-94-017-9644-6
Online ISBN:978-94-017-9645-3
eBook Packages:EngineeringEngineering (R0)
Share this chapter
Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:
Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.
Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative