Part ofa series on |
The Self |
---|
Constructs |
Theories |
Processes |
Value judgment |
As applied to activities |
Interpersonal |
Social |
Politics |
Personal identity is the uniquenumerical identity of aperson over time.[1][2] Discussions regarding personal identity typically aim to determine the necessary and sufficient conditions under which a person at one time and a person at another time can be said to be thesame person, persisting through time.
Inphilosophy, theproblem of personal identity[3] is concerned with how one is able to identify a single person over a time interval, dealing with such questions as, "What makes it true that a person at one time is the same thing as a person at another time?" or "What kinds of things are we persons?"
In contemporarymetaphysics, the matter of personal identity is referred to as thediachronic problem of personal identity.[a][4] Thesynchronic problem concerns the question of what features and traits characterize a person at a given time.Analytic philosophy andcontinental philosophy both inquire about the nature of identity. Continental philosophy deals with conceptually maintaining identity when confronted by different philosophicpropositions,postulates, andpresuppositions about the world and its nature.[5][6]
One way to explain how persons persist over time is to say that identity consists in physical or bodily continuity.[7][8] However, there are problems with this view. As theShip of Theseus thought experiment illustrates, even for inanimate objects there are difficulties in determining whether one physical body at one time is the same thing as a physical body at another time. With humans, over time our bodies age and grow, losing and gaining matter, and over sufficient years will not consist of most of the matter they once consisted of. It is thus problematic to ground the persistence of personal identity over time in the continuous existence of our bodies. Nevertheless, this approach has its supporters, who define humans as biological organisms. Theyassert theproposition that apsychological relation is not necessary for personal continuity.[b] This personal identityontology assumes therelational theory[9] oflife-sustaining processes instead of bodily continuity.
Theteletransportation problem proposed byDerek Parfit is designed to bring outintuitions about corporeal continuity. The thought experiment discusses cases in which a person isteleported from Earth to Mars. Ultimately, the inability to specify where on a spectrum the transmitted person stops being identical to the initial person on Earth appears to show that having a numerically identical physical body is not the criterion for personal identity.[10]
In another concept ofmind, the set ofcognitive faculties[c] are considered to consist of animmaterial substance, separate from and independent of the body.[11] If a person is then identified with their mind, rather than their body—if a person is considered tobe their mind—and their mind is such a non-physical substance, then personal identity over time may be grounded in the persistence of this non-physical substance, despite the continuous change in the substance of the body it is associated with.
The mind-body problem[12][13][14][15] concerns the explanation of the relationship, if any, that exists between minds, ormental processes, and bodily states or processes. One of the aims of philosophers who work in this area is to explain how a non-material mind can influence a material body and vice versa.
This is controversial and problematic, and adopting it as a solution raises questions.Perceptual experiences depend onstimuli which arrive at varioussensory organs from the external world and these stimuli cause changes inmental states; ultimately causingsensation.[d] Adesire for food, for example, will tend to cause a person to move their body in a manner and in a direction to obtain food. The question, then, is how it can be possible for conscious experiences to arise out of an organ (thehuman brain) possessing electrochemical properties. A related problem is to explain howpropositional attitudes (e.g. beliefs and desires) can causeneurons of the brain to fire and muscles to contract in the correct manner. These comprise some of the puzzles that have confrontedepistemologists andphilosophers of mind from at least the time ofRené Descartes.
John Locke considered personal identity (or theself) to be founded onconsciousness (viz.memory), and not on thesubstance of either thesoul or thebody.[16] Chapter 27 of Book II of hisEssay Concerning Human Understanding (1689), entitled "On Identity and Diversity", has been said to be one of the first modern conceptualizations of consciousness as the repeated self-identification ofoneself. Through this identification,moral responsibility could be attributed to thesubject and punishment andguilt could be justified, as critics such asNietzsche would point out.
According to Locke, personal identity (the self) "depends on consciousness, not on substance" nor on the soul. We are the same person to the extent that we are conscious of the past and future thoughts and actions in the same way as we are conscious of present thoughts and actions. If consciousness is this "thought" which "goes along with the substance…which makes the same person," then personal identity is only founded on the repeated act of consciousness: "This may show us wherein personal identity consists: not in the identity of substance, but…in the identity of consciousness." For example, one may claim to be areincarnation of Plato, therefore having the same soul substance. One would be the same person as Plato only if one had the same consciousness of Plato's thoughts and actions that he himself did. Therefore, self-identity is not based on the soul. One soul may have various personalities.
Neither is self-identity founded on the body substance, argues Locke, as the body may change while the person remains the same. Even the identity of animals is not founded on their body: "animal identity is preserved in identity of life, and not of substance," as the body of the animal grows and changes during its life. On the other hand, identity of humans is based on their consciousness.[e]
This border case leads to this problematic thought that since personal identity is based on consciousness, and only oneself can be aware of one's consciousness, exterior human judges may never know if they are really judging—and punishing—the same person, or simply the same body. In other words, Locke argues that one may be judged only for the acts of the body, as this is what is apparent to all but God. We are only responsible for the acts of which we are conscious. This forms the basis of theinsanity defense—one cannot be held accountable for acts of which one wasunconscious—and therefore leads to philosophical questions:
personal identity consists [not in the identity of substance] but in the identity of consciousness, wherein if Socrates and the present mayor of Queenborough agree, they are the same person: if the same Socrates waking and sleeping do not partake of the same consciousness, Socrates waking and sleeping is not the same person. And to punish Socrates waking for what sleeping Socrates thought, and waking Socrates was never conscious of, would be no more right, than to punish one twin for what his brother-twin did, whereof he knew nothing, because their outsides were so like, that they could not be distinguished; for such twins have been seen.[17]
Or again:
PERSON, as I take it, is the name for this self. Wherever a man finds what he calls himself, there, I think, another may say is the same person. It is a forensic term, appropriating actions and their merit; and so belong only to intelligent agents, capable of a law, and happiness, and misery. This personality extends itself beyond present existence to what is past, only by consciousness,—whereby it becomes concerned and accountable; owns and imputes to itself past actions, just upon the same ground and for the same reason as it does the present. All which is founded in a concern for happiness, the unavoidable concomitant of consciousness; that which is conscious of pleasure and pain, desiring that that self that is conscious should be happy. And therefore whatever past actions it cannot reconcile or APPROPRIATE to that present self by consciousness, it can be no more concerned in it than if they had never been done: and to receive pleasure or pain, i.e. reward or punishment, on the account of any such action, is all one as to be made happy or miserable in its first being, without any demerit at all. For, supposing a MAN punished now for what he had done in another life, whereof he could be made to have no consciousness at all, what difference is there between that punishment and being CREATED miserable? And therefore, conformable to this, the apostle tells us, that, at the great day, when every one shall 'receive according to his doings, the secrets of all hearts shall be laid open.' The sentence shall be justified by the consciousness all person shall have, that THEY THEMSELVES, in what bodies soever they appear, or what substances soever that consciousness adheres to, are the SAME that committed those actions, and deserve that punishment for them.[17]
Henceforth, Locke's conception of personal identity founds it not on the substance or the body, but in the "same continued consciousness", which is also distinct from the soul since the soul may have no consciousness of itself (as inreincarnation). He creates a third term between the soul and the body. For Locke, the body may change, while consciousness remains the same.[18][19] Therefore, personal identity, for Locke, is not in the body but in consciousness.
Bernard Williams presents a thought experiment appealing to theintuitions about what it is to be the same person in thefuture.[20] The thought experiment consists of two approaches to the same experiment.
For thefirst approach Williams suggests that suppose that there is some process by which subjecting two persons to it can result in the two persons have "exchanged" bodies. The process has put into the body of person B thememories,behavioral dispositions, andpsychological characteristics of the person who prior to undergoing the process belonged toperson A; and conversely withperson B. To show this one is to suppose that before undergoing the process person A and B are asked to which resulting person, A-Body-Person or B-Body-Person, they wish to receive a punishment and which a reward. Upon undergoing the process and receiving either the punishment or reward, it appears to that A-Body-Person expresses the memories of choosing who gets which treatment as if that person was person B; conversely with B-Body-Person.
This sort of approach to the thought experiment appears to show that since the person who expresses the psychological characteristics of person A to be person A, then intuition is thatpsychological continuity is the criterion for personal identity.
Thesecond approach is to suppose that someone is told that one will havememories erased and then one will betortured. Does one need to beafraid of being tortured? The intuition is that people will be afraid of being tortured, since it will still be one despite not having one's memories. Next, Williams asked one to consider several similarscenarios.[f]Intuition is that in all the scenarios one is to be afraid of being tortured, that it is still one's self despite having one's memories erased and receiving new memories. The last scenario isidentical to the first.[g]
In the first approach, intuition is to show that one'spsychological continuity is the criterion for personal identity, but in second approach, intuition is that it is one'sbodily continuity that is the criterion for personal identity. To resolve this conflict Williams feels one's intuition in the second approach is stronger and if he was given the choice of distributing a punishment and a reward he would want his body-person to receive the reward and the other body-person to receive the punishment, even if that other body-person has his memories.
Inpsychology, personal continuity, also calledpersonal persistence orself-continuity, is the uninterrupted connection concerning a particular person of their private life andpersonality. Personal continuity is the union affecting the facets arising from personality in order to avoiddiscontinuities from one moment oftime to another time.[h][21]
Personal continuity is an important part ofidentity; this is the process of ensuring that the qualities of the mind, such asself-awareness,sentience,sapience, and the ability toperceive the relationship between oneself and one's environment, are consistent from one moment to the next. Personal continuity is the property of a continuous and connected period of time[22][23] and is intimately related to do with a person's body or physical being in a singlefour-dimensionalcontinuum.[24]Associationism, a theory of how ideas combine in the mind, allows events or views to be associated with each other in the mind, thus leading to a form of learning. Associations can result fromcontiguity, similarity, or contrast. Through contiguity, one associates ideas or events that usually happen to occur at the same time. Some of these events form anautobiographical memory in which each is a personal representation of the general or specific events and personal facts.
Ego integrity is the psychological concept of theego's accumulated assurance of its capacity for order and meaning. Ego identity is the accruedconfidence that the innersameness and continuity prepared in the past are matched by the sameness and continuity of one's meaning for others, as evidenced in the promise of a career.Body and ego control organ expressions[25][26][27][28][29] and of the other attributes of the dynamics of a physical system to face theemotions ofego death[30][31] in circumstances which can summon, sometimes, anti-theonymisticself-abandonment.[25][32][33][34][35][36]
It has been argued from the nature ofsensations andideas that there is no such thing as a permanent identity.[37] Daniel Shapiro asserts that one of four major views on identity does not recognize a "permanent identity" and instead thinks of "thoughts without a thinker"—"a consciousness shell with drifting emotions and thoughts but no essence". According to him this view is based on the Buddhist concept ofanatta, "a continuously evolving flow of awareness."[38]Malcolm David Eckel states that "the self changes at every moment and has no permanent identity"[39]—it is a "constant process of changing or becoming;" a "fluid ever-changing self."[40]
David Hume undertook looking at themind–body problem. Hume also investigated a person's character, the relationship between human and animal nature, and the nature ofagency. Hume pointed out that we tend to think that we are the same person we were five years ago. Though we've changed in many respects, the same person appears present now as was present then. We might start thinking about which features can be changed without changing the underlying self. Hume denied a distinction between the various features of a person and the mysterious self that supposedly bears those features. When we beginintrospecting:
[We] always stumble on some particular perception or other.… I may venture to affirm of the rest of mankind, that they are nothing but abundle or collection of different perceptions which succeed each other with an inconceivable rapidity and are in perpetual flux and movement.[41]
It is plain, that in the course of our thinking, and in the constant revolution of our ideas, our imagination runs easily from one idea to any other that resembles it, and that this quality alone is to the fancy a sufficient bond and association. It is likewise evident that as the senses, in changing their objects, are necessitated to change them regularly, and take them as they lie contiguous to each other, the imagination must by long custom acquire the same method of thinking, and run along the parts of space and time in conceiving its objects.[42]
Note in particular that, in Hume's view, these perceptions do notbelong to anything. Hume, similar to theBuddha,[43] compares the soul to acommonwealth, which retains its identity not by virtue of some enduring core substance, but by being composed of many different, related, and yetconstantly changing elements.[44] The question of personal identity then becomes a matter of characterizing theloose cohesion[i] of one's personal experience.[j]
In short, what matters for Hume is not that 'identity' exists, but the fact that the relations of causation, contiguity, and resemblances obtain among the perceptions.Critics of Hume state that in order for the various states and processes of the mind to seem unified, there must be something which perceives their unity, the existence of which would be no less mysterious than a personal identity. Hume solves this by considering substance as engendered by thetogetherness of its properties.
The "no-self theory" holds that the selfcannot be reduced to a bundle because the concept of a self is incompatible with the idea of abundle.Propositionally, the idea of a bundle implies the notion of bodily or psychological relations that do not in fact exist.James Giles, a principal exponent of this view, argues that theno-self oreliminativist theory and the bundle orreductionist theory agree about the non-existence of asubstantive self. The reductionist theory, according to Giles, mistakenly resurrects the idea[k] of the self[45] in terms of various accounts aboutpsychological relations.[l] The no-self theory, on the other hand, "lets the self lie where it has fallen".[46] This is because the no-self theory rejects all theories of the self, even the bundle theory. On Giles' reading, Hume is actually a no-self theorist and it is a mistake to attribute to him a reductionist view like the bundle theory. Hume'sassertion that personal identity is afiction supports this reading, according to Giles.
The Buddhist view of personal identity is also a no-self theory rather than a reductionist theory, becausethe Buddha rejects attempts toreconstructions in terms of consciousness, feelings, or the body in notions of an eternal/permanent, unchanging Self,[47] since our thoughts, personalities and bodies are never the same from moment to moment, as specifically explained inŚūnyatā.[48]
According to this line of criticism, thesense of self is anevolutionary artifact,[m] which saves time in the circumstances it evolved for. But sense of self breaks down when considering some events such asmemory loss,[n]dissociative identity disorder,brain damage,brainwashing, and variousthought experiments.[49] When presented withimperfections in the intuitive sense of self and the consequences to this concept which rely on thestrict concept of self, a tendency tomend the concept occurs, possibly because ofcognitive dissonance.[o]
Open individualism is a term coined byDaniel Kolak that refers to the view in thephilosophy of self that there exists only one numericallyidenticalsubject, who is everyone at all times, in the past, present and future.[50]: 617 It is a theoretical solution to the question of personal identity, being contrasted with "Empty individualism", the view that personal identities correspond to a fixed pattern that instantaneously disappears with the passage of time, and "Closed individualism", the common view that personal identities are particular to subjects and yet survive over time.[50]: xxii
![]() | This section'sfactual accuracy isdisputed. Relevant discussion may be found on thetalk page. Please help to ensure that disputed statements arereliably sourced.(April 2024) (Learn how and when to remove this message) |
Since the 21st century, philosophers have also been using the methods of psychological science to better understand philosophical intuitions.[51] This empirical approach to philosophy is known asExperimental philosophy or "xPhi" for short. Studies in xPhi have found various psychological factors predict variance even in philosophers views about personal identity.[52]
Findings from xPhi suggest that moral intuitions may have a major influence on our intuitions about personal identity. For example, some experimental philosophers have found that when a person undergoes a dramatic change (e.g., traumatic brain injury), people are less likely to think that the person is the "same" after their dramatic change if the person became morally worse (as opposed to morally better).[53] Data like this support the "moral self hypothesis", that "moral traits are essential" to personal identity,[54] with some going as far as saying that, "When someone undergoes dramatic mental change, their numerical identity—whether they're the same person as they were before—can seem to become disrupted".
While the direction of change (e.g., moral improvement vs. moral deterioration) has been found to cause substantial shifts in peoples' judgments about personal identity, multiple studies find that none of these shifts constitute thinking that someone is numerically non-identical to the person they were before the change—such that the person before the change is one person and the person after the change is an entirely separate second person: when people were asked how many people are described in cases of dramatic moral change, the vast majority of answers were "one" (rather than two or more).[55] This aligns with more recent evidence that these shifts in intuitions about personal identity are about qualitative identity (i.e., how similar one is to a prior version of themselves) rather than numerical identity (i.e., whether there are two or more people described by cases in which a person undergoes a dramatic change).[56]
In this respect, I cannot compare the soul more properly to any thing than to a republic or commonwealth, in which the several members are united by the reciprocal ties of government and subordination, and give rise to other persons, who propagate the same republic in the incessant changes of its parts. And as the same individual republic may not only change its members, but also its laws and constitutions; in like manner the same person may vary his character and disposition, as well as his impressions and ideas, without losing his identity.