Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Jump to content
WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
Search

Nonsense

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Communication that lacks any coherent meaning
For other uses, seeNonsense (disambiguation).
Not to be confused withNon-science.
This articleneeds additional citations forverification. Please helpimprove this article byadding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.
Find sources: "Nonsense" – news ·newspapers ·books ·scholar ·JSTOR
(September 2020) (Learn how and when to remove this message)

Nonsense is a form ofcommunication, viaspeech,writing, or any othersymbolic system, that lacks any coherent meaning. In ordinary usage, nonsense is sometimes synonymous withabsurdity or theridiculous. Manypoets,novelists andsongwriters have used nonsense in their works, often creating entire works using it for reasons ranging from pure comic amusement or satire, to illustrating a point about language or reasoning. In the philosophy of language and philosophy of science, nonsense is distinguished fromsense or meaningfulness, and attempts have been made to come up with acoherent andconsistent method of distinguishing sense from nonsense. It is also an important field of study incryptography regarding separating asignal fromnoise.

Literary

[edit]
Main article:Literary nonsense

The phrase "Colorless green ideas sleep furiously" was coined byNoam Chomsky as an example of nonsense. However, this can easily be confused withpoetic symbolism. The individualwords make sense and are arranged according to propergrammatical rules, yet the result is nonsense. The inspiration for this attempt at creating verbal nonsense came from the idea ofcontradiction and seemingly irrelevant and/or incompatible characteristics, which conspire to make the phrase meaningless, but are open to interpretation. The phrase "the square root of Tuesday" operates on the latter principle. This principle is behind the inscrutability of thekōan "What is the sound of one hand clapping?", where one hand would presumably be insufficient for clapping without the intervention of another. [Editor’s note: It is possible to imagine a context where case-sensitive word-strings such as “Colorless green ideas sleep furiously” could be meaningfully used as a passphrase to decrypt a digital file. This one counterfactual suggests that both literary meaning and nonsense are dependent upon the particular “language-game” in which words (or characters) are used or misused. (See Wittgenstein’sPhilosophical Investigations, §23.][citation needed][1]

Verse

[edit]

Jabberwocky, apoem (ofnonsense verse) found inThrough the Looking-Glass, and What Alice Found There byLewis Carroll (1871), is a nonsense poem written in the English language. The wordjabberwocky is also occasionally used as a synonym of nonsense.[2]

A Book of Nonsense (c. 1875 James Miller edition) by Edward Lear

Nonsense verse is the verse form of literary nonsense, a genre that can manifest in many other ways. Its best-known exponent isEdward Lear, author ofThe Owl and the Pussycat and hundreds oflimericks.

Nonsense verse is part of a long line of tradition predating Lear: thenursery rhymeHey Diddle Diddle could also be termed a nonsense verse. There are also some works whichappear to be nonsense verse, but actually are not, such as the popular 1940s songMairzy Doats.

Lewis Carroll, seeking a nonsense riddle, once posed the questionHow is araven like a writing desk?. Someone answered him,BecausePoe wrote on both. However, there are other possible answers (e.g.both have inkyquills).

Examples

[edit]

The first verse ofJabberwocky byLewis Carroll;

'Twas brillig, and the slithy toves
Did gyre and gimble in the wabe;
All mimsy were the borogoves,
And the mome raths outgrabe.

The first four lines ofOn the Ning Nang Nong bySpike Milligan;[3]

On the Ning Nang Nong
Where the cows go Bong!
and the monkeys all say BOO!
There's a Nong Nang Ning

The first verse ofSpirk Troll-Derisive byJames Whitcomb Riley;[4]

The Crankadox leaned o'er the edge of the moon,
And wistfully gazed on the sea
Where the Gryxabodill madly whistled a tune
To the air of "Ti-fol-de-ding-dee."

The first four lines ofThe Mayor of Scuttleton byMary Mapes Dodge;[4]

The Mayor of Scuttleton burned his nose
Trying to warm his copper toes;
He lost his money and spoiled his will
By signing his name with an icicle quill;

Oh Freddled Gruntbuggly byProstetnic Vogon Jeltz; a creation ofDouglas Adams

Oh freddled gruntbuggly,
Thy micturations are to me
As plurdled gabbleblotchits on a lurgid bee.
Groop I implore thee, my foonting turlingdromes,
And hooptiously drangle me with crinkly bindlewurdles,
Or I will rend thee in the gobberwarts
With my blurglecruncheon, see if I don't!

Philosophy of language and of science

[edit]
Further information:Sense

In thephilosophy of language and thephilosophy of science, nonsense refers to a lack ofsense ormeaning. Different technical definitions of meaning delineate sense from nonsense.

Logical positivism

[edit]
Further information:Logical positivism

Wittgenstein

[edit]
Further information:Ludwig Wittgenstein

InLudwig Wittgenstein's writings, the word "nonsense" carries a special technical meaning which differs significantly from the normal use of the word. In this sense, "nonsense" does not refer to meaningless gibberish, but rather to the lack of sense in the context ofsense and reference. In this context, logicaltautologies, and purely mathematical propositions may be regarded as "nonsense". For example, "1+1=2" is a nonsensical proposition.[5] Wittgenstein wrote inTractatus Logico Philosophicus that some of the propositions contained in his own book should be regarded as nonsense.[6] Used in this way, "nonsense" does not necessarily carry negative connotations.

Disguised Epistemic Nonsense

[edit]

InLudwig Wittgenstein’s later work,Philosophical Investigations (PI §464), he says that “My aim is: to teach you to pass from a piece of disguised nonsense to something that is patent nonsense.” In his remarksOn Certainty (OC), he considersG. E. Moore’s “Proof of an External World” as an example of disguised epistemic nonsense. Moore’s “proof” is essentially an attempt to assert the truth of the sentence ‘Here is one hand’ as a paradigm case of genuine knowledge. He does this during a lecture before The British Academy where the existence of his hand is so obvious as to appear indubitable. If Moore does indeedknow that he has a hand, thenphilosophical skepticism (formerly calledidealism) must be false. (cf. Schönbaumsfeld (2020).

Wittgenstein however shows that Moore’s attempt fails because his proof tries to solve a pseudo-problem that is patently nonsensical. Moore mistakenly assumes that syntactically correct sentences are meaningful regardless of how one uses them. In Wittgenstein’s view, linguistic meaning for the most part is the way sentences are used in various contexts to accomplish certain goals (PI §43). J. L. Austin likewise notes that "It is, of course, not really correct that a sentence everis a statement: rather, it isused inmaking a statement, and the statement itself is a 'logical construction' out of the makings of statements" (Austin 1962, p1, note1). Disguised epistemic nonsense therefore is themisuse of ordinary declarative sentences in philosophical contexts where they seem meaningful but produce little or nothing of significance (cf.Contextualism). Moore’s unintentional misuse of ‘Here is one hand’ thus fails to state anything that his audience could possibly understand in the context of his lecture.

According to Wittgenstein, such propositional sentences instead express fundamental beliefs that function as non-cognitive “hinges”. Such hinges establish the rules by which the language-game of doubt and certainty is played. Wittgenstein points out that “If I want the door to turn the hinges must stay put” (OC §341-343).[6] In a 1968 article titled “Pretence”, Robert Caldwell states that: “A general doubt is simply a groundless one, for it fails to respect the conceptual structure of the practice in which doubt is sometimes legitimate” (Caldwell 1968, p49). "If you are not certain of any fact," Wittgenstein notes, "you cannot be certain of the meaning of your words either" (OC §114). Truth-functionally speaking, Moore’s attempted assertion and the skeptic’s denial are epistemically useless. "Neither the question nor the assertion makes sense" (OC §10). In other words,bothphilosophical realism and its negation,philosophical skepticism, are nonsense (OC §37&58). Both bogus theories violate the rules of the epistemic game that make genuine doubt and certainty meaningful. Caldwell concludes that: “The concepts of certainty and doubt apply to our judgments only when the sense of what we judge is firmly established” (Caldwell, p57).

The broader implication is that classical philosophical “problems” may be little more than complicated semantic illusions that are empirically unsolvable (cf. Schönbaumsfeld 2016). They arise when semantically correct sentences are misused in epistemic contexts thus creating the illusion of meaning. With some mental effort however, they can be dissolved in such a way that a rational person can justifiably ignore them. According to Wittgenstein, "It is not our aim to refine or complete the system of rules for the use of our words in unheard-of ways. For the clarity that we are aiming at is indeed complete clarity. But this simply means that the philosophical problems should completely disappear" (PI §133). The net effect is to expose a “A whole cloud of philosophy condensed into a drop of grammar” (PI p222).

In contrast to the above Wittgensteinian approach to nonsense, Cornman, Lehrer and Pappas argue in their textbook,Philosophical Problems and Arguments: An Introduction (PP&A) that philosophical skepticism is perfectly meaningful in thesemantic sense. It is only in theepistemic sense that it seems nonsensical. For example, the sentence ‘Worms integrate the moon by C# when moralizing to rescind apples’ is neither true nor false and therefore is semantic nonsense. Epistemic nonsense, however, is perfectly grammatical and semantical. It justappears to be preposterously false. When the skeptic boldly asserts the sentence [x]: ‘We know nothing whatsoever’ then:

“It is not that the sentence asserts nothing; on the contrary, it is because the sentence asserts something [that seems] patently false…. The sentence uttered is perfectly meaningful; what is nonsensical and meaningless is the fact that the person [a skeptic] has uttered it. To put the matter another way, we can make sense of the sentence [x]; we know what it asserts. But we cannot make sense of the man uttering it; we do not understand why he would utter it. Thus, when we use terms like ‘nonsense’ and ‘meaningless’ in the epistemic sense, the correct use of them requires only that what is uttered seem absurdly false. Of course, to seem preposterously false, the sentence must assert something, and thus be either true or false.” (PP&A, 60).

Keith Lehrer makes a similar argument in part VI of his monograph, “Why Not Scepticism?” (WNS 1971). A Wittgensteinian, however, might respond that Lehrer and Moore make the same mistake. Both assume that it is the sentence [x] that is doing the “asserting”, not just the philosopher’s misuse of it in the wrong context.Both Moore’s attempted “assertion”and the skeptic’s “denial” of ‘Here is one hand’ in the context of the British Academy are preposterous. Therefore, both claims are epistemic nonsense disguised in meaningful syntax. “[T]he mistake here” according to Caldwell, “lies in thinking that [epistemic] criteria provide us with certainty when they actually provide sense” (Caldwell p53). No one, including philosophers, has special dispensation from committing this semantic fallacy.

“The real discovery,” according to Wittgenstein, “is the one that makes me capable of stopping doing philosophy when I want to.—The one that gives philosophy peace, so that it is no longer tormented by questions which bring itself in question…. There is nota philosophical method, though there are indeed  methods, like different therapies” (PI §133). He goes on to say that “The philosopher's  treatment of a question is like the treatment of an illness” (PI §255).

Leonardo Vittorio Arena

[edit]

Starting from Wittgenstein, but through an original perspective, the Italian philosopher Leonardo Vittorio Arena, in his bookNonsense as the meaning, highlights this positive meaning of nonsense to undermine every philosophical conception which does not take note of the absolute lack of meaning of the world and life. Nonsense implies the destruction of all views or opinions, on the wake of the Indian Buddhist philosopher Nagarjuna. In the name of nonsense, it is finally refused the conception of duality and the Aristotelian formal logic.

Cryptography

[edit]

The problem of distinguishing sense from nonsense is important incryptography and otherintelligence fields. For example, they need to distinguishsignal fromnoise.Cryptanalysts have devisedalgorithms to determine whether a given text is in fact nonsense or not. These algorithms typically analyze the presence of repetitions andredundancy in a text; in meaningful texts, certain frequently used words recur, for example,the,is andand in a text in theEnglish language. Arandom scattering of letters, punctuation marks and spaces do not exhibit these regularities.Zipf's law attempts to state this analysis mathematically. By contrast, cryptographers typically seek to make theircipher texts resemble random distributions, to avoid telltale repetitions and patterns which may give an opening for cryptanalysis.[citation needed]

It is harder for cryptographers to deal with the presence or absence of meaning in a text in which the level of redundancy and repetition ishigher than found innatural languages (for example, in the mysterious text of theVoynich manuscript).[citation needed]

Teaching machines to talk nonsense

[edit]
See also:SCIgen

Scientists have attempted to teach machines to produce nonsense. The Markov chain technique is one method which has been used to generate texts by algorithm and randomizing techniques that seem meaningful. Another method is sometimes called theMad Libs method: it involves creating templates for varioussentence structures and filling in the blanks withnoun phrases orverb phrases; these phrase-generation procedures can be looped to addrecursion, giving the output the appearance of greater complexity and sophistication.Racter was a computer program which generated nonsense texts by this method; however, Racter's book,The Policeman’s Beard is Half Constructed, proved to have been the product of heavy human editing of the program's output.

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1953).Philosophical Investigations (3rd ed.). Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell Ltd. pp. 11e.ISBN 0-631-14670-9.
  2. ^"the definition of Jabberwocky".Dictionary.com.
  3. ^"Top poetry is complete nonsense".BBC News. 10 October 1998.
  4. ^abA Nonsense Anthology. 1 November 2005 – via Project Gutenberg.
  5. ^Schroeder, Severin (2006).Wittgenstein: the way out of the fly-bottle. Polity. p. 110.ISBN 978-0-7456-2615-4.
  6. ^Biletzki, Anat and Anat Matar, "Ludwig Wittgenstein", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2008 Edition) "The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy"

6. A new branch of philosophy called “hinge epistemology” has sprouted from Wittgenstein’s remarksOn Certainty. SeeDuncan Pritchard,Crispin Wright,Daniele Moyal-Sharrock,et al. Whether Wittgenstein would have agreed with their interpretations of his work is debatable.

References

[edit]
  • Kahn, David,The Codebreakers (Scribner, 1996)ISBN 0-684-83130-9
  • Austin, J. L. (1962). "How to Do Things with Words",The William James Lectures delivered at Harvard University in 1955. Oxford, Clarendon Press.
  • Caldwell, Robert L., “Pretence” (Jan. 1968),Mind, New Series, Vol. 77, No. 305.
  • James Cornman, Keith Lehrer & George Pappas (PP&A 1992).Philosophical Problems and Arguments: An Introduction – 4th ed. Hackett Publishing Co., Inc., Indianapolis.
  • Lehrer, Keith (WNS 1971). “Why Not Scepticism?” part VI,Philosophical Forum, vol. II, 289-290.
  • Schönbaumsfeld, Genia (2016).The Illusion of Doubt. Oxford University Press,ISBN 978-0-19-878394-7
  • Schönbaumsfeld, Genia (2020). "G E Moore's Attempt to Refute Scepticism and Wittgenstein's Critique" video lecture. University of South Hampton. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=SINqcUocOAU.
  • Cohen, Roni and Idels, Ofer. (2024) "Israeli Nonsense: humor, globalization and vegetables during the early nineties," Humor.

External links

[edit]
Look uphokum in Wiktionary, the free dictionary.
Wikimedia Commons has media related toNonsense.
Wikiquote has quotations related toNonsense.
Authority control databases: NationalEdit this at Wikidata
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Nonsense&oldid=1268916894"
Categories:
Hidden categories:

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp