Insemantics, adonkey sentence is a sentence containing apronoun which is semanticallybound but syntactically free. They are a classic puzzle informal semantics andphilosophy of language because they are fullygrammatical and yet defy straightforward attempts to generate theirformal language equivalents. In order to explain how speakers are able to understand them, semanticists have proposed a variety of formalisms including systems ofdynamic semantics such asDiscourse representation theory. Their name comes from the example sentence "Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it", in which "it" acts asa donkey pronoun because it is semantically but not syntactically bound by the indefinitenoun phrase "a donkey". The phenomenon is known asdonkey anaphora.[a]
The prototypical donkey sentence, "Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it.", requires careful consideration for adequate description (though reading "each" in place of "every" does simplify the formal analysis). The donkey pronoun in this case is the wordit. Correctly translating this sentence will require using auniversal quantifier for the indefinite noun phrase "a donkey", rather than the expected existential quantifier.
The naive first attempt at translation given below is not a well-formed sentence, since the variable is leftfree in the predicate.[8]
It may be attempted to extend thescope of the existential quantifier to bind the free instance of, but it still does not give a correct translation.[8]
This translation is incorrect since it is already true if there exists any object that is not a donkey: Given any object to be substituted for, substituting any non-donkey object for makes thematerial conditional true (since itsantecedent is false), and so existential clause is true for every choice of.
A correct translation into first-order logic for the donkey sentence seems to be
,
indicating that indefinites must sometimes be interpreted as existential quantifiers, and other times as universal quantifiers.[8]
There is nothing wrong with donkey sentences: they are grammatically correct, they are well-formed and meaningful, and their syntax is regular. However, it is difficult to explain how donkey sentences produce their semantic results, and how those results generalize consistently with all other language use. If such an analysis were successful, it might allow a computer program to accurately translate natural language forms intological form.[9] It is unknown how natural language users agree – apparently effortlessly – on the meaning of sentences such as the examples.[citation needed]
It is usual to distinguish two main kinds of theories about the semantics of donkey pronouns. The most classical proposals fall within the so-calleddescription-theoretic approach, a label that is meant to encompass all the theories that treat the semantics of these pronouns as akin to, or derivative from, the semantics ofdefinite descriptions. The second main family of proposals goes by the namedynamic theories, and they model donkey anaphora – and anaphora in general – on the assumption that the meaning of a sentence lies in its potential to change the context (understood as the information shared by the participants in a conversation).[10]
This sectionneeds expansion. You can help byadding to it.(March 2020)
Description-theoretic approaches are theories of donkey pronouns in which definite descriptions play an important role. They were pioneered byGareth Evans's E-type approach,[11] which holds that donkey pronouns can be understood as referring terms whose reference is fixed by description.
For example, in "Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it.", the donkey pronoun "it" can be expanded as a definite description to yield "Every farmer who owns a donkey beats the donkey he/she owns." This expanded sentence can be interpreted along the lines of Russell'stheory of descriptions.[12]
Later authors have attributed an even larger role to definite descriptions, to the point of arguing that donkey pronouns have the semantics,[13][14] and even the syntax,[15] of definite descriptions. Approaches of the latter kind are usually calledD-type.
Donkey sentences became a major force in advancingsemantic research in the 1980s, with the introduction ofdiscourse representation theory (DRT). During that time, an effort was made to settle the inconsistencies which arose from the attempts to translate donkey sentences intofirst-order logic.
The solution thatDRT provides for the donkey sentence problem can be roughly outlined as follows: The common semantic function of non-anaphoricnoun phrases is the introduction of a newdiscourse referent, which is in turn available for the binding of anaphoric expressions. No quantifiers are introduced into the representation, thus overcoming the scope problem that the logical translations had.
Walter Burley, a medieval scholastic philosopher, introduced donkey sentences in the context of the theory ofsupposition theory, the medieval equivalent of reference theory.
^Cooper, Robin (1979). "The interpretation of pronouns". In Frank Heny; Helmut Schnelle (eds.).Syntax and Semantics 10: Selections from the third Gröningen roundtable. Academic Press.ISBN012613510X.
^Lewis, David (1975). "Adverbs of quantification". In Keenan, Edward L. (ed.).Formal Semantics of Natural Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.ISBN9780511897696 – via users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LewisQA.pdf.
Conway, L. and S. Crain. 'Donkey Anaphora in Child Grammar'. InProceedings of the North East Linguistics Society (NELS)25.University of Massachusetts Amherst, 1995.
Kanazawa, Makoto. 'Weak vs. Strong Readings of Donkey Sentences and Monotonicity Inference in a Dynamic Setting'.Linguistics and Philosophy17 (1994): 109–158.
Krifka, Manfred. 'Pragmatic Strengthening in Plural Predications and Donkey Sentences'. InProceedings from Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT)6. Ithaca, New York:Cornell University, 1996. Pages 136–153.
Lappin, Shalom. 'An Intensional Parametric Semantics for Vague Quantifiers'.Linguistics and Philosophy23 (2000): 599–620.
^In 2007, Adrian Brasoveanu published studies of donkey pronoun analogs inHindi, and analysis of complex andmodal versions of donkey pronouns in English.
Huang, C-T James.'Logical Form'. Chapter 3 inGovernment and Binding Theory and the Minimalist Program: Principles and Parameters in Syntactic Theory edited by Gert Webelhuth. Oxford and Cambridge:Blackwell Publishing, 1995. Pages 127–177.
Kitagawa, Yoshihisa.'Copying Variables'. Chapter 2 inFunctional Structure(s), Form and Interpretation: Perspectives from East Asian Languages. Edited by Yen-hui Audrey Li and others.Routledge, 2003. Pages 28–64.