Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Jump to content
WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
Search

Axiom of infinity

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Axiom of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory
This articleneeds additional citations forverification. Please helpimprove this article byadding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.
Find sources: "Axiom of infinity" – news ·newspapers ·books ·scholar ·JSTOR
(October 2019) (Learn how and when to remove this message)

Inaxiomatic set theory and the branches ofmathematics andphilosophy that use it, theaxiom of infinity is one of theaxioms ofZermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It guarantees the existence of at least oneinfinite set, namely a set containing thenatural numbers. It was first published byErnst Zermelo as part of hisset theory in 1908.[1]

Formal statement

[edit]

Usingfirst-order logic primitive symbols, the axiom can be expressed as follows:[2]

I (o (oI ¬n (no))  x (xIy (yI  a (ay(ax  a=x))))).{\displaystyle \exists \mathrm {I} \ (\exists o\ (o\in \mathrm {I} \ \land \lnot \exists n\ (n\in o))\ \land \ \forall x\ (x\in \mathrm {I} \Rightarrow \exists y\ (y\in \mathrm {I} \ \land \ \forall a\ (a\in y\Leftrightarrow (a\in x\ \lor \ a=x))))).}

In English, this sentence means: "there exists aset𝐈 such that theempty set is an element of it, and for every elementx{\displaystyle x} of𝐈, there exists an elementy{\displaystyle y} of𝐈 such thatx{\displaystyle x} is an element ofy{\displaystyle y}, the elements ofx{\displaystyle x} are also elements ofy{\displaystyle y}, and nothing else is an element ofy{\displaystyle y}."

This sentence can be abbreviated in set-builder notation as:

I(Ix(xI(x{x})I)).{\displaystyle \exists \mathrm {I} \,(\varnothing \in \mathrm {I} \,\land \,\forall x\,(x\in \mathrm {I} \Rightarrow \,(x\cup \{x\})\in \mathrm {I} )).}

Some mathematicians may call a set built this way aninductive set.

Interpretation and consequences

[edit]

This axiom is closely related to thevon Neumann construction of the natural numbers in set theory, in which thesuccessor ofx is defined asx ∪ {x}. Ifx is a set, then it follows from the other axioms of set theory that this successor is also a uniquely defined set. Successors are used to define the usual set-theoretic encoding of thenatural numbers. In this encoding, zero is the empty set:

0 = {}.

The number 1 is the successor of 0:

1 = 0 ∪ {0} = {} ∪ {0} = {0} = {{}}.

Likewise, 2 is the successor of 1:

2 = 1 ∪ {1} = {0} ∪ {1} = {0, 1} = { {}, {{}} },

and so on:

3 = {0, 1, 2} = { {}, {{}}, {{}, {{}}} };
4 = {0, 1, 2, 3} = { {}, {{}}, { {}, {{}} }, { {}, {{}}, {{}, {{}}} } }.

A consequence of this definition is that every natural number is equal to the set of all preceding natural numbers. The count of elements in each set, at the top level, is the same as the represented natural number, and the nesting depth of the most deeply nested empty set {}, including its nesting in the set that represents the number of which it is a part, is also equal to the natural number that the set represents.

This construction forms the natural numbers. However, the other axioms are insufficient to prove the existence of the set ofall natural numbers,N0{\displaystyle \mathbb {N} _{0}}. Therefore, its existence is taken as an axiom – the axiom of infinity. This axiom asserts that there is a setI that contains 0 and isclosed under the operation of taking the successor; that is, for each element ofI, the successor of that element is also inI.

Thus the essence of the axiom is:

There is a set,I, that includes all the natural numbers.

The axiom of infinity is also one of thevon Neumann–Bernays–Gödel axioms.

Extracting the natural numbers from the infinite set

[edit]

The infinite setI is a superset of the natural numbers. To show that the natural numbers themselves constitute a set, theaxiom schema of specification can be applied to remove unwanted elements, leaving the setN of all natural numbers. This set is unique by theaxiom of extensionality.

To extract the natural numbers, we need a definition of which sets are natural numbers. The natural numbers can be defined in a way that does not assume any axioms except theaxiom of extensionality and theaxiom of induction—a natural number is either zero or a successor and each of its elements is either zero or a successor of another of its elements. In formal language, the definition says:

n(nN([n=k(n=k{k})]mn[m=kn(m=k{k})])).{\displaystyle \forall n(n\in \mathbf {N} \iff ([n=\emptyset \,\,\lor \,\,\exists k(n=k\cup \{k\})]\,\,\land \,\,\forall m\in n[m=\emptyset \,\,\lor \,\,\exists k\in n(m=k\cup \{k\})])).}

Or, even more formally:

n(nN([k(¬kn)kj(jn(jkj=k))]{\displaystyle \forall n(n\in \mathbf {N} \iff ([\forall k(\lnot k\in n)\lor \exists k\forall j(j\in n\iff (j\in k\lor j=k))]\;\land }
m(mn[k(¬km)k(knj(jm(jkj=k)))]))).{\displaystyle \forall m(m\in n\Rightarrow [\forall k(\lnot k\in m)\lor \exists k(k\in n\land \forall j(j\in m\iff (j\in k\lor j=k)))]))).}

Alternative method

[edit]

An alternative method is the following. LetΦ(x){\displaystyle \Phi (x)} be the formula that says "x is inductive"; i.e.Φ(x)=(xy(yx(y{y}x))){\displaystyle \Phi (x)=(\emptyset \in x\wedge \forall y(y\in x\to (y\cup \{y\}\in x)))}. Informally, what we will do is take the intersection of all inductive sets. More formally, we wish to prove the existence of a unique setW{\displaystyle W} such that

x(xWI(Φ(I)xI)).{\displaystyle \forall x(x\in W\leftrightarrow \forall I(\Phi (I)\to x\in I)).} (*)

For existence, we will use the Axiom of Infinity combined with theAxiom schema of specification. LetI{\displaystyle I} be an inductive set guaranteed by the Axiom of Infinity. Then we use the axiom schema of specification to define our setW={xI:J(Φ(J)xJ)}{\displaystyle W=\{x\in I:\forall J(\Phi (J)\to x\in J)\}} – i.e.W{\displaystyle W} is the set of all elements ofI{\displaystyle I}, which also happen to be elements of every other inductive set. This clearly satisfies the hypothesis of (*), since ifxW{\displaystyle x\in W}, thenx{\displaystyle x} is in every inductive set, and ifx{\displaystyle x} is in every inductive set, it is in particular inI{\displaystyle I}, so it must also be inW{\displaystyle W}.

For uniqueness, first note that any set that satisfies (*) is itself inductive, since 0 is in all inductive sets, and if an elementx{\displaystyle x} is in all inductive sets, then by the inductive property so is its successor. Thus if there were another setW{\displaystyle W'} that satisfied (*) we would have thatWW{\displaystyle W'\subseteq W} sinceW{\displaystyle W} is inductive, andWW{\displaystyle W\subseteq W'} sinceW{\displaystyle W'} is inductive. ThusW=W{\displaystyle W=W'}. Letω{\displaystyle \omega } denote this unique element.

This definition is convenient because theprinciple of induction immediately follows: IfIω{\displaystyle I\subseteq \omega } is inductive, then alsoωI{\displaystyle \omega \subseteq I}, so thatI=ω{\displaystyle I=\omega }.

Both these methods produce systems that satisfy the axioms ofsecond-order arithmetic, since theaxiom of power set allows us to quantify over thepower set ofω{\displaystyle \omega }, as insecond-order logic. Thus they both completely determineisomorphic systems, and since they are isomorphic under theidentity map, they must in fact beequal.

An apparently weaker version

[edit]

Some old texts use an apparently weaker version of the axiom of infinity, to wit:

x(y(yx)y(yxz(zxyz))).{\displaystyle \exists x\,(\exists y\,(y\in x)\,\land \,\forall y(y\in x\,\rightarrow \,\exists z(z\in x\,\land \,y\subsetneq z)))\,.}

This says thatx is non-empty and for every elementy ofx there is another elementz ofx such thaty is a subset ofz andy is not equal toz. This implies thatx is an infinite set without saying much about its structure. However, with the help of the other axioms of ZF, we can show that this implies the existence of ω. First, if we take the powerset of any infinite setx, then that powerset will contain elements that are subsets ofx of every finitecardinality (among other subsets ofx). Proving the existence of those finite subsets may require either the axiom of separation or the axioms of pairing and union. Then we can apply the axiom of replacement to replace each element of that powerset ofx by theinitialordinal number of the same cardinality (or zero, if there is no such ordinal). The result will be an infinite set of ordinals. Then we can apply the axiom of union to that to get an ordinal greater than or equal to ω.

Independence

[edit]

The axiom of infinity cannot be proved from the other axioms of ZFC if they are consistent. (To see why, note that ZFC{\displaystyle \vdash } Con(ZFC − Infinity) and use Gödel'sSecond incompleteness theorem.)

The negation of the axiom of infinity cannot be derived from the rest of the axioms of ZFC, if they are consistent. (This is tantamount to saying that ZFC is consistent, if the other axioms are consistent.) Thus, ZFC implies neither the axiom of infinity nor its negation and is compatible with either.

Indeed, using thevon Neumann universe, we can build a model of ZFC − Infinity + (¬Infinity). It isVω{\displaystyle V_{\omega }\!}, the class ofhereditarily finite sets, with the inherited membership relation. Note that if the axiom of the empty set is not taken as a part of this system (since it can be derived from ZF + Infinity), then theempty domain also satisfies ZFC − Infinity + ¬Infinity, as all of its axioms are universally quantified, and thus trivially satisfied if no set exists.

The cardinality of the set of natural numbers,aleph null (0{\displaystyle \aleph _{0}}), has many of the properties of alarge cardinal. Thus the axiom of infinity is sometimes regarded as the firstlarge cardinal axiom, and conversely large cardinal axioms are sometimes called[by whom?] stronger axioms of infinity.

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^Zermelo:Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre, 1907, in: Mathematische Annalen 65 (1908), 261-281; Axiom des Unendlichen p. 266f.
  2. ^"Metamath Proof Explorer".Metamath.
History
Branches of mathematics
Formalizations of infinity
Geometries
Mathematicians
Overview
Venn diagram of set intersection
Axioms
Operations
  • Concepts
  • Methods
Set types
Theories
Set theorists
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Axiom_of_infinity&oldid=1273600229"
Categories:
Hidden categories:

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp