Philosophy of science is the branch ofphilosophy concerned with the foundations,methods, and implications ofscience. Amongst its central questions arethe difference between science and non-science, thereliability of scientific theories, and the ultimate purpose and meaning of science as a human endeavour. Philosophy of science focuses onmetaphysical,epistemic andsemantic aspects of scientific practice, and overlaps withmetaphysics,ontology,logic, andepistemology, for example, when it explores the relationship between science and the concept oftruth. Philosophy of science is both a theoretical andempirical discipline, relying on philosophical theorising as well asmeta-studies of scientific practice. Ethical issues such asbioethics andscientific misconduct are often consideredethics orscience studies rather than the philosophy of science.
Many of the central problems concerned with the philosophy of science lack contemporary consensus, including whether science can infertruth about unobservable entities andwhether inductive reasoning can be justified as yielding definite scientific knowledge. Philosophers of science also consider philosophical problems within particular sciences (such asbiology,physics and social sciences such aseconomics andpsychology). Some philosophers of science also use contemporary results in science to reach conclusions aboutphilosophy itself.
While philosophical thought pertaining to science dates back at least to the time ofAristotle, the general philosophy of science emerged as a distinct discipline only in the 20th century following thelogical positivist movement, which aimed to formulate criteria for ensuring all philosophical statements' meaningfulness and objectively assessing them.Karl Popper criticized logical positivism and helped establish a modern set of standards forscientific methodology.Thomas Kuhn's 1962 bookThe Structure of Scientific Revolutions was also formative, challenging the view ofscientific progress as the steady, cumulative acquisition of knowledge based on a fixed method of systematic experimentation and instead arguing that any progress is relative to a "paradigm", the set of questions, concepts, and practices that define a scientific discipline in a particular historical period.
Subsequently, thecoherentist approach to science, in which a theory is validated if it makes sense of observations as part of a coherent whole, became prominent due toW. V. Quine and others. Some thinkers such asStephen Jay Gould seek to ground science inaxiomatic assumptions, such as theuniformity of nature. A vocal minority of philosophers, andPaul Feyerabend in particular, argue against the existence of the "scientific method", so all approaches to science should be allowed, including explicitlysupernatural ones. Another approach to thinking about science involves studying howknowledge is created from asociological perspective, an approach represented by scholars likeDavid Bloor andBarry Barnes. Finally, a tradition incontinental philosophy approaches science from the perspective of a rigorous analysis of human experience.
Philosophies of the particular sciences range from questions about the nature oftime raised by Einstein'sgeneral relativity, to the implications ofeconomics forpublic policy. A central theme is whether the terms of one scientific theory can be intra- or intertheoreticallyreduced to the terms of another. Can chemistry be reduced to physics, or can sociology be reduced to individualpsychology? The general questions of philosophy of science also arise with greater specificity in some particular sciences. For instance, the question of the validity of scientific reasoning is seen in a different guise in thefoundations of statistics. The question of what counts as science and what should be excluded arises as a life-or-death matter in thephilosophy of medicine. Additionally, the philosophies of biology, psychology, and thesocial sciences explore whether the scientific studies ofhuman nature can achieve objectivity or are inevitably shaped byvalues and by social relations.
Introduction
editDefining science
editDistinguishing between science andnon-science is referred to as the demarcation problem. For example, shouldpsychoanalysis,creation science, andhistorical materialism be considered pseudosciences?Karl Popper called this the central question in the philosophy of science.[1] However, no unified account of the problem has won acceptance among philosophers, and some regard the problem as unsolvable or uninteresting.[2][3]Martin Gardner has argued for the use of aPotter Stewart standard ("I know it when I see it") for recognizing pseudoscience.[4]
Early attempts by thelogical positivists grounded science in observation while non-science was non-observational and hence meaningless.[5] Popper argued that the central property of science isfalsifiability. That is, every genuinely scientific claim is capable of being proven false, at least in principle.[6]
An area of study or speculation that masquerades as science in an attempt to claim a legitimacy that it would not otherwise be able to achieve is referred to aspseudoscience,fringe science, orjunk science.[7][8][9][10][11][12][13] PhysicistRichard Feynman coined the term "cargo cult science" for cases in which researchers believe they are doing science because their activities have the outward appearance of it but actually lack the "kind of utter honesty" that allows their results to be rigorously evaluated.[14]
Scientific explanation
editA closely related question is what counts as a good scientific explanation. In addition to providing predictions about future events, society often takes scientific theories to provideexplanations for events that occur regularly or have already occurred. Philosophers have investigated the criteria by which a scientific theory can be said to have successfully explained a phenomenon, as well as what it means to say a scientific theory hasexplanatory power.[citation needed]
One early and influential account of scientific explanation is thedeductive-nomological model. It says that a successful scientific explanation must deduce the occurrence of the phenomena in question from ascientific law.[15] This view has been subjected to substantial criticism, resulting in several widely acknowledged counterexamples to the theory.[16] It is especially challenging to characterize what is meant by an explanation when the thing to be explained cannot be deduced from any law because it is a matter of chance, or otherwise cannot be perfectly predicted from what is known.Wesley Salmon developed a model in which a good scientific explanation must be statistically relevant to the outcome to be explained.[17][18] Others have argued that the key to a good explanation is unifying disparate phenomena or providing a causal mechanism.[18]
Justifying science
editAlthough it is often taken for granted, it is not at all clear how one can infer the validity of a general statement from a number of specific instances or infer the truth of a theory from a series of successful tests.[19] For example, a chicken observes that each morning the farmer comes and gives it food, for hundreds of days in a row. The chicken may therefore useinductive reasoning to infer that the farmer will bring foodevery morning. However, one morning, the farmer comes and kills the chicken. How is scientific reasoning more trustworthy than the chicken's reasoning?
One approach is to acknowledge that induction cannot achieve certainty, but observing more instances of a general statement can at least make the general statement moreprobable. So the chicken would be right to conclude from all those mornings that it is likely the farmer will come with food again the next morning, even if it cannot be certain. However, there remain difficult questions about the process of interpreting any given evidence into a probability that the general statement is true. One way out of these particular difficulties is to declare that all beliefs about scientific theories aresubjective, or personal, and correct reasoning is merely about how evidence should change one's subjective beliefs over time.[19]
Some argue that what scientists do is not inductive reasoning at all but ratherabductive reasoning, or inference to the best explanation. In this account, science is not about generalizing specific instances but rather about hypothesizing explanations for what is observed. As discussed in the previous section, it is not always clear what is meant by the "best explanation".Ockham's razor, which counsels choosing thesimplest available explanation, thus plays an important role in some versions of this approach. To return to the example of the chicken, would it be simpler to suppose that the farmer cares about it and will continue taking care of it indefinitely or that the farmer is fattening it up for slaughter? Philosophers have tried to make thisheuristic principle more precise regarding theoreticalparsimony or other measures. Yet, although various measures of simplicity have been brought forward as potential candidates, it is generally accepted that there is no such thing as a theory-independent measure of simplicity. In other words, there appear to be as many different measures of simplicity as there are theories themselves, and the task of choosing between measures of simplicity appears to be every bit as problematic as the job of choosing between theories.[20]Nicholas Maxwell has argued for some decades that unity rather than simplicity is the key non-empirical factor in influencing the choice of theory in science, persistent preference for unified theories in effect committing science to the acceptance of a metaphysical thesis concerning unity in nature. In order to improve this problematic thesis, it needs to be represented in the form of a hierarchy of theses, each thesis becoming more insubstantial as one goes up the hierarchy.[21]
Observation inseparable from theory
editWhen making observations, scientists look through telescopes, study images on electronic screens, record meter readings, and so on. Generally, on a basic level, they can agree on what they see, e.g., the thermometer shows 37.9 degrees C. But, if these scientists have different ideas about the theories that have been developed to explain these basic observations, they may disagree about what they are observing. For example, beforeAlbert Einstein'sgeneral theory of relativity, observers would have likely interpreted an image of theEinstein cross as five different objects in space. In light of that theory, however, astronomers will tell you that there are actually only two objects, one in the center andfour different images of a second object around the sides. Alternatively, if other scientists suspect that something is wrong with the telescope and only one object is actually being observed, they are operating under yet another theory. Observations that cannot be separated from theoretical interpretation are said to betheory-laden.[22]
All observation involves bothperception andcognition. That is, one does not make an observation passively, but rather is actively engaged in distinguishing the phenomenon being observed from surrounding sensory data. Therefore, observations are affected by one's underlying understanding of the way in which the world functions, and that understanding may influence what is perceived, noticed, or deemed worthy of consideration. In this sense, it can be argued that all observation is theory-laden.[22]
The purpose of science
editShould science aim to determine ultimate truth, or are there questions that sciencecannot answer?Scientific realists claim that science aims at truth and that one ought to regardscientific theories as true, approximately true, or likely true. Conversely,scientific anti-realists argue that science does not aim (or at least does not succeed) at truth, especially truth aboutunobservables like electrons or other universes.[23]Instrumentalists argue that scientific theories should only be evaluated on whether they are useful. In their view, whether theories are true or not is beside the point, because the purpose of science is to make predictions and enable effective technology.
Realists often point to the success of recent scientific theories as evidence for the truth (or near truth) of current theories.[24][25] Antirealists point to either the many false theories in thehistory of science,[26][27] epistemic morals,[28] the success of falsemodeling assumptions,[29] or widely termedpostmodern criticisms of objectivity as evidence against scientific realism.[24] Antirealists attempt to explain the success of scientific theories without reference to truth.[30] Some antirealists claim that scientific theories aim at being accurate only about observable objects and argue that their success is primarily judged by that criterion.[28]
Real patterns
editThe notion ofreal patterns has been propounded, notably by philosopherDaniel C. Dennett, as an intermediate position between strong realism andeliminative materialism.[jargon] This concept delves into the investigation of patterns observed in scientific phenomena to ascertain whether they signify underlying truths or are mere constructs of human interpretation. Dennett provides a unique ontological account concerning real patterns, examining the extent to which these recognized patterns have predictive utility and allow for efficient compression of information.[31]
The discourse on real patterns extends beyond philosophical circles, finding relevance in various scientific domains. For example, in biology, inquiries into real patterns seek to elucidate the nature of biological explanations, exploring how recognized patterns contribute to a comprehensive understanding of biological phenomena.[32] Similarly, in chemistry, debates around the reality of chemical bonds as real patterns continue.[33]
Evaluation of real patterns also holds significance in broader scientific inquiries. Researchers, like Tyler Millhouse, propose criteria for evaluating the realness of a pattern, particularly in the context of universal patterns and the human propensity to perceive patterns, even where there might be none.[34] This evaluation is pivotal in advancing research in diverse fields, from climate change to machine learning, where recognition and validation of real patterns in scientific models play a crucial role.[35]
Values and science
editValues intersect with science in different ways. There are epistemic values that mainly guide the scientific research. The scientific enterprise is embedded in particular culture and values through individual practitioners. Values emerge from science, both as product and process and can be distributed among several cultures in the society. When it comes to the justification of science in the sense of general public participation by single practitioners, science plays the role of a mediator between evaluating the standards and policies of society and its participating individuals, wherefore science indeed falls victim to vandalism and sabotage adapting the means to the end.[36]
If it is unclear what counts as science, how the process of confirming theories works, and what the purpose of science is, there is considerable scope for values and other social influences to shape science. Indeed,values can play a role ranging from determining which research gets funded to influencing which theories achieve scientific consensus.[37] For example, in the 19th century, cultural values held by scientists about race shaped research onevolution, and values concerningsocial class influenced debates onphrenology (considered scientific at the time).[38]Feminist philosophers of science, sociologists of science, and others explore how social values affect science.
History
editPre-modern
editThe origins of philosophy of science trace back toPlato andAristotle,[39] who distinguished the forms of approximate and exact reasoning, set out the threefold scheme ofabductive,deductive, andinductive inference, and also analyzed reasoning byanalogy. The eleventh century Arab polymathIbn al-Haytham (known in Latin asAlhazen) conducted his research in optics by way of controlled experimental testing and appliedgeometry, especially in his investigations into the images resulting from thereflection andrefraction of light.Roger Bacon (1214–1294), an English thinker and experimenter heavily influenced by al-Haytham, is recognized by many to be the father of modern scientific method.[40] His view that mathematics was essential to a correct understanding of natural philosophy is considered to have been 400 years ahead of its time.[41]
Modern
editFrancis Bacon (no direct relation toRoger Bacon, who lived 300 years earlier) was a seminal figure in philosophy of science at the time of theScientific Revolution. In his workNovum Organum (1620)—an allusion to Aristotle'sOrganon—Bacon outlined a newsystem of logic to improve upon the old philosophical process ofsyllogism. Bacon's method relied on experimentalhistories to eliminate alternative theories.[42] In 1637,René Descartes established a new framework for grounding scientific knowledge in his treatise,Discourse on Method, advocating the central role ofreason as opposed to sensory experience. By contrast, in 1713, the 2nd edition ofIsaac Newton'sPhilosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica argued that "... hypotheses ... have no place in experimental philosophy. In this philosophy[,] propositions are deduced from the phenomena and rendered general by induction."[43] This passage influenced a "later generation of philosophically-inclined readers to pronounce a ban on causal hypotheses in natural philosophy".[43] In particular, later in the 18th century,David Hume would famously articulateskepticism about the ability of science to determinecausality and gave a definitive formulation of theproblem of induction, though both theses would be contested by the end of the 18th century by Immanuel Kant in hisCritique of Pure Reason andMetaphysical Foundations of Natural Science. In 19th centuryAuguste Comte made a major contribution to the theory of science. The 19th century writings ofJohn Stuart Mill are also considered important in the formation of current conceptions of the scientific method, as well as anticipating later accounts of scientific explanation.[44]
Logical positivism
editInstrumentalism[jargon] became popular among physicists around the turn of the 20th century, after which logical positivism defined the field for several decades. Logical positivism accepts only testable statements as meaningful, rejects metaphysical interpretations, and embracesverificationism (a set oftheories of knowledge that combineslogicism,empiricism, andlinguistics to ground philosophy on a basis consistent with examples from theempirical sciences). Seeking to overhaul all of philosophy and convert it to a newscientific philosophy,[45] theBerlin Circle and theVienna Circle propounded logical positivism in the late 1920s.
InterpretingLudwig Wittgenstein's earlyphilosophy of language, logical positivists identified a verifiability principle or criterion of cognitive meaningfulness. FromBertrand Russell's logicism they sought reduction of mathematics to logic. They also embraced Russell'slogical atomism,Ernst Mach'sphenomenalism—whereby the mind knows only actual or potential sensory experience, which is the content of all sciences, whether physics or psychology—andPercy Bridgman'soperationalism. Thereby, only theverifiable was scientific andcognitively meaningful, whereas the unverifiable was unscientific, cognitively meaningless "pseudostatements"—metaphysical, emotive, or such—not worthy of further review by philosophers, who were newly tasked to organize knowledge rather than develop new knowledge.[citation needed]
Logical positivism is commonly portrayed as taking the extreme position that scientific language should never refer to anything unobservable—even the seemingly core notions of causality, mechanism, and principles—but that is an exaggeration. Talk of such unobservables could be allowed as metaphorical—direct observations viewed in the abstract—or at worst metaphysical or emotional.Theoretical laws would be reduced toempirical laws, whiletheoretical terms would garner meaning fromobservational terms viacorrespondence rules. Mathematics in physics would reduce tosymbolic logic via logicism, whilerational reconstruction would convertordinary language into standardized equivalents, all networked and united by alogical syntax. A scientific theory would be stated with its method of verification, whereby alogical calculus orempirical operation could verify its falsity or truth.[citation needed]
In the late 1930s, logical positivists fled Germany and Austria for Britain and America. By then, many had replaced Mach's phenomenalism withOtto Neurath'sphysicalism, andRudolf Carnap had sought to replaceverification with simplyconfirmation. WithWorld War II's close in 1945, logical positivism became milder,logical empiricism, led largely byCarl Hempel, in America, who expounded thecovering law model of scientific explanation as a way of identifying the logical form of explanations without any reference to the suspect notion of "causation". The logical positivist movement became a major underpinning ofanalytic philosophy,[46] and dominatedAnglosphere philosophy, including philosophy of science, while influencing sciences, into the 1960s. Yet the movement failed to resolve its central problems,[47][48][49] and its doctrines were increasingly assaulted. Nevertheless, it brought about the establishment of philosophy of science as a distinct subdiscipline of philosophy, with Carl Hempel playing a key role.[50]
Thomas Kuhn
editIn the 1962 bookThe Structure of Scientific Revolutions,Thomas Kuhn argued that the process of observation and evaluation takes place within a "paradigm", which he describes as "universally recognized achievements that for a time provide model problems and solutions to community of practitioners."[51] A paradigm implicitly identifies the objects and relations under study and suggests what experiments, observations or theoretical improvements need to be carried out to produce a useful result.[52] He characterizednormal science as the process of observation and "puzzle solving" which takes place within a paradigm, whereasrevolutionary science occurs when one paradigm overtakes another in aparadigm shift.[53]
Kurn was a historian of science, and his ideas were inspired by the study of older paradigms that have been discarded, such asAristotelian mechanics oraether theory. These had often been portrayed by historians as using "unscientific" methods or beliefs. But careful examination showed that they were no less "scientific" than modern paradigms. Both were based on valid evidence, both failed to answer every possible question.[54]
A paradigm shift occurred when a significant number of observational anomalies arose in the old paradigm and efforts to resolve them within the paradigm were unsuccessful. A new paradigm was available that handled the anomalies with less difficulty and yet still covered (most of) the previous results. Over a period of time, often as long as a generation, more practitioners began working within the new paradigm and eventually the old paradigm was abandoned.[55] For Kuhn, acceptance or rejection of a paradigm is a social process as much as a logical process.
Kuhn's position, however, is not one ofrelativism; he wrote "terms like 'subjective' and 'intuitive' cannot be applied to [paradigms]."[56] Paradigms are grounded in objective, observable evidence, but our use of them is psychological and our acceptance of them is social.
Current approaches
editNaturalism's axiomatic assumptions
editAccording to Robert Priddy, all scientific study inescapably builds on at least some essential assumptions that cannot be tested by scientific processes;[57] that is, that scientists must start with some assumptions as to the ultimate analysis of the facts with which it deals. These assumptions would then be justified partly by their adherence to the types of occurrence of which we are directly conscious, and partly by their success in representing the observed facts with a certain generality, devoid ofad hoc suppositions."[58]Kuhn also claims that all science is based on assumptions about the character of the universe, rather than merely on empirical facts. These assumptions – a paradigm – comprise a collection of beliefs, values and techniques that are held by a given scientific community, which legitimize their systems and set the limitations to their investigation.[59] For naturalists, nature is the only reality, the "correct" paradigm, and there is no such thing assupernatural, i.e. anything above, beyond, or outside of nature. The scientific method is to be used to investigate all reality, including the human spirit.[60]
Some claim that naturalism is the implicit philosophy of working scientists, and that the following basic assumptions are needed to justify the scientific method:[61]
- That there is an objective reality shared by all rational observers.[61][62]
"The basis for rationality is acceptance of an external objective reality."[63] "Objective reality is clearly an essential thing if we are to develop a meaningful perspective of the world. Nevertheless its very existence is assumed."[64] "Our belief that objective reality exist is an assumption that it arises from a real world outside of ourselves. As infants we made this assumption unconsciously. People are happy to make this assumption that adds meaning to our sensations and feelings, than live withsolipsism."[65] "Without this assumption, there would be only the thoughts and images in our own mind (which would be the only existing mind) and there would be no need of science, or anything else."[66][self-published source?] - That this objective reality is governed by natural laws;[61][62]
"Science, at least today, assumes that the universe obeys knowable principles that don't depend on time or place, nor on subjective parameters such as what we think, know or how we behave."[63] Hugh Gauch argues that science presupposes that "the physical world is orderly and comprehensible."[67] - That reality can be discovered by means of systematic observation and experimentation.[61][62]
Stanley Sobottka said: "The assumption of external reality is necessary for science to function and to flourish. For the most part, science is the discovering and explaining of the external world."[66][self-published source?] "Science attempts to produce knowledge that is as universal and objective as possible within the realm of human understanding."[63] - That Nature has uniformity of laws and most if not all things in nature must have at least a natural cause.[62]
BiologistStephen Jay Gould referred to these two closely related propositions as the constancy of nature's laws and the operation of known processes.[68] Simpson agrees that the axiom of uniformity of law, an unprovable postulate, is necessary in order for scientists to extrapolate inductive inference into the unobservable past in order to meaningfully study it.[69] "The assumption of spatial and temporal invariance of natural laws is by no means unique to geology since it amounts to a warrant for inductive inference which, as Bacon showed nearly four hundred years ago, is the basic mode of reasoning in empirical science. Without assuming this spatial and temporal invariance, we have no basis for extrapolating from the known to the unknown and, therefore, no way of reaching general conclusions from a finite number of observations. (Since the assumption is itself vindicated by induction, it can in no way "prove" the validity of induction — an endeavor virtually abandoned after Hume demonstrated its futility two centuries ago)."[70] Gould also notes that natural processes such as Lyell's "uniformity of process" are an assumption: "As such, it is anothera priori assumption shared by all scientists and not a statement about the empirical world."[71] According to R. Hooykaas: "The principle of uniformity is not a law, not a rule established after comparison of facts, but a principle, preceding the observation of facts ... It is the logical principle of parsimony of causes and of economy of scientific notions. By explaining past changes by analogy with present phenomena, a limit is set to conjecture, for there is only one way in which two things are equal, but there are an infinity of ways in which they could be supposed different."[72] - That experimental procedures will be done satisfactorily without any deliberate or unintentional mistakes that will influence the results.[62]
- That experimenters won't be significantly biased by their presumptions.[62]
- That random sampling is representative of the entire population.[62]
A simple random sample (SRS) is the most basic probabilistic option used for creating a sample from a population. The benefit of SRS is that the investigator is guaranteed to choose a sample that represents the population that ensures statistically valid conclusions.[73]
Coherentism
editIn contrast to the view that science rests on foundational assumptions, coherentism asserts that statements are justified by being a part of a coherent system. Or, rather, individual statements cannot be validated on their own: only coherent systems can be justified.[74] A prediction of atransit of Venus is justified by its being coherent with broader beliefs about celestial mechanics and earlier observations. As explained above, observation is a cognitive act. That is, it relies on a pre-existing understanding, a systematic set of beliefs. An observation of a transit of Venus requires a huge range of auxiliary beliefs, such as those that describe theoptics of telescopes, themechanics of the telescope mount, and an understanding ofcelestial mechanics. If the prediction fails and a transit is not observed, that is likely to occasion an adjustment in the system, a change in some auxiliary assumption, rather than a rejection of the theoretical system.[citation needed]
According to theDuhem–Quine thesis, afterPierre Duhem andW.V. Quine, it is impossible to test a theory in isolation.[75] One must always add auxiliary hypotheses in order to make testable predictions. For example, to testNewton's Law of Gravitation in the solar system, one needs information about the masses and positions of the Sun and all the planets. Famously, the failure to predict the orbit ofUranus in the 19th century led not to the rejection of Newton's Law but rather to the rejection of the hypothesis that theSolar System comprises only seven planets. The investigations that followed led to the discovery of an eighth planet,Neptune. If a test fails, something is wrong. But there is a problem in figuring out what that something is: a missing planet, badly calibrated test equipment, an unsuspected curvature of space, or something else.[citation needed]
One consequence of the Duhem–Quine thesis is that one can make any theory compatible with any empirical observation by the addition of a sufficient number of suitablead hoc hypotheses.Karl Popper accepted this thesis, leading him to rejectnaïve falsification. Instead, he favored a "survival of the fittest" view in which the most falsifiable scientific theories are to be preferred.[76]
Anything goes methodology
editPaul Feyerabend (1924–1994) argued that no description of scientific method could possibly be broad enough to include all the approaches and methods used by scientists, and that there are no useful and exception-freemethodological rules governing the progress of science. He argued that "the only principle that does not inhibit progress is:anything goes".[77]
Feyerabend said that science started as a liberating movement, but that over time it had become increasingly dogmatic and rigid and had some oppressive features, and thus had become increasingly anideology. Because of this, he said it was impossible to come up with an unambiguous way to distinguish science fromreligion,magic, ormythology. He saw the exclusive dominance of science as a means of directing society asauthoritarian and ungrounded.[77] Promulgation of this epistemological anarchism earned Feyerabend the title of "the worst enemy of science" from his detractors.[78]
Sociology of scientific knowledge methodology
editAccording to Kuhn, science is an inherently communal activity which can only be done as part of a community.[79] For him, the fundamental difference between science and other disciplines is the way in which the communities function. Others, especially Feyerabend and some post-modernist thinkers, have argued that there is insufficient difference between social practices in science and other disciplines to maintain this distinction. For them, social factors play an important and direct role in scientific method, but they do not serve to differentiate science from other disciplines. On this account, science is socially constructed, though this does not necessarily imply the more radical notion that reality itself is asocial construct.
Michel Foucault sought to analyze and uncover how disciplines within the social sciences developed and adopted the methodologies used by their practitioners. In works likeThe Archaeology of Knowledge, he used the termhuman sciences. The human sciences do not comprise mainstream academic disciplines; they are rather an interdisciplinary space for the reflection onman who is the subject of more mainstream scientific knowledge, taken now as an object, sitting between these more conventional areas, and of course associating with disciplines such asanthropology,psychology,sociology, and evenhistory.[80] Rejecting therealist view of scientific inquiry, Foucault argued throughout his work that scientific discourse is not simply an objective study of phenomena, as bothnatural andsocial scientists like to believe, but is rather the product of systems of power relations struggling to construct scientific disciplines and knowledge within given societies.[81] With the advances of scientific disciplines, such as psychology and anthropology, the need to separate, categorize, normalize and institutionalize populations into constructed social identities became a staple of the sciences. Constructions of what were considered "normal" and "abnormal" stigmatized and ostracized groups of people, like the mentally ill and sexual and gender minorities.[82]
However, some (such as Quine) do maintain that scientific reality is a social construct:
Physical objects are conceptually imported into the situation as convenient intermediaries not by definition in terms of experience, but simply as irreducible posits comparable, epistemologically, to the gods of Homer ... For my part I do, qua lay physicist, believe in physical objects and not in Homer's gods; and I consider it a scientific error to believe otherwise. But in point of epistemological footing, the physical objects and the gods differ only in degree and not in kind. Both sorts of entities enter our conceptions only ascultural posits.[83]
The public backlash of scientists against such views, particularly in the 1990s, became known as thescience wars.[84]
A major development in recent decades has been the study of the formation, structure, and evolution of scientific communities by sociologists and anthropologists – includingDavid Bloor,Harry Collins,Bruno Latour,Ian Hacking andAnselm Strauss. Concepts and methods (such as rational choice, social choice or game theory) fromeconomics have also been applied[by whom?] for understanding the efficiency of scientific communities in the production of knowledge. This interdisciplinary field has come to be known asscience and technology studies.[85]Here the approach to the philosophy of science is to study how scientific communities actually operate.
Continental philosophy
editPhilosophers in thecontinental philosophical tradition are not traditionally categorized[by whom?] as philosophers of science. However, they have much to say about science, some of which has anticipated themes in the analytical tradition. For example, inThe Genealogy of Morals (1887)Friedrich Nietzsche advanced the thesis that the motive for the search for truth in sciences is a kind of ascetic ideal.[86]
In general, continental philosophy views science from aworld-historical perspective. Philosophers such asPierre Duhem (1861–1916) andGaston Bachelard (1884–1962) wrote their works with this world-historical approach to science, predating Kuhn's 1962 work by a generation or more. All of these approaches involve a historical and sociological turn to science, with a priority on lived experience (a kind of Husserlian"life-world"), rather than a progress-based or anti-historical approach as emphasised in the analytic tradition. One can trace this continental strand of thought through thephenomenology ofEdmund Husserl (1859–1938), the late works ofMerleau-Ponty (Nature: Course Notes from the Collège de France, 1956–1960), and thehermeneutics ofMartin Heidegger (1889–1976).[87]
The largest effect on the continental tradition with respect to science came from Martin Heidegger's critique of thetheoretical attitude in general, which of course includes the scientific attitude.[88] For this reason, the continental tradition has remained much more skeptical of the importance of science inhuman life and in philosophical inquiry. Nonetheless, there have been a number of important works: especially those of a Kuhnian precursor,Alexandre Koyré (1892–1964). Another important development was that ofMichel Foucault's analysis of historical and scientific thought inThe Order of Things (1966) and his study of power and corruption within the "science" ofmadness.[89] Post-Heideggerian authors contributing to continental philosophy of science in the second half of the 20th century includeJürgen Habermas (e.g.,Truth and Justification, 1998),Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker (The Unity of Nature, 1980;German:Die Einheit der Natur (1971)), andWolfgang Stegmüller (Probleme und Resultate der Wissenschaftstheorie und Analytischen Philosophie, 1973–1986).
Other topics
editReductionism
editAnalysis involves breaking an observation or theory down into simpler concepts in order to understand it.Reductionism can refer to one of several philosophical positions related to this approach. One type of reductionism suggests that phenomena are amenable to scientific explanation at lower levels of analysis and inquiry. Perhaps a historical event might be explained in sociological and psychological terms, which in turn might be described in terms of human physiology, which in turn might be described in terms of chemistry and physics.[90]Daniel Dennett distinguishes legitimate reductionism from what he callsgreedy reductionism, which denies real complexities and leaps too quickly to sweeping generalizations.[91]
Social accountability
editA broad issue affecting the neutrality of science concerns the areas which science chooses to explore—that is, what part of the world and of humankind are studied by science.Philip Kitcher in hisScience, Truth, and Democracy[92]argues that scientific studies that attempt to show one segment of the population as being less intelligent, less successful, or emotionally backward compared to others have a political feedback effect which further excludes such groups from access to science. Thus such studies undermine the broad consensus required for good science by excluding certain people, and so proving themselves in the end to be unscientific.
Philosophy of particular sciences
editThere is no such thing as philosophy-free science; there is only science whose philosophical baggage is taken on board without examination.[93]
— Daniel Dennett,Darwin's Dangerous Idea, 1995
In addition to addressing the general questions regarding science and induction, many philosophers of science are occupied by investigating foundational problems in particular sciences. They also examine the implications of particular sciences for broader philosophical questions. The late 20th and early 21st century has seen a rise in the number of practitioners of philosophy of a particular science.[94]
Philosophy of statistics
editThe problem of induction discussed above is seen in another form in debates over thefoundations of statistics.[95] The standard approach tostatistical hypothesis testing avoids claims about whether evidence supports a hypothesis or makes it more probable. Instead, the typical test yields ap-value, which is the probability of theevidence being such as it is, under the assumption that thenull hypothesis is true. If thep-value is too high, the hypothesis is rejected, in a way analogous to falsification. In contrast,Bayesian inference seeks to assign probabilities to hypotheses. Related topics in philosophy of statistics includeprobability interpretations,overfitting, and the difference betweencorrelation and causation.
Philosophy of mathematics
editPhilosophy of mathematics is concerned with the philosophical foundations and implications ofmathematics.[96] The central questions are whethernumbers,triangles, and other mathematical entities exist independently of the humanmind and what is the nature of mathematicalpropositions. Is asking whether "1 + 1 = 2" is true fundamentally different from asking whether a ball is red? Wascalculus invented or discovered? A related question is whether learning mathematics requiresexperience or reason alone. What does it mean to prove a mathematicaltheorem and how does one know whether amathematical proof is correct? Philosophers of mathematics also aim to clarify the relationships between mathematics andlogic, human capabilities such asintuition, and thematerial universe.
Philosophy of physics
editPhilosophy of physics is the study of the fundamental,philosophical questions underlying modernphysics, the study ofmatter andenergy and how they interact. The main questions concern the nature ofspace and time,atoms andatomism. Also included are the predictions ofcosmology, theinterpretation of quantum mechanics, the foundations ofstatistical mechanics,causality,determinism, and the nature ofphysical laws.[97] Classically, several of these questions were studied as part ofmetaphysics (for example, those about causality, determinism, and space and time).
Philosophy of chemistry
editPhilosophy of chemistry is the philosophical study of themethodology and content of the science ofchemistry. It is explored by philosophers, chemists, and philosopher-chemist teams. It includes research on general philosophy of science issues as applied to chemistry. For example, can all chemical phenomena be explained byquantum mechanics or is it not possible to reduce chemistry to physics? For another example, chemists have discussed the philosophy ofhow theories are confirmed in the context of confirmingreaction mechanisms. Determining reaction mechanisms is difficult because they cannot be observed directly. Chemists can use a number of indirect measures as evidence to rule out certain mechanisms, but they are often unsure if the remaining mechanism is correct because there are many other possible mechanisms that they have not tested or even thought of.[98] Philosophers have also sought to clarify the meaning of chemical concepts which do not refer to specific physical entities, such aschemical bonds.
Philosophy of astronomy
editThe philosophy of astronomy seeks to understand and analyze the methodologies and technologies used by experts in the discipline, focusing on how observations made aboutspace andastrophysical phenomena can be studied. Given that astronomers rely and use theories and formulas from other scientific disciplines, such as chemistry and physics, the pursuit of understanding how knowledge can be obtained about the cosmos, as well as the relation in which Earth and theSolar System have within personal views of humanity's place in the universe, philosophical insights into how facts about space can be scientifically analyzed and configure with other established knowledge is a main point of inquiry.
Philosophy of Earth sciences
editThe philosophy of Earth science is concerned with how humans obtain and verify knowledge of the workings of the Earth system, including theatmosphere,hydrosphere, andgeosphere (solid earth). Earth scientists' ways of knowing and habits of mind share important commonalities with other sciences, but also have distinctive attributes that emerge from the complex, heterogeneous, unique, long-lived, and non-manipulatable nature of the Earth system.
Philosophy of biology
editPhilosophy of biology deals withepistemological,metaphysical, andethical issues in thebiological andbiomedical sciences. Although philosophers of science and philosophers generally have long been interested in biology (e.g.,Aristotle,Descartes,Leibniz and evenKant), philosophy of biology only emerged as an independent field of philosophy in the 1960s and 1970s.[102] Philosophers of science began to pay increasing attention to developments in biology, from the rise of themodern synthesis in the 1930s and 1940s to the discovery of the structure ofdeoxyribonucleic acid (DNA) in 1953 to more recent advances ingenetic engineering. Other key ideas such as thereduction of all life processes tobiochemical reactions as well as the incorporation ofpsychology into a broaderneuroscience are also addressed. Research in current philosophy of biology includes investigation of the foundations of evolutionary theory (such asPeter Godfrey-Smith's work),[103] and the role of viruses as persistent symbionts in host genomes. As a consequence, the evolution of genetic content order is seen as the result of competent genome editors[further explanation needed] in contrast to former narratives in which error replication events (mutations) dominated.
Philosophy of medicine
editBeyondmedical ethics andbioethics, the philosophy of medicine is a branch of philosophy that includes theepistemology andontology/metaphysics of medicine. Within the epistemology of medicine,evidence-based medicine (EBM) (or evidence-based practice (EBP)) has attracted attention, most notably the roles of randomisation,[104][105][106]blinding andplacebo controls. Related to these areas of investigation, ontologies of specific interest to the philosophy of medicine includeCartesian dualism, the monogenetic conception of disease[107] and the conceptualization of 'placebos' and 'placebo effects'.[108][109][110][111] There is also a growing interest in the metaphysics of medicine,[112] particularly the idea of causation. Philosophers of medicine might not only be interested in how medical knowledge is generated, but also in the nature of such phenomena. Causation is of interest because the purpose of much medical research is to establish causal relationships, e.g. what causes disease, or what causes people to get better.[113]
Philosophy of psychiatry
editPhilosophy of psychiatry explores philosophical questions relating topsychiatry andmental illness. The philosopher of science and medicine Dominic Murphy identifies three areas of exploration in the philosophy of psychiatry. The first concerns the examination of psychiatry as a science, using the tools of the philosophy of science more broadly. The second entails the examination of the concepts employed in discussion of mental illness, including the experience of mental illness, and the normative questions it raises. The third area concerns the links and discontinuities between thephilosophy of mind andpsychopathology.[114]
Philosophy of psychology
editPhilosophy of psychology refers to issues at the theoretical foundations of modernpsychology. Some of these issues are epistemological concerns about the methodology of psychological investigation. For example, is the best method for studying psychology to focus only on the response ofbehavior to external stimuli or should psychologists focus onmental perception and thought processes?[115] If the latter, an important question is how the internal experiences of others can be measured. Self-reports of feelings and beliefs may not be reliable because, even in cases in which there is no apparent incentive for subjects to intentionally deceive in their answers, self-deception or selective memory may affect their responses. Then even in the case of accurate self-reports, how can responses be compared across individuals? Even if two individuals respond with the same answer on aLikert scale, they may be experiencing very different things.
Other issues in philosophy of psychology are philosophical questions about the nature of mind, brain, and cognition, and are perhaps more commonly thought of as part ofcognitive science, orphilosophy of mind. For example, are humansrational creatures?[115] Is there any sense in which they havefree will, and how does that relate to the experience of making choices? Philosophy of psychology also closely monitors contemporary work conducted incognitive neuroscience,psycholinguistics, andartificial intelligence, questioning what they can and cannot explain in psychology.
Philosophy of psychology is a relatively young field, because psychology only became a discipline of its own in the late 1800s. In particular,neurophilosophy has just recently become its own field with the works ofPaul Churchland andPatricia Churchland.[94] Philosophy of mind, by contrast, has been a well-established discipline since before psychology was a field of study at all. It is concerned with questions about the very nature of mind, the qualities of experience, and particular issues like the debate betweendualism andmonism.
Philosophy of social science
editThe philosophy of social science is the study of the logic and method of thesocial sciences, such associology andcultural anthropology.[116] Philosophers of social science are concerned with the differences and similarities between the social and thenatural sciences, causal relationships between social phenomena, the possible existence of social laws, and theontological significance ofstructure and agency.
The French philosopher,Auguste Comte (1798–1857), established the epistemological perspective ofpositivism inThe Course in Positivist Philosophy, a series of texts published between 1830 and 1842. The first three volumes of theCourse dealt chiefly with thenatural sciences already in existence (geoscience,astronomy,physics,chemistry,biology), whereas the latter two emphasised the inevitable coming ofsocial science: "sociologie".[117] For Comte, the natural sciences had to necessarily arrive first, before humanity could adequately channel its efforts into the most challenging and complex "Queen science" of human society itself. Comte offers an evolutionary system proposing that society undergoes three phases in its quest for the truth according to a general 'law of three stages'. These are (1) thetheological, (2) themetaphysical, and (3) thepositive.[118]
Comte's positivism established the initial philosophical foundations for formal sociology andsocial research.Durkheim,Marx, andWeber are more typically cited as the fathers of contemporary social science. Inpsychology, a positivistic approach has historically been favoured inbehaviourism. Positivism has also been espoused by 'technocrats' who believe in the inevitability ofsocial progress through science and technology.[119]
The positivist perspective has been associated with 'scientism'; the view that the methods of the natural sciences may be applied to all areas of investigation, be it philosophical, social scientific, or otherwise. Among most social scientists and historians, orthodox positivism has long since lost popular support. Today, practitioners of both social and physical sciences instead take into account the distorting effect of observerbias and structural limitations. This scepticism has been facilitated by a general weakening of deductivist accounts of science by philosophers such asThomas Kuhn, and new philosophical movements such ascritical realism andneopragmatism. The philosopher-sociologistJürgen Habermas has critiqued pureinstrumental rationality as meaning that scientific-thinking becomes something akin toideology itself.[120]
Philosophy of technology
editThe philosophy of technology is a sub-field ofphilosophy that studies the nature oftechnology. Specific research topics include study of the role of tacit and explicit knowledge in creating and using technology, the nature of functions in technological artifacts, the role of values in design, and ethics related to technology. Technology and engineering can both involve the application of scientific knowledge. Thephilosophy of engineering is an emerging sub-field of the broader philosophy of technology.
See also
editReferences
edit- ^Thornton, Stephen (2006)."Karl Popper".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2007-06-27. Retrieved2007-12-01.
- ^"Science and Pseudo-science".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008. Archived fromthe original on 2015-09-05.
- ^Laudan, Larry (1983). "The Demise of the Demarcation Problem". In Grünbaum, Adolf; Cohen, Robert Sonné; Laudan, Larry (eds.).Physics, Philosophy, and Psychoanalysis: Essays in Honor of Adolf Grünbaum. Springer.ISBN 978-90-277-1533-3.
- ^Gordin, Michael D. (2012).The Pseudoscience Wars: Immanuel Velikovsky and the Birth of the Modern Fringe. University of Chicago Press. pp. 12–13.ISBN 978-0-226-30442-7.
- ^Uebel, Thomas (2006)."Vienna Circle".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2007-06-26. Retrieved2007-12-01.
- ^Popper, Karl (2004).The logic of scientific discovery (reprint ed.). London & New York: Routledge Classics.ISBN 978-0-415-27844-7First published 1959 by Hutchinson & Co.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: postscript (link) - ^"Pseudoscientific – pretending to be scientific, falsely represented as being scientific".Oxford American Dictionary.Oxford English Dictionary.
- ^Hansson, Sven Ove (1996). "Defining Pseudoscience".Philosophia Naturalis.33:169–176., as cited in"Science and Pseudo-science".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008. Archived fromthe original on 2015-09-05.. The Stanford article states: "Many writers on pseudoscience have emphasized that pseudoscience is non-science posing as science. The foremost modern classic on the subject (Gardner 1957) bears the titleFads and Fallacies in the Name of Science. According to Brian Baigrie (1988, 438), "[w]hat is objectionable about these beliefs is that they masquerade as genuinely scientific ones." These and many other authors assume that to be pseudoscientific, an activity or a teaching has to satisfy the following two criteria (Hansson 1996): (1) it is not scientific, and (2) its major proponents try to create the impression that it is scientific".
- ^Hewitt, Paul G.; Suchocki, John; Hewitt, Leslie A. (2003).Conceptual Physical Science (3rd ed.). Addison Wesley.ISBN 0-321-05173-4.
- ^Bennett, Jeffrey O. (2003).The Cosmic Perspective (3rd ed.). Addison Wesley.ISBN 0-8053-8738-2.
- ^Gauch HG Jr.Scientific Method in Practice (2003).
- ^A 2006National Science Foundation report on Science and engineering indicators quotedMichael Shermer's (1997) definition of pseudoscience: '"claims presented so that they appear [to be] scientific even though they lack supporting evidence and plausibility"(p. 33). In contrast, science is "a set of methods designed to describe and interpret observed and inferred phenomena, past or present, and aimed at building a testable body of knowledge open to rejection or confirmation" (p. 17)'.Shermer, Michael (1997).Why People Believe Weird Things: Pseudoscience, Superstition, and Other Confusions of Our Time. New York: W.H. Freeman and Company.ISBN 978-0-7167-3090-3. as cited byNational Science Foundation; Division of Science Resources Statistics (2006)."Science and Technology: Public Attitudes and Understanding".Science and engineering indicators 2006.
- ^"A pretended or spurious science; a collection of related beliefs about the world mistakenly regarded as being based on scientific method or as having the status that scientific truths now have," from theOxford English Dictionary, second edition 1989.
- ^Feynman, Richard."Cargo Cult Science"(PDF). Archived fromthe original(PDF) on 2013-12-01. Retrieved2015-10-25.
- ^Hempel, Carl G.; Oppenheim, Paul (1948). "Studies in the Logic of Explanation".Philosophy of Science.15 (2):135–175.CiteSeerX 10.1.1.294.3693.doi:10.1086/286983.S2CID 16924146.
- ^Salmon, Merrilee; Earman, John; Glymour, Clark; Lenno, James G.; Machamer, Peter; McGuire, J.E.; Norton, John D.; Salmon, Wesley C.; Schaffner, Kenneth F. (1992).Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Prentice-Hall.ISBN 978-0-13-663345-7.
- ^Salmon, Wesley (1971).Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.ISBN 9780822974116.
- ^abWoodward, James (2003)."Scientific Explanation".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2007-07-06. Retrieved2007-12-07.
- ^abVickers, John (2013)."The Problem of Induction".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2014-04-07. Retrieved2014-02-25.
- ^Baker, Alan (2013)."Simplicity".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2014-03-26. Retrieved2014-02-25.
- ^Nicholas Maxwell (1998)The Comprehensibility of the UniverseArchived 2018-02-27 at theWayback Machine Clarendon Press; (2017)Understanding Scientific Progress: Aim-Oriented EmpiricismArchived 2018-02-20 at theWayback Machine, Paragon House, St. Paul
- ^abBogen, Jim (2013)."Theory and Observation in Science".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2014-02-27. Retrieved2014-02-25.
- ^Levin, Michael (1984)."What Kind of Explanation is Truth?". In Jarrett Leplin (ed.).Scientific Realism. Berkeley: University of California Press. pp. 124–1139.ISBN 978-0-520-05155-3.
- ^abBoyd, Richard (2002)."Scientific Realism".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2007-07-06. Retrieved2007-12-01.
- ^Specific examples include:
- Popper, Karl (2002).Conjectures and Refutations. London & New York: Routledge Classics.ISBN 978-0-415-28594-0First published 1963 by Routledge and Kegan Paul
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: postscript (link) - Smart, J.J.C. (1968).Between Science and Philosophy. New York: Random House.
- Putnam, Hilary (1975).Mathematics, Matter and Method (Philosophical Papers, Vol. I). London: Cambridge University Press.
- Putnam, Hilary (1978).Meaning and the Moral Sciences. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- Boyd, Richard (1984)."The Current Status of Scientific Realism". In Jarrett Leplin (ed.).Scientific Realism. Berkeley: University of California Press. pp. 41–82.ISBN 978-0-520-05155-3.
- Popper, Karl (2002).Conjectures and Refutations. London & New York: Routledge Classics.ISBN 978-0-415-28594-0First published 1963 by Routledge and Kegan Paul
- ^Stanford, P. Kyle (2006).Exceeding Our Grasp: Science, History, and the Problem of Unconceived Alternatives. Oxford University Press.ISBN 978-0-19-517408-3.
- ^Laudan, Larry (1981). "A Confutation of Convergent Realism".Philosophy of Science.48:218–249.CiteSeerX 10.1.1.594.2523.doi:10.1086/288975.S2CID 108290084.
- ^abvan Fraassen, Bas (1980).The Scientific Image. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.ISBN 978-0-19-824424-0.
- ^Winsberg, Eric (September 2006). "Models of Success Versus the Success of Models: Reliability without Truth".Synthese.152:1–19.doi:10.1007/s11229-004-5404-6.S2CID 18275928.
- ^Stanford, P. Kyle (June 2000). "An Antirealist Explanation of the Success of Science".Philosophy of Science.67 (2):266–284.doi:10.1086/392775.S2CID 35878807.
- ^Dennett, D. (1991). Real Patterns. The Journal of Philosophy.
- ^Burnston, D. C. (2017). Real Patterns in Biological Explanation. Philosophy of Science.
- ^Seifert, V. A. (2022). The Chemical Bond is a Real Pattern. Philosophy of Science.
- ^Millhouse, T. (2020). Really real patterns. Australasian Journal of Philosophy.
- ^Santa Fe Institute. (2022). Real patterns in science & cognition.https://www.santafe.edu/news-center/news/real-patterns-science-cognition
- ^Rosenstock, Linda; Lee, Lore Jackson (January 2002)."Attacks on Science: The Risks to Evidence-Based Policy".American Journal of Public Health.92 (1):14–18.doi:10.2105/ajph.92.1.14.ISSN 0090-0036.PMC 1447376.PMID 11772749.
- ^Longino, Helen (2013)."The Social Dimensions of Scientific Knowledge".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2014-03-26. Retrieved2014-03-06.
- ^Douglas Allchin, "Values in Science and in Science Education," in International Handbook of Science Education, B.J. Fraser and K.G. Tobin (eds.), 2:1083–1092, Kluwer Academic Publishers (1988).
- ^Aristotle, "Prior Analytics", Hugh Tredennick (trans.), pp. 181–531 inAristotle, Volume 1,Loeb Classical Library, William Heinemann, London, 1938.
- ^Lindberg, David C. (1980).Science in the Middle Ages. University of Chicago Press. pp. 350–351.ISBN 978-0-226-48233-0.
- ^Clegg, Brian (2004).The First Scientist: A Life of Roger Bacon. Da Capo Press. p. 2.ISBN 978-0786713585.
- ^Bacon, FrancisNovum Organum (The New Organon), 1620. Bacon's work described many of the accepted principles, underscoring the importance of empirical results, data gathering and experiment.Encyclopædia Britannica (1911), "Bacon, Francis" states: [In Novum Organum, we ] "proceed to apply what is perhaps the most valuable part of the Baconian method, the process of exclusion or rejection. This elimination of the non-essential, ..., is the most important of Bacon's contributions to the logic of induction, and that in which, as he repeatedly says, his method differs from all previous philosophies."
- ^abMcMullin, Ernan."The Impact of Newton's Principia on the Philosophy of Science".paricenter.com. Pari Center for New Learning. Archived fromthe original on 24 October 2015. Retrieved29 October 2015.
- ^"John Stuart Mill (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". plato.stanford.edu.Archived from the original on 2010-01-06. Retrieved2009-07-31.
- ^Michael Friedman,Reconsidering Logical Positivism (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999),p. xivArchived 2016-06-28 at theWayback Machine.
- ^See"Vienna Circle"Archived 2015-08-10 at theWayback Machine inStanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ^Smith, L.D. (1986).Behaviorism and Logical Positivism: A Reassessment of the Alliance. Stanford University Press. p. 314.ISBN 978-0-8047-1301-6.LCCN 85030366. Retrieved2016-01-27.
The secondary and historical literature on logical positivism affords substantial grounds for concluding that logical positivism failed to solve many of the central problems it generated for itself. Prominent among the unsolved problems was the failure to find an acceptable statement of the verifiability (later confirmability) criterion of meaningfulness. Until a competing tradition emerged (about the late 1950s), the problems of logical positivism continued to be attacked from within that tradition. But as the new tradition in the philosophy of science began to demonstrate its effectiveness—by dissolving and rephrasing old problems as well as by generating new ones—philosophers began to shift allegiances to the new tradition, even though that tradition has yet to receive a canonical formulation.
- ^Bunge, M.A. (1996).Finding Philosophy in Social Science. Yale University Press. p. 317.ISBN 978-0-300-06606-7.LCCN lc96004399. Retrieved2016-01-27.
To conclude, logical positivism was progressive compared with the classical positivism ofPtolemy,Hume,d'Alembert,Comte,John Stuart Mill, andErnst Mach. It was even more so by comparison with its contemporary rivals—neo-Thomism,neo-Kantianism,intuitionism, dialectical materialism, phenomenology, andexistentialism. However, neo-positivism failed dismally to give a faithful account of science, whether natural or social. It failed because it remained anchored to sense-data and to a phenomenalist metaphysics, overrated the power of induction and underrated that of hypothesis, and denounced realism and materialism as metaphysical nonsense. Although it has never been practiced consistently in the advanced natural sciences and has been criticized by many philosophers, notably Popper (1959 [1935], 1963), logical positivism remains the tacit philosophy of many scientists. Regrettably, the anti-positivism fashionable in the metatheory of social science is often nothing but an excuse for sloppiness and wild speculation.
- ^"Popper, Falsifiability, and the Failure of Positivism". 7 August 2000. Archived fromthe original on January 7, 2014. Retrieved7 January 2014.
The upshot is that the positivists seem caught between insisting on the V.C. [Verifiability Criterion]—but for no defensible reason—or admitting that the V.C. requires a background language, etc., which opens the door to relativism, etc. In light of this dilemma, many folk—especially following Popper's "last-ditch" effort to "save" empiricism/positivism/realism with the falsifiability criterion—have agreed that positivism is a dead-end.
- ^Friedman,Reconsidering Logical Positivism (Cambridge U P, 1999),p. xiiArchived 2016-06-28 at theWayback Machine.
- ^Kuhn, Thomas (1972).The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (2nd ed.). The University of Chicago.ISBN 0-226-45803-2., p. viii
- ^Kuhn clarified that these are two related senses of "paradigm": (1) "the entire constellation of beliefs, values, techniques" and (2) "the set of puzzle-examples which, employed as models or examples, can replace explicit rules as a basis" and are used to illustrate the field for beginners.Kuhn 1972, p. 175
- ^Bird, Alexander (2013). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.)."Thomas Kuhn".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2017-07-13. Retrieved2015-10-26.
- ^Kuhn 1972, p. 1-7.
- ^Kuhn 1972.
- ^Kuhn 1972, p. 175.
- ^Priddy, Robert (1998)."Chapter Five, Scientific Objectivity in Question".Science Limited.
- ^Whitehead 1997, p. 135.
- ^Boldman, Lee (2007)."Chapter 6, The Privileged Status of Science"(PDF).
- ^Papineau, David"Naturalism", inThe Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, quote, "The great majority of contemporary philosophers would happily... reject 'supernatural' entities, and allow that science is a possible route (if not necessarily the only one) to important truths about the 'human spirit'."
- ^abcdHeilbron 2003, p. vii.
- ^abcdefgChen 2009, pp. 1–2.
- ^abcDurak 2008.
- ^Vaccaro, Joan."Reality". Retrieved22 December 2017.
- ^Vaccaro, Joan."Objectiveism". Retrieved22 December 2017.
Objective reality exists beyond or outside our self. Any belief that it arises from a real world outside us is actually an assumption. It seems more beneficial to assume that an objective reality exists than to live with solipsism, and so people are quite happy to make this assumption. In fact we made this assumption unconsciously when we began to learn about the world as infants. The world outside ourselves appears to respond in ways which are consistent with it being real. The assumption of objectivism is essential if we are to attach the contemporary meanings to our sensations and feelings and make more sense of them.
- ^abSobottka 2005, p. 11.
- ^Gauch 2002, p. 154, "Expressed as a single grand statement, science presupposes that the physical world is orderly and comprehensible. The most obvious components of this comprehensive presupposition are that the physical world exists and that our sense perceptions are generally reliable."
- ^Gould 1987, p. 120, "You cannot go to a rocky outcrop and observe either the constancy of nature's laws or the working of known processes. It works the other way around." You first assume these propositions and "then you go to the outcrop of rock."
- ^Simpson 1963, pp. 24–48, "Uniformity is an unprovable postulate justified, or indeed required, on two grounds. First, nothing in our incomplete but extensive knowledge of history disagrees with it. Second, only with this postulate is a rational interpretation of history possible and we are justified in seeking—as scientists we must seek—such a rational interpretation."
- ^Gould 1965, pp. 223–228.
- ^Gould 1984, p. 11.
- ^Hooykaas 1963, p. 38.
- ^"Simple Random Sampling". Archived fromthe original on 2018-01-02. Retrieved2018-01-06.
A simple random sample (SRS) is the most basic probabilistic option used for creating a sample from a population. Each SRS is made of individuals drawn from a larger population, completely at random. As a result, said individuals have an equal chance of being selected throughout the sampling process. The benefit of SRS is that as a result, the investigator is guaranteed to choose a sample which is representative of the population, which ensures statistically valid conclusions.
- ^Olsson, Erik (2014). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.)."Coherentist Theories of Epistemic Justification".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2018-09-14. Retrieved2015-10-26.
- ^Sandra Harding (1976).Can theories be refuted?: essays on the Dunhem–Quine thesis. Springer Science & Business Media. pp. 9–.ISBN 978-90-277-0630-0.Archived from the original on 2016-06-28. Retrieved2016-01-27.
- ^Popper, Karl (2005).The Logic of Scientific Discovery (Taylor & Francis e-Library ed.). London and New York: Routledge / Taylor & Francis e-Library. chapters 3–4.ISBN 978-0-203-99462-7.
- ^abFeyerabend, Paul (1993) [1974].Against Method (3rd ed.). London; New York:Verso.ISBN 086091481X.OCLC 29026104.
- ^Preston, John (2007-02-15)."Paul Feyerabend". InZalta, Edward N. (ed.).Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ^Kuhn, T.S. (1996). "[Postscript]".The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 3rd. ed. [Univ. of Chicago Pr]. p. 176.ISBN 978-0-226-45808-3.
A paradigm is what the members of a community of scientists share,and, conversely, a scientific community consists of men who share a paradigm.
- ^"Foucault, Michel".Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved29 August 2022.
- ^Morrison, Thomas (2018)."Foucault's Elephant".Philosophy Now. No. 127. Retrieved29 August 2022.
- ^Power, Jason L. (2015)."'Disciplining' Truth and Science: Michel Foucault and the Power of Social Science"(PDF).World Scientific News.7:15–29.ISSN 2392-2192.Archived(PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09.
- ^Quine, Willard Van Orman (1980)."Two Dogmas of Empiricism".From a Logical Point of View.Harvard University Press.ISBN 978-0-674-32351-3.
- ^Ashman, Keith M.; Barringer, Philip S., eds. (2001).After the Science Wars. London: Routledge.ISBN 978-0-415-21209-0. Retrieved29 October 2015.
The 'war' is between scientists who believe that science and its methods are objective, and an increasing number of social scientists, historians, philosophers, and others gathered under the umbrella of Science Studies.
- ^Woodhouse, Edward. Science Technology and Society. Spring 2015 ed. n.p.: U Readers, 2014. Print.
- ^Hatab, Lawrence J. (2008)."How Does the Ascetic Ideal Function in Nietzsche'sGenealogy?"(PDF).The Journal of Nietzsche Studies.35 (35/36):106–123.doi:10.2307/jnietstud.35.2008.0106.S2CID 170630145. Retrieved2019-10-22.
- ^Gutting, Gary (2004),Continental Philosophy of Science, Blackwell Publishers, Cambridge, MA.
- ^Wheeler, Michael (2015)."Martin Heidegger".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2015-10-16. Retrieved2015-10-29.
- ^Foucault, Michel (1961). Khalfa, Jean (ed.).History of Madness [Folie et Déraison: Histoire de la folie à l'âge classique]. Translated by Murphy, Jonathan; Khalfa, Jean. London: Routledge (published 2013).ISBN 9781134473809.Archived from the original on 15 July 2019. Retrieved3 Mar 2019.
{{cite book}}
:ISBN / Date incompatibility (help) - ^Cat, Jordi (2013)."The Unity of Science".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2014-04-07. Retrieved2014-03-01.
- ^Levine, George (2008).Darwin Loves You: Natural Selection and the Re-enchantment of the World. Princeton University Press. p. 104.ISBN 978-0-691-13639-4. Retrieved28 October 2015.
- ^Kitcher, Philip (2001).Science, Truth, and Democracy. Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Science. New York: Oxford University Press.ISBN 9780198033356. Retrieved26 September 2020.
- ^Dennett, Daniel (1995).Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life. Simon and Schuster. p. 21.ISBN 978-1-4391-2629-5.
- ^abBickle, John; Mandik, Peter; Landreth, Anthony (2010). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.)."The Philosophy of Neuroscience".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2013-12-02. Retrieved2015-12-28(Summer 2010 Edition)
{{cite web}}
: CS1 maint: postscript (link) - ^Romeijn, Jan-Willem (2014). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.)."Philosophy of Statistics".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2018-09-14. Retrieved2015-10-29.
- ^Horsten, Leon (2015). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.)."Philosophy of Mathematics".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved2015-10-29.
- ^Ismael, Jenann (2015). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.)."Quantum Mechanics".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2015-11-06. Retrieved2015-10-29.
- ^Weisberg, Michael; Needham, Paul; Hendry, Robin (2011)."Philosophy of Chemistry".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Archived from the original on 2014-04-07. Retrieved2014-02-14.
- ^"Philosophy, Logic and Scientific Method".Archived from the original on 2012-08-02. Retrieved2018-07-03.
- ^Gewertz, Ken (February 8, 2007)."The philosophy of evolution: Godfrey-Smith takes an ingenious evolutionary approach to how the mind works".Harvard University Gazette. Archived fromthe original on October 11, 2008. RetrievedJuly 3, 2018..
- ^Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection. Oxford University Press. 2010.
- ^Hull D. (1969), What philosophy of biology is not, Journal of the History of Biology, 2, pp. 241–268.
- ^Recent examples include Okasha S. (2006),Evolution and the Levels of Selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press, and Godfrey-Smith P. (2009),Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- ^Papineau, D (1994). "The Virtues of Randomization".British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.45 (2):437–450.doi:10.1093/bjps/45.2.437.S2CID 123314067.
- ^Worrall, J (2002). "What Evidence in Evidence-Based Medicine?".Philosophy of Science.69 (3): S316–330.doi:10.1086/341855.JSTOR 3081103.S2CID 55078796.
- ^Worrall, J. (2007). "Why there's no cause to randomize".British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.58 (3):451–488.CiteSeerX 10.1.1.120.7314.doi:10.1093/bjps/axm024.S2CID 16964968.
- ^Lee, K., 2012.The Philosophical Foundations of Modern Medicine, London/New York, Palgrave/Macmillan.
- ^Grünbaum, A (1981). "The Placebo Concept".Behaviour Research and Therapy.19 (2):157–167.doi:10.1016/0005-7967(81)90040-1.PMID 7271692.
- ^Gøtzsche, P.C. (1994). "Is there logic in the placebo?".Lancet.344 (8927):925–926.doi:10.1016/s0140-6736(94)92273-x.PMID 7934350.S2CID 33650340.
- ^Nunn, R., 2009. It's time to put the placebo out of our misery"British Medical Journal 338, b1568.
- ^Turner, A (2012)."Placebos" and the logic of placebo comparison".Biology & Philosophy.27 (3):419–432.doi:10.1007/s10539-011-9289-8.hdl:1983/6426ce5a-ab57-419c-bc3c-e57d20608807.S2CID 4488616.Archived from the original on 2018-12-29. Retrieved2018-12-29.
- ^Worrall, J (2011). "Causality in medicine: getting back to the Hill top".Preventive Medicine.53 (4–5):235–238.doi:10.1016/j.ypmed.2011.08.009.PMID 21888926.
- ^Cartwright, N (2009)."What are randomised controlled trials good for?"(PDF).Philosophical Studies.147 (1):59–70.doi:10.1007/s11098-009-9450-2.S2CID 56203659.Archived(PDF) from the original on 2018-07-24. Retrieved2019-09-01.
- ^Murphy, Dominic (Spring 2015). "Philosophy of PsychiatryArchived 2019-03-18 at theWayback Machine".The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta. Accessed 18 August 2016.
- ^abMason, Kelby; Sripada, Chandra Sekhar; Stich, Stephen (2010)."Philosophy of Psychology"(PDF). In Moral, Dermot (ed.).Routledge Companion to Twentieth-Century Philosophy. London: Routledge. Archived fromthe original(PDF) on 2017-05-17. Retrieved2014-02-20.
- ^Hollis, Martin (1994).The Philosophy of Social Science: An Introduction. Cambridge.ISBN 978-0-521-44780-5.
- ^"Stanford Encyclopaedia: Auguste Comte".Archived from the original on 2017-10-11. Retrieved2010-01-10.
- ^Giddens, Anthony (1974).Positivism and Sociology. Heinemann.ISBN 978-0435823405.
- ^Schunk,Learning Theories: An Educational Perspective, 5th, 315
- ^Outhwaite, William, 1988Habermas: Key Contemporary Thinkers, Polity Press (Second Edition 2009),ISBN 978-0-7456-4328-1 p. 68
Sources
edit- Chen, Christina S. (2009). Larson, Thomas (ed.)."Atheism and the Assumptions of Science and Religion".Lyceum.X (2):1–10. Archived from the original on May 25, 2013.
- Durak, Antoine Berke (6 June 2008)."The nature of reality and knowledge".
- Gauch, Hugh G. (2002).Scientific Method in Practice.Cambridge University Press.
- Gould, Stephen J (1965)."Is uniformitarianism necessary?".American Journal of Science.263 (3):223–228.Bibcode:1965AmJS..263..223G.doi:10.2475/ajs.263.3.223.
- Gould, Stephen J (1984). "Toward the vindication of punctuational change in catastrophes and earth history".Catastrophes and Earth History. Princeton University Press. p. 9–34.
- Gould, Stephen J (1987).Time's Arrow, Time's Cycle: Myth and Metaphor in the Discovery of Geological Time. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. p. 120.ISBN 978-0-674-89199-9.
You first assume.
- Heilbron, J.L., ed. (2003).The Oxford Companion to the History of Modern Science. New York: Oxford University Press.ISBN 978-0-19-511229-0.
- Hooykaas, R (1963).The principle of uniformity in geology, biology, and theology, 2nd impression. London: E.J. Brill.
- Simpson, G.G. (1963). "Historical science". In Albritton, Jr., C.C. (ed.).Fabric of geology. Stanford, California: Freeman, Cooper, and Company. pp. 24–48.
- Sobottka, Stanley (2005)."Consciousness"(PDF). p. 11.
- Whitehead, A.N. (1997) [1920].Science and the Modern World. Lowell Lectures. New York: Free Press. p. 135.ISBN 978-0-684-83639-3.LCCN 67002244.
Further reading
edit- Bovens, L. and Hartmann, S. (2003),Bayesian Epistemology, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
- Gutting, Gary (2004),Continental Philosophy of Science, Blackwell Publishers, Cambridge, MA.
- Godfrey-Smith, Peter (2003),Theory and Reality: An Introduction the Philosophy of Science, University of Chicago Press.
- Kuhn, T. S. (1970).The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd. ed. Univ. of Chicago Press.ISBN 978-0-226-45804-5.
- Losee, J. (1998),A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
- Papineau, David (2005)Problems of the Philosophy of Science. Oxford Companion to Philosophy, Oxford.
- Salmon, Merrilee H.; Science, University of Pittsburgh. Department of the History and Philosophy of (1992).Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Upper Saddle River, N.J: Prentice Hall.ISBN 978-0-13-663345-7.
- Popper, Karl, (1963)Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge,ISBN 0-415-04318-2.
- van Fraassen, Bas (1980).The Scientific Image. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.ISBN 978-0-19-824424-0.
- Ziman, John (2000).Real Science: what it is, and what it means. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.