Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Wikipedia

Equivalence class

(Redirected fromEquivalence classes)
This article is about equivalency in mathematics. For equivalency in music, seeequivalence class (music).
"Quotient map" redirects here. For Quotient map in topology, seeQuotient map (topology).

Inmathematics, when the elements of somesetS{\displaystyle S} have a notion of equivalence (formalized as anequivalence relation), then one may naturally split the setS{\displaystyle S} intoequivalence classes. These equivalence classes are constructed so that elementsa{\displaystyle a} andb{\displaystyle b} belong to the sameequivalence classif, and only if, they are equivalent.

Congruence is an example of an equivalence relation. The leftmost two triangles are congruent, while the third and fourth triangles are not congruent to any other triangle shown here. Thus, the first two triangles are in the same equivalence class, while the third and fourth triangles are each in their own equivalence class.

Formally, given a setS{\displaystyle S} and an equivalence relation{\displaystyle \sim } onS,{\displaystyle S,} theequivalence class of an elementa{\displaystyle a} inS{\displaystyle S} is denoted[a]{\displaystyle [a]} or, equivalently,[a]{\displaystyle [a]_{\sim }} to emphasize its equivalence relation{\displaystyle \sim }, and is defined as the set of all elements inS{\displaystyle S} with whicha{\displaystyle a} is{\displaystyle \sim }-related. The definition of equivalence relations implies that the equivalence classes form apartition ofS,{\displaystyle S,} meaning, that every element of the set belongs to exactly one equivalence class. The set of the equivalence classes is sometimes called thequotient set or thequotient space ofS{\displaystyle S} by,{\displaystyle \sim ,} and is denoted byS/.{\displaystyle S/{\sim }.}

When the setS{\displaystyle S} has some structure (such as agroup operation or atopology) and the equivalence relation,{\displaystyle \sim ,} is compatible with this structure, the quotient set often inherits a similar structure from its parent set. Examples includequotient spaces in linear algebra,quotient spaces in topology,quotient groups,homogeneous spaces,quotient rings,quotient monoids, andquotient categories.

Definition and notation

edit

Anequivalence relation on a setX{\displaystyle X}  is abinary relation{\displaystyle \sim }  onX{\displaystyle X}  satisfying the three properties:[1]

The equivalence class of an elementa{\displaystyle a}  is defined as[2]

[a]={xX:ax}.{\displaystyle [a]=\{x\in X:a\sim x\}.} 

The word "class" in the term "equivalence class" may generally be considered as a synonym of "set", although some equivalence classes are not sets butproper classes. For example, "beingisomorphic" is an equivalence relation ongroups, and the equivalence classes, calledisomorphism classes, are not sets.

The set of all equivalence classes inX{\displaystyle X}  with respect to an equivalence relationR{\displaystyle R}  is denoted asX/R,{\displaystyle X/R,}  and is calledX{\displaystyle X} moduloR{\displaystyle R}  (or thequotient set ofX{\displaystyle X}  byR{\displaystyle R} ).[3] Thesurjective mapx[x]{\displaystyle x\mapsto [x]}  fromX{\displaystyle X}  ontoX/R,{\displaystyle X/R,}  which maps each element to its equivalence class, is called thecanonical surjection, or thecanonical projection.

Every element of an equivalence class characterizes the class, and may be used torepresent it. When such an element is chosen, it is called arepresentative of the class. The choice of a representative in each class defines aninjection fromX/R{\displaystyle X/R}  toX. Since itscomposition with the canonical surjection is the identity ofX/R,{\displaystyle X/R,}  such an injection is called asection, when using the terminology ofcategory theory.

Sometimes, there is a section that is more "natural" than the other ones. In this case, the representatives are calledcanonical representatives. For example, inmodular arithmetic, for everyintegerm greater than1, thecongruence modulom is an equivalence relation on the integers, for which two integersa andb are equivalent—in this case, one sayscongruent—ifm dividesab;{\displaystyle a-b;}  this is denotedab(modm).{\textstyle a\equiv b{\pmod {m}}.}  Each class contains a unique non-negative integer smaller thanm,{\displaystyle m,}  and these integers are the canonical representatives.

The use of representatives for representing classes allows avoiding considering explicitly classes as sets. In this case, the canonical surjection that maps an element to its class is replaced by the function that maps an element to the representative of its class. In the preceding example, this function is denotedamodm,{\displaystyle a{\bmod {m}},}  and produces the remainder of theEuclidean division ofa bym.

Properties

edit

For a setX{\displaystyle X}  with anequivalence relation ~, every elementx{\displaystyle x}  ofX{\displaystyle X}  is a member of the equivalence class[x]{\displaystyle [x]}  byreflexivity (aa{\displaystyle a\sim a}  for allaX{\displaystyle a\in X} ). Every two equivalence classes[x]{\displaystyle [x]}  and[y]{\displaystyle [y]}  are either equal ifxy{\displaystyle x\sim y} , ordisjoint otherwise. (The proof is shown below.) Therefore, the set of all equivalence classes ofX{\displaystyle X}  forms apartition ofX{\displaystyle X} : every elementx{\displaystyle x}  ofX{\displaystyle X}  belongs to one and only one equivalence class[x]{\displaystyle [x]} , which may be the equivalence classes for other elements ofX{\displaystyle X} .[4] (I.e., all elements inX{\displaystyle X}  are grouped into non-empty sets, that are here equivalence classes ofX{\displaystyle X} .)

Conversely, for a setX{\displaystyle X} , every partition comes from an equivalence relation in this way, and different relations give different partitions. Thusxy{\displaystyle x\sim y}  if and only ifx{\displaystyle x}  andy{\displaystyle y}  belong to the same set of the partition.[5]

It follows from the properties in the previous section that if{\displaystyle \,\sim \,}  is an equivalence relation on a setX,{\displaystyle X,}  andx{\displaystyle x}  andy{\displaystyle y}  are two elements ofX,{\displaystyle X,}  the following statements are equivalent:

Proof

edit

Examples

edit

Graphical representation

edit
Main article:Cluster graph
 
Graph of an example equivalence with 7 classes

Anundirected graph may be associated to anysymmetric relation on a setX,{\displaystyle X,}  where the vertices are the elements ofX,{\displaystyle X,}  and two verticess{\displaystyle s}  andt{\displaystyle t}  are joined if and only ifst.{\displaystyle s\sim t.}  Among these graphs are the graphs of equivalence relations. These graphs, calledcluster graphs, are characterized as the graphs such that theconnected components arecliques.[2]

Invariants

edit

If{\displaystyle \,\sim \,}  is an equivalence relation onX,{\displaystyle X,}  andP(x){\displaystyle P(x)}  is a property of elements ofX{\displaystyle X}  such that wheneverxy,{\displaystyle x\sim y,} P(x){\displaystyle P(x)}  is true ifP(y){\displaystyle P(y)}  is true, then the propertyP{\displaystyle P}  is said to be aninvariant of,{\displaystyle \,\sim \,,}  orwell-defined under the relation.{\displaystyle \,\sim .} 

A frequent particular case occurs whenf{\displaystyle f}  is a function fromX{\displaystyle X}  to another setY{\displaystyle Y} ; iff(x1)=f(x2){\displaystyle f\left(x_{1}\right)=f\left(x_{2}\right)}  wheneverx1x2,{\displaystyle x_{1}\sim x_{2},}  thenf{\displaystyle f}  is said to beclass invariant under,{\displaystyle \,\sim \,,}  or simplyinvariant under.{\displaystyle \,\sim .}  This occurs, for example, in thecharacter theory of finite groups. Some authors use "compatible with{\displaystyle \,\sim \,} " or just "respects{\displaystyle \,\sim \,} " instead of "invariant under{\displaystyle \,\sim \,} ".

Anyfunctionf:XY{\displaystyle f:X\to Y}  isclass invariant under,{\displaystyle \,\sim \,,}  according to whichx1x2{\displaystyle x_{1}\sim x_{2}}  if and only iff(x1)=f(x2).{\displaystyle f\left(x_{1}\right)=f\left(x_{2}\right).}  The equivalence class ofx{\displaystyle x}  is the set of all elements inX{\displaystyle X}  which get mapped tof(x),{\displaystyle f(x),}  that is, the class[x]{\displaystyle [x]}  is theinverse image off(x).{\displaystyle f(x).}  This equivalence relation is known as thekernel off.{\displaystyle f.} 

More generally, a function may map equivalent arguments (under an equivalence relationX{\displaystyle \sim _{X}}  onX{\displaystyle X} ) to equivalent values (under an equivalence relationY{\displaystyle \sim _{Y}}  onY{\displaystyle Y} ). Such a function is amorphism of sets equipped with an equivalence relation.

Quotient space in topology

edit

Intopology, aquotient space is atopological space formed on the set of equivalence classes of an equivalence relation on a topological space, using the original space's topology to create the topology on the set of equivalence classes.

Inabstract algebra,congruence relations on the underlying set of an algebra allow the algebra to induce an algebra on the equivalence classes of the relation, called aquotient algebra. Inlinear algebra, aquotient space is a vector space formed by taking aquotient group, where the quotient homomorphism is alinear map. By extension, in abstract algebra, the term quotient space may be used forquotient modules,quotient rings,quotient groups, or any quotient algebra. However, the use of the term for the more general cases can as often be by analogy with the orbits of a group action.

The orbits of agroup action on a set may be called the quotient space of the action on the set, particularly when the orbits of the group action are the rightcosets of a subgroup of a group, which arise from the action of the subgroup on the group by left translations, or respectively the left cosets as orbits under right translation.

A normal subgroup of a topological group, acting on the group by translation action, is a quotient space in the senses of topology, abstract algebra, and group actions simultaneously.

Although the term can be used for any equivalence relation's set of equivalence classes, possibly with further structure, the intent of using the term is generally to compare that type of equivalence relation on a setX,{\displaystyle X,}  either to an equivalence relation that induces some structure on the set of equivalence classes from a structure of the same kind onX,{\displaystyle X,}  or to the orbits of a group action. Both the sense of a structure preserved by an equivalence relation, and the study ofinvariants under group actions, lead to the definition ofinvariants of equivalence relations given above.

See also

edit

Notes

edit
  1. ^Devlin 2004, p. 122.
  2. ^abcDevlin 2004, p. 123.
  3. ^Wolf 1998, p. 178
  4. ^Maddox 2002, p. 74, Thm. 2.5.15
  5. ^Avelsgaard 1989, p. 132, Thm. 3.16
  6. ^Avelsgaard 1989, p. 127
  7. ^Maddox 2002, pp. 77–78

References

edit
  • Avelsgaard, Carol (1989),Foundations for Advanced Mathematics, Scott Foresman,ISBN 0-673-38152-8
  • Devlin, Keith (2004),Sets, Functions, and Logic: An Introduction to Abstract Mathematics (3rd ed.), Chapman & Hall/ CRC Press,ISBN 978-1-58488-449-1
  • Maddox, Randall B. (2002),Mathematical Thinking and Writing, Harcourt/ Academic Press,ISBN 0-12-464976-9
  • Stein, Elias M.; Shakarchi, Rami (2012).Functional Analysis: Introduction to Further Topics in Analysis. Princeton University Press.doi:10.1515/9781400840557.ISBN 978-1-4008-4055-7.
  • Wolf, Robert S. (1998),Proof, Logic and Conjecture: A Mathematician's Toolbox, Freeman,ISBN 978-0-7167-3050-7

Further reading

edit
  • Sundstrom (2003),Mathematical Reasoning: Writing and Proof, Prentice-Hall
  • Smith; Eggen; St.Andre (2006),A Transition to Advanced Mathematics (6th ed.), Thomson (Brooks/Cole)
  • Schumacher, Carol (1996),Chapter Zero: Fundamental Notions of Abstract Mathematics, Addison-Wesley,ISBN 0-201-82653-4
  • O'Leary (2003),The Structure of Proof: With Logic and Set Theory, Prentice-Hall
  • Lay (2001),Analysis with an introduction to proof, Prentice Hall
  • Morash, Ronald P. (1987),Bridge to Abstract Mathematics, Random House,ISBN 0-394-35429-X
  • Gilbert; Vanstone (2005),An Introduction to Mathematical Thinking, Pearson Prentice-Hall
  • Fletcher; Patty,Foundations of Higher Mathematics, PWS-Kent
  • Iglewicz; Stoyle,An Introduction to Mathematical Reasoning, MacMillan
  • D'Angelo; West (2000),Mathematical Thinking: Problem Solving and Proofs, Prentice Hall
  • Cupillari,The Nuts and Bolts of Proofs, Wadsworth
  • Bond,Introduction to Abstract Mathematics, Brooks/Cole
  • Barnier; Feldman (2000),Introduction to Advanced Mathematics, Prentice Hall
  • Ash,A Primer of Abstract Mathematics, MAA

External links

edit

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp